- 24,488
- 15,057
I'm agnostic about this question. As long as there's no clear evidence against standard QT, there seems not to be a chance to find a more comprehensive theory.
Strange. I have never heard about a minimal version without collapse.vanhees71 said:I've never heard or read a convincing argument for the necessity of a collpase. The naive collapse is unphysical, and it doesn't help to call it epistemic. I have minimally interpreted quantum theory without a collapse, and that's all what's needed by experimentalists and theorists alike to describe quantitative observations with a high accuracy. So again: What do I need a collapse for?
But you do admit that probably there is something which is not the wave function (otherwise you would need either the collapse or many-worlds), even if you don't care what exactly that something might be. Am I right?vanhees71 said:I'm agnostic about this question. As long as there's no clear evidence against standard QT, there seems not to be a chance to find a more comprehensive theory.
I think "smart" is not the problem. Most are not ready to accept the hypothesis that relativistic symmetry is not fundamental, not even as a working hypothesis, which one accepts for the sake of the argument, to have a look at how it fails, no, it is rejected out of hand, without any discussion. Like here, where even to discuss the Lorentz ether interpretation vs. Minkowski interpretation is forbidden (BTW with a completely wrong argument that there is no difference in the predictions, in a situation where one can derive Bell's inequalities only in the Minkowski interpretation, but not in the Lorentz interpretation, which allows hidden causal influences, SCNR).stevendaryl said:It seems to me that if there is a solution to the interpretation problem for QM, we already have enough information to solve it--we're just not smart enough, maybe.
Where do you see the preferred basis problem in the de Broglie-Bohm interpretation?Demystifier said:With such a more common terminology, their theorems say that the physical content of QM is not basis independent. But this claim is not new at all. This is nothing but a restatement of the preferred basis problem appearing in one way or another in all interpretations of QM.
Ilja said:Strange. I have never heard about a minimal version without collapse.
As you know, the position basis has a preferred role in dBB, which some people consider to be a problem. You will probably agree with me that this is not a problem for non-relativistic QM, but a generalization of dBB to relativistic quantum field theory is much more problematic. Does the preferred basis fixes a preferred Lorentz frame? If yes, which one? Should the preferred basis be associated with particles or fields? If it is fields, then what about fermions? If it is particles, then what about Unruh effect and curved spacetime? These are all non-trivial questions and neither of the proposed answers (including yours and mine) is without problems.Ilja said:Where do you see the preferred basis problem in the de Broglie-Bohm interpretation?
Within quantum theory there's nothing else than the mathematical setup to define it, including the Born rule. If you want a deterministic theory with hidden variables, then there's more and according to the violation of Bell's inequality it'll be a non-local model.Demystifier said:But you do admit that probably there is something which is not the wave function (otherwise you would need either the collapse or many-worlds), even if you don't care what exactly that something might be. Am I right?
Ilja said:I think "smart" is not the problem. Most are not ready to accept the hypothesis that relativistic symmetry is not fundamental, not even as a working hypothesis, which one accepts for the sake of the argument, to have a look at how it fails, no, it is rejected out of hand, without any discussion. Like here, where even to discuss the Lorentz ether interpretation vs. Minkowski interpretation is forbidden (BTW with a completely wrong argument that there is no difference in the predictions, in a situation where one can derive Bell's inequalities only in the Minkowski interpretation, but not in the Lorentz interpretation, which allows hidden causal influences, SCNR).
You didn't answer my question, probably because you missed my point entirely. So let me try to explain my point (and my question) again.vanhees71 said:Within quantum theory there's nothing else than the mathematical setup to define it, including the Born rule. If you want a deterministic theory with hidden variables, then there's more and according to the violation of Bell's inequality it'll be a non-local model.
At the moment, however, I don't see the necessity for such a deterministic theory, because quantum theory never has been disproven by any experiment. In my opinion there are more urgent true problems to solve like: What's dark matter? How can we understand the smallness of "dark energy"? What's a consistent quantum theory of gravity? I don't see any urgent demand for a solution of the pseudo-problem of interpretation of quantum theory.
Well, you cannot discard a link between those problems and QM incompleteness-interpretations.vanhees71 said:At the moment, however, I don't see the necessity for such a deterministic theory, because quantum theory never has been disproven by any experiment. In my opinion there are more urgent true problems to solve like: What's dark matter? How can we understand the smallness of "dark energy"? What's a consistent quantum theory of gravity? I don't see any urgent demand for a solution of the pseudo-problem of interpretation of quantum theory.
I don't think that follows. One has to distinguish nature and its mathematical description. Ontology is concerned with nature itself. It tries to answer questions like: "What is the real nature of the things that we - as humans - perceive? What is beyond perception?" On the other hand, we have a mathematical description of nature, which includes mathematical objects like wave functions, fields or trajectories. None of these things exist in the way ontology talks about existence. A ball for example might exist in one way or the other or it might not, but it is not a trajectory, because a trajectory is just a certain string of symbols written on a piece of paper (for example the string ##x(t)=-\frac{1}{2}gt^2## is a trajectory). Obviously, a ball that you can see in front of you is never the string of symbols ##x(t)=-\frac{1}{2}gt^2## and neither is it any other string of symbols, so a ball is definitely not a trajectory. Neither is it a wave function. I still don't know what the ball "is", but I definitely know that it is not identical with its mathematical description. Even in classical mechanics, we strictly can't know what the right ontology is to interpret it. The difference between CM and QM is just that there are no interpretational difficulties with the standard ontology of CM (which postulates the existence of tiny little balls or something like that), so nobody worries about it. But still, if we prefer to accept only analytical arguments, having a classical (mathematical) description of physics doesn't tell us anything about ontology. So having a list of individual observations doesn't tell us anything about the (ontological) existence of "something". For example, I can easily build a measurement apparatus that measures something that most definitely doesn't correspond to something that onologically exists: Take a piece of paper and write "5" on it. Whenever you look at it, it reveals the number 5. It even has a classical and a quantum observable corresponding to it (a constant function ##f(x,p)=5## or the identity operator multiplied by 5). So I don't think it is possible to analytically conclude the ontological existence of "something" (whatever it is) from having a recorded list of measurement results.Demystifier said:I talked about ontology.
The point is the following. According to the statistical ensemble interpretation, which you said you accept, the wave function does not describe an individual observation, but only a statistical ensemble. Do you agree?
On the other hand, individual observations do exist. Do you agree with that too?
Now, if you agree with both claims above, then logically you must accept that something (individual observation) exists which is not a wave function. Q.E.D.
Are you saying that, even if nothing exists in the ontological sense, it is still logically possible to have measurement results?rubi said:So I don't think it is possible to analytically conclude the ontological existence of "something" (whatever it is) from having a recorded list of measurement results.
rubi said:None of these things exist in the way ontology talks about existence.
rubi said:A ball for example might exist in one way or the other or it might not, but it is not a trajectory, because a trajectory is just a certain string of symbols written on a piece of paper
I'm not adressing that situation, because obviously, something exists ("I think, therefore I am"). I'm basically arguing that the word "existence" can refer to different things and we should not mix them. On the one hand, we have the mathematical meaning of existence, which can be rigorously defined in mathematical logic and it is mainly a syntactic notion that has no inherent meaning. On the other hand, there is the ontlogical meaning of the word "existence", which talks about a loosely defined philosophical idea. My claim is that either notion of "existence" doesn' tell us anything about the other notion, respectively. So there are two things that we can't conclude analytically:Demystifier said:Are you saying that, even if nothing exists in the ontological sense, it is still logically possible to have measurement results?
rubi said:From having a mathematical descrption of nature using (syntactically) existing mathematical objects, we can't conclude anything about ontological existence.
You are making good points!rubi said:I'm not adressing that situation, because obviously, something exists ("I think, therefore I am"). I'm basically arguing that the word "existence" can refer to different things and we should not mix them. On the one hand, we have the mathematical meaning of existence, which can be rigorously defined in mathematical logic and it is mainly a syntactic notion that has no inherent meaning. On the other hand, there is the ontlogical meaning of the word "existence", which talks about a loosely defined philosophical idea. My claim is that either notion of "existence" doesn' tell us anything about the other notion, respectively. So there are two things that we can't conclude analytically:
1. From having a list of measurement results that exists in an ontological way (I can see it), we can't conclude anything about the (syntactic) existence of mathematical objects that describe them.
2. From having a mathematical descrption of nature using (syntactically) existing mathematical objects, we can't conclude anything about ontological existence.
I think if it comes to "ontology" it means that you need determinism, but that's perhaps another topic.Demystifier said:You didn't answer my question, probably because you missed my point entirely. So let me try to explain my point (and my question) again.
First, I didn't talk about determinism, so why do you talk about it? I talked about ontology.
Yes, that's the very point of quantum theory with Born's rule, and Born's rule is crucial. As is marvelously demonstrated in Weinbergs textbook, Lectures on Quantum Mechanics, it's a postulate independent of the others.The point is the following. According to the statistical ensemble interpretation, which you said you accept, the wave function does not describe an individual observation, but only a statistical ensemble. Do you agree?
Sure, otherwise I couldn't measure any individual system, which one definitely can (nowadays even single elementary particles or photons).On the other hand, individual observations do exist. Do you agree with that too?
First of all: QT is incomplete if you insist on wave functions. You can live with wave function alone only in (part) of non-relativistic QT. I don't know, why individual observations should be beyond quantum theory. The only constraint by QT compared to classical theory (CT) is that about individual observations you can in general make only probabilistic statements, even if you have complete knowledge about the system (i.e., if you know in which pure state it has been prepared).Now, if you agree with both claims above, then logically you must accept that something (individual observation) exists which is not a wave function. Q.E.D.
I think, that's answered now, right?So to condense all these questions into one: Do you agree that statistical ensemble interpretation of QM requires that something which is not a wave function must exist?
I don't think that any physical theory is complete. It's great. So there's still enough left to be discovered for us and hopefully many future generations of scientists :-).TrickyDicky said:Well, you cannot discard a link between those problems and QM incompleteness-interpretations.
Not at all, but maybe the right answer lies in post #117.vanhees71 said:I think, that's answered now, right?
Demystifier said:Do you agree that statistical ensemble interpretation of QM requires that something which is not a wave function must exist?
bhobba said:Its pretty well known eg
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wave_function_collapse
On the other hand, the collapse is considered a redundant or optional approximation in:
the Consistent histories approach, self-dubbed "Copenhagen done right"
the Bohm interpretation
the Many-worlds interpretation
the Ensemble Interpretation
In the ensemble interpretation state and preparation procedure are the same thing. If you have a filtering type observation all you have done is prepared the system differently. I suppose to some extent if that's the same as collapse or not depends on what you mean by collapse. I side with it isn't because it's consistent with the Bohmian interpretation and it doesn't have collapse. Indeed in Ballentine's original paper some say its really BM in disguise. I don't think it is, but he did express it a bit poorly in that paper - and it has been corrected in his textbook.
Thanks
Bill
That, of course, is obvious to me, but apparently not to vanhees.bhobba said:Of course it does - the ensemble is a conceptualisation of the outcomes of an observation.
What's the difference between that and viewing the length of a queue in a statistical modelling problem as an ensemble of possible lengths? What its the length of is not germane to the model.
Of course, I meant that it's clarified what I think. I don't expect that we can find a conclusion about these issues.Demystifier said:Not at all, but maybe the right answer lies in post #117.
If that means that you think that wave function exists syntactically while observations exist ontologically, and that we can't be certain how to relate these two types of existence, than it's clear.vanhees71 said:Of course, I meant that it's clarified what I think.
Philosophers rarely agree on anything, so I doubt that all philosophers agree on this. :D However, I'm not enough of a philosopher to answer that question.bhobba said:Would all philosophers agree with you on that? For example would Penrose agree with that - he believes the mathematics is the only reality - what we experience is just a platonic shadow of that reality.
Well, I'm making a difference between the path of the ball that you can see with your eyes and the mathematical object that we use for its description. Unfortunately, we refer to both things using the word "path".So the path traced out by a ball is just a string of symbols on a bit of paper. Actually it can be modeled by all sorts of things.
I'm not an expert in the philosophy of physics, so I don't know to what extent this fight is caused by this unawareness, but at least in the discussions I'm having, this unawareness plays a big role (in my opinion).Demystifier said:You are making good points!
So, would you say that the fight between "physicists" and "philosophers" on the meaning of quantum theory is to a large extent caused by the fact that they are not aware that they talk about two different types of "existence"?
Demystifier said:That, of course, is obvious to me, but apparently not to vanhees.
In my opinion too. Thanks for pointing this out!rubi said:I'm not an expert in the philosophy of physics, so I don't know to what extent this fight is caused by this unawareness, but at least in the discussions I'm having, this unawareness plays a big role (in my opinion).
rubi said:Philosophers rarely agree on anything, so I doubt that all philosophers agree on this. :D However, I'm not enough of a philosopher to answer that question.
I don't see a preferred role for "positions", but for the configuration. But it is, of course, not a problem, but an axiom. And to prefer configuration over momentum is also done in the classical Lagrange approach, which looks much more natural compared with the Hamilton formalism.Demystifier said:As you know, the position basis has a preferred role in dBB, which some people consider to be a problem. You will probably agree with me that this is not a problem for non-relativistic QM, but a generalization of dBB to relativistic quantum field theory is much more problematic. Does the preferred basis fixes a preferred Lorentz frame? If yes, which one? Should the preferred basis be associated with particles or fields? If it is fields, then what about fermions? If it is particles, then what about Unruh effect and curved spacetime? These are all non-trivial questions and neither of the proposed answers (including yours and mine) is without problems.
But is there any experimental support for giving up realism (in the form used by Bell in his theorem)? Or causality (in a form including Reichenbach's principle of common cause, which would also be sufficient to prove Bell's inequality)? In above cases, quantum effects by themself are no such evidence, because dBB gives a version which is compatible with realism and causality.stevendaryl said:You're right, that giving up relativity (as the Bohm-DeBroglie interpretation does) is a way out, but it isn't a satisfying way out because there is no experimental justification for such a leap. There is absolutely no experimental support for the existence of a preferred frame.
Ilja said:But is there any experimental support for giving up realism (in the form used by Bell in his theorem)? Or causality (in a form including Reichenbach's principle of common cause, which would also be sufficient to prove Bell's inequality)?
Once we have - with the violation of Bell's inequality - a conflict between fundamental relativity, on the one hand, and realism and causality, on the other hand, we have to decide what we have to throw away. And the situation where it is almost forbidden to argue that realism and causality should be preserved, and fundamental relativity thrown away, is not very satisfactory.
Last but no least, relativistic symmetry appears automatically if we have only a single universal wave equation for all observable fields. Therefore, it can be easily obtained as an effective symmetry without fundamental character.
The violation of Bell's inequality requires a preferred frame for realistic causal theories. It requires an explanation (Reichenbach's principle), and this explanation can be A \to B or B \to A because the common cause itself is unable to violate Bell's inequalities. So, if you want a causality without causal loops, you have to decide which of the two possibilities is correct. And the correct choice is hidden. Such is life.stevendaryl said:I don't know if that would work to remove the frame dependence of Bohm-DeBroglie, or not.
No problem, see the derivation of the EEP in http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0205035 Alternatively, think about a theory where we have, for reasons of simplicity, only one wave equation for all fields, which is essentially what we have. Then, everything you have, all what you can use to measure something, can influence any other events only through this same wave equation. This also gives you immediately local Lorentz invariance. I would guess you can derive this yourself. But this unique wave equation for all fields may be, of course, an approximation, which fails on the atomic scale of such an ether, and possibly also for extremely large energies of the waves.stevendaryl said:Well if the appearance of Lorentz invariance can be derived from some more fundamental assumption in a natural way, then I can more easily accept giving it up as an approximate symmetry.
But if there are two possible choices, and Bohmian theory requires to pick only one, don't you see that as a problem? The whole idea of Bohmian mechanics is not only to agree with observations (for that purpose the standard QM is also fine), but also to offer a reasonable ontological picture of the world. On the other hand, the two different choices propose two different ontological pictures of the world, which is a problem because then the existence of competitive pictures implies that neither of the pictures is sufficiently reasonable by itself.Ilja said:If there are two different possible choices, above in agreement with observation, fine, the theory is not falsified.
I think that pure quantum states are represented by rays in Hilbert space and that their physical meaning is given by Born's rule. What ontologically "exists" and what thus defines states physically is an equivalence class of "preparation procedures" that put the described system into this state.Demystifier said:If that means that you think that wave function exists syntactically while observations exist ontologically, and that we can't be certain how to relate these two types of existence, than it's clear.
As I said, the "preferred basis problem" takes different forms in different interpretations. But I don't think they have nothing to do with each other. In particular, a choice of configuration can also be viewed as a choice of basis, as a generalization of the fact that the the usual choice of configuration x can be viewed as a choice of the basis |x>.Ilja said:So, I would say that certainly the choice of the configuration space of a theory is a problem. ... But it has nothing to do with the conceptual "preferred basis problem" of other interpretations.
It's important to clarify the meaning of certain terms we use, and I don't think that this kind of existence would be called "ontological" by philosophers of physics. In this context, by ontological existence one would mean individual preparations, not the equivalence class of similar preparations.vanhees71 said:What ontologically "exists" and what thus defines states physically is an equivalence class of "preparation procedures" that put the described system into this state.
It's too easy to construct ugly theories which disagree with QM at some experimentally testable level. For example, one such extremely ugly "theory" is that QM is always right except when experiments are performed on the dark side of the Moon, and future experiments can decide if that theory is true.atyy said:Hmm, why not say that the purpose of BM is to disagree with QM at some level? Then it doesn't matter how ugly it is, since experiment will pick. And then we can say to all non-believers in reality, "nature doesn't care what we like" :)
That's a healthy attitude. But isn't it essentially the same as saying:vanhees71 said:I don't see a problem in this since I don't think that our contemporary physical models are complete in any sense. :)
Different ontological pictures are, IMHO, not a problem at all. First, it is also important that we know what we don't know. So, if there are two different ontological pictures, it means, we don't know which is the true one. Such is life. We cannot know everything.Demystifier said:But if there are two possible choices, and Bohmian theory requires to pick only one, don't you see that as a problem? The whole idea of Bohmian mechanics is not only to agree with observations (for that purpose the standard QM is also fine), but also to offer a reasonable ontological picture of the world. On the other hand, the two different choices propose two different ontological pictures of the world, which is a problem because then the existence of competitive pictures implies that neither of the pictures is sufficiently reasonable by itself.
The point of considering interpretations is, essentially, that they ultimately tend to disagree. The point is that they usually have problems. And how are these problems solved? By a modification of the theory, of course. And after this, the "interpretation" is no longer an interpretation but a different theory.atyy said:Hmm, why not say that the purpose of BM is to disagree with QM at some level? Then it doesn't matter how ugly it is, since experiment will pick.
If quantum theory does not, in fact, predict the result of individual measurements, but only their statistical mean, then why should oneDemystifier said:It's important to clarify the meaning of certain terms we use, and I don't think that this kind of existence would be called "ontological" by philosophers of physics. In this context, by ontological existence one would mean individual preparations, not the equivalence class of similar preparations.
On the other hand, QM in its statistical ensemble form says nothing about individual preparations. In this sense QM in the statistical ensemble form is not complete, because individual preparations obviously exist (ontologically), and yet the theory says (syntactically) nothing about them.
This proves that QM in the statistical ensemble form is not ontologically complete. A possible way to stop worry about that is to assume that QM in the statistical ensemble form is at least syntactically complete, i.e. that syntax (formal mathematical theory) correctly describing individual preparations - does not exist. But such an assumption is not very well grounded, especially with a known counter-example candidates such as Bohmian mechanics, many-worlds, and objective-collapse theories.
TrickyDicky said:If quantum theory does not, in fact, predict the result of individual measurements, but only their statistical mean, then why should one expect a syntax describing individual preparations?
My question was in reference to Demistifier comment about syntacticalatyy said:In the ensemble interpretation, there is a classical/quantum cut. One may like to call it something else, but as most proponents of the ensemble interpretation agree, there is no meaning to the "wave function of the universe" in that interpretation. If there is no "wave function of the universe", one has to say which part of the universe the wave function applies to, which is the classical/quantum cut in all but name.
So the measurement problem can be phrased in different forms, such as the question about individual systems, or removing the classical quantum cut.
Would that, then, not make the ensemble interpretation just a "shut up and calculate" interpretation in disguise?TrickyDicky said:If quantum theory does not, in fact, predict the result of individual measurements, but only their statistical mean, then why should one expect a syntax describing individual preparations?
TrickyDicky said:My question was in reference to Demistifier comment about syntactical
completeness, I don't inmediately see
how your post answers it but I will
address what you write anyway.
The reasoning about the wave function of the uiverse you use would be valid if like MW the ensemble int. considered the wave function as ontologicaly real, but it doesn't.
I think ensemble is the "shut up and calculate" genuine interpretation but done in an honest and elegant way ;-)bohm2 said:Would that, then, not make the ensemble interpretation just a "shut up and calculate" interpretation in disguise?
Yes, that's right.atyy said:Copenhagen does not consider the wave function real on the same level as measurement outcomes. That is the point of the classical/quantum cut.
This doesn't follow. First the ensemble interpretation not only does not have an ontology for the wave function, it doesn't have an ontology for classical reality as it is the case in the Copenhagen interpretation.Any minimal interpretation which does not consider the wave function of the universe to
be meaningful has a classical/quantum cut.