Understanding Topology: Exploring T2-Spaces, Separability, and More

  • Thread starter JasonRox
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Topology
In summary: The Space of Reals is separable. Since the rational numbers are countable and it is a subset of R, and R is the only closed set that contains Q then Q- = R. Hence, it is separable.5 - The Finite Complement Topology is separable. If X is countable, then we are done. If X is not countable, then we can create a countable subset (call it A) within X such that X is the only closed set that contains A. Therefore, A~N (cardinality) because if this were not true, then A is finite, which is closed and A- <> X, so it is not dense. (
  • #1
JasonRox
Homework Helper
Gold Member
2,386
4
I have a few questions to ask. They are simple, but the purpose is to make sure I'm staying on track.

First, the definitions that I will use.

T2-Space or Hausdorff Space, find http://http://mathworld.wolfram.com/T2-Space.html" here.

Separable Space, find http://mathworld.wolfram.com/SeparableSpace.html" here.

Let X be the underlying set.

The questions or statements are...

1 - The Space of Reals is a T2-Space. This seems rather obvious since you can just construct the intervals for x and y (x<>y) such that they do not overlap. Hence, two neighbourhoods that are disjoint.

2 - The Discrete Topology is separable if and only if X itself is countable.

Note: A- is the intersection of the collection of closed subsets in X that contain A. Therefore, if A is closed, A- = A.

Note: A is dense in X if and only if A- = X.

Note: <> means not equal to.

Now, using the notes above.

X can be the only possible solution in this case because every subset is closed, therefore A- <> X, unless A=X. Therefore, if X is countable, it is separable.

Is that right?

3 - The Indiscrete Topology is separable if and only if there is countable subset in X. If X is the set of real numbers, then it is separable because the naturals numbers is a countable subset in R, and it is dense because N- = X, because X is the only set that contains N.

4 - The Space of Reals is separable. Since the rational numbers are countable and it is a subset of R, and R is the only closed set that contains Q then Q- = R. Hence, it is separable.

5 - The Finite Complement Topology is separable. If X is countable, then we are done. If X is not countable, then we can create a countable subset (call it A) within X such that X is the only closed set that contains A.

Therefore, A~N (cardinality) because if this were not true, then A is finite, which is closed and A- <> X, so it is not dense. (A can not have higher cardinality of N because then it wouldn't be countable like we constructed.)

Is my thinking right?

EDIT: I am going to re-read my post later. I might have some mistakes that I don't know yet.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I can't tell if you are strictly disinguishing between finite and countable, in some cases you are and in some not.

4: in what topology.

It's correct if not written in the shortest way. Eg in cofinite topology, since only finite sets are closed, either X, if X is finite, or any countably infinite set is dense hence X is separable.

Personally I prefer =/= to be not equal rather than<> since that only really is computer speak for 'strictly greater than or strictly less than'
 
  • #3
What I mean about the Space of Reals, is the topology of intervals, which if you remember from my last question of topology.

matt grime said:
I can't tell if you are strictly disinguishing between finite and countable, in some cases you are and in some not.

What do you mean?
 
Last edited:
  • #4
JasonRox said:
I have a few questions to ask. They are simple, but the purpose is to make sure I'm staying on track.
First, the definitions that I will use.
T2-Space or Hausdorff Space, find http://http://mathworld.wolfram.com/T2-Space.html" here.
Separable Space, find http://mathworld.wolfram.com/SeparableSpace.html" here.
Let X be the underlying set.
The questions or statements are...
1 - The Space of Reals is a T2-Space. This seems rather obvious since you can just construct the intervals for x and y (x<>y) such that they do not overlap. Hence, two neighbourhoods that are disjoint.
More specifically, intervals centered on x and y with radius |x-y|/2 will work.

2 - The Discrete Topology is separable if and only if X itself is countable.
Note: A- is the intersection of the collection of closed subsets in X that contain A. Therefore, if A is closed, A- = A.
Note: A is dense in X if and only if A- = X.
Note: <> means not equal to.
Now, using the notes above.
X can be the only possible solution in this case because every subset is closed, therefore A- <> X, unless A=X. Therefore, if X is countable, it is separable.
Is that right?
Actually, it proves the otherway: X is separable only if it is countable.
"If X is countable, then it is separable" is true for any topology.
3 - The Indiscrete Topology is separable if and only if there is countable subset in X. If X is the set of real numbers, then it is separable because the naturals numbers is a countable subset in R, and it is dense because N- = X, because X is the only set that contains N.
?? Are you specifically talking about the real numbers with the indiscrete topology? If so then you should say that. Yes, the set of real numbers contains a countable subset and so is separable with the indiscrete topology. "because X is the only set that contains N" is not correct. I presume you meant "because X is the only set in the topology that contains N" or "because X is the only open set that contains N".
4 - The Space of Reals is separable. Since the rational numbers are countable and it is a subset of R, and R is the only closed set that contains Q then Q- = R. Hence, it is separable.
Yes, that's completely true.
5 - The Finite Complement Topology is separable. If X is countable, then we are done. If X is not countable, then we can create a countable subset (call it A) within X such that X is the only closed set that contains A.
Therefore, A~N (cardinality) because if this were not true, then A is finite, which is closed and A- <> X, so it is not dense. (A can not have higher cardinality of N because then it wouldn't be countable like we constructed.)
Is my thinking right?[/quote]
"Therefore, A~ N"?? Didn't you want to prove "separable"?
How do you get " If X is not countable, then we can create a countable subset (call it A) within X such that X is the only closed set that contains A." Aren't you assuming here that X is separable?

EDIT: I am going to re-read my post later. I might have some mistakes that I don't know yet.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #5
In my language countable means in bijection with some subset of the naturals, and hence includes finite stuff. Some people disallow finite sets from being countable. You carefully distinguish between countable and finite at some points. I mean in particular the odd point where you use the condition 'iff it has a countable subset' for indiscrete: all non-empty sets have a countable subset in my opinion. Since you distinguish this then apparently you disallow finite countable sets. Then later you say 'let A be countable' and 'prove' that A is inbijection with N, but surely that is your definition of countable, if you're going to condition on something have a countable subset.
 
  • #6
HallsofIvy said:
?? Are you specifically talking about the real numbers with the indiscrete topology? If so then you should say that. Yes, the set of real numbers contains a countable subset and so is separable with the indiscrete topology. "because X is the only set that contains N" is not correct. I presume you meant "because X is the only set in the topology that contains N" or "because X is the only open set that contains N".

Thanks, I see my error now. I was just using the real numbers as an example. So in the topology, X is the only closed set that contains N.

Just like matt grime pointed out before, but he deleted I guess. Every set has a countable subset, hence all Indiscrete Topology's are separable.

"Therefore, A~ N"?? Didn't you want to prove "separable"?
How do you get " If X is not countable, then we can create a countable subset (call it A) within X such that X is the only closed set that contains A." Aren't you assuming here that X is separable?

Let me explain a little bit better.

If X is countable, then it is separable because X is a countable subset, which is dence in X.

If X is not countable, then we can create a countable set (call it A) in X, such that X is the only closed set that contains A.

The reason why we must have A~N is because if it wasn't, then A would be finite because A is countable. Since A is finite, A is also closed, hence A is not dense in X.

This is why A must have A~N (cardinality). This assures us that no finite subset of X will contain A, which leaves us with only X as the closed set that contains A, which makes it dense in X. Since now A is a subset of X, it is countable, and is dense in X, we now have the definition of a separable topology.
 
Last edited:
  • #7
matt grime said:
In my language countable means in bijection with some subset of the naturals, and hence includes finite stuff. Some people disallow finite sets from being countable. You carefully distinguish between countable and finite at some points. I mean in particular the odd point where you use the condition 'iff it has a countable subset' for indiscrete: all non-empty sets have a countable subset in my opinion. Since you distinguish this then apparently you disallow finite countable sets. Then later you say 'let A be countable' and 'prove' that A is inbijection with N, but surely that is your definition of countable, if you're going to condition on something have a countable subset.

That's the definition I use as well.

I apologize for any difficulties in my writing. I'll do my best to improve on my future questions.
 
  • #8
if you want to understand topology, i recommend you get away from this type of investigation as soon as you can, and start learning about covering spaces, fundamental groups, homology, cohomology, tangent and cotangent bundles, and the properties of specific spaces, like lens spaces, projective spaces, compact 2 manifolds, spheres, tori, lie groups, symmetric products, algebraic varieties, etc.

it is easy to be fooled into thinking topology is about definitions, when really it is about properties of ordinary spaces that occur in practice.
 
  • #9
Spoken like a physicist!
 
  • #10
Well, how many times do really ever actually have to work out if you've just created a T3 space? I don't even know what a T3 space is, and I'm quite proud of that in a perverse way. In real life you only ever need the standard metric topology or some other topology of continuity of functions that you pick a posteri to make things work (eg topology of pointwise convergence, topology of uniform convergence), or the zariski topology, or the compact open topology. Very rarely do you pass outside these things. I would suggest you only need to know about 6 topologies to do maths. And you should learn the properties as needed.

As an example, over the last 6 months off and on I've been dabbling in algebraic geometry so that I can do some mirror symmetry stuff in the near future (interesting conferences in Seoul, San Francisco and Vienna this year for those thinking about working in this area) and finding it too dull for words because the textbooks were written in far too much generality. However by studying curves, ie dimension 2 stuff, alone I've now gotten round to understanding what Riemann Roch is really saying, I've gotten to like divisors since they are just points in dim 2 not bizarre codim 1 things. We only really look at curves anyway, and divisors there are very different from divisors in general.

Here the analogy is: who gives a monkey's about what separable is, in the abstract sense? All that's important is that the Hilbert Spaces we find occurring naturally need to have a countable dense subset to make their study nice, and lo and behold they do.
 
Last edited:
  • #11
well as a young person, after college and before grad school, i studied kelley's general topology and thought i was learning some topology. he had T1, T2, T3, T4 spaces in there, and I was a little worried i might not remember all the differences, or the right hypotheses for every theorem.
then later i was upset that in studying algebraic topology i did not know much about circles and spheres, and so on, much less lens spaces or projective space.
kelley did admit he meant his book to be titled "what every young analyst should know" and not what every young topologist or geometer should know, or maybe i would have skipped it.
since then i have almost never met a space that was not T2, i.e. in topology, hello, essentially all decent spaces are hausdorff. so maybe kelley was thinking of abstract harmonic analysts and people wanting to study "bornological spaces" and "barrelled spaces" and other far out weird stuff of infinite dimensions.
normal people (by my definition) study much more mundane spaces.
now i admit that in abstract algebra geometry the "unmentionable" topology, to quote zariski, i.e. the zariski topology is not hausdorff. so what, you just have to understand the correct definition of hausdorff to fix that right up. i.e. affine algebraic varieties ARE hausdorff, they are just not T2. I.e. T2 is not the right definition of hausdorff. what you really want from "hausdorffness" is that two morphisms should agree on a clsed subset, so if they agree on a dense set they agree everywhere, stuff .like that. disjoint neighborhoods is just a tool in a certain setting, to get the more important consequences. when the setting changes, you have to change the definition to get those same consequences.



i.e. a traditional topological space is hausdorff (T2) if and only if the diagonal is closed in the product topology.

hence for an algebraic variety, the right definition of hausdorff, called separated, is that the diagonal be closed, where of course the product is NOT given the product topology, but is given its natural structure in the category of algebraic varieties, i.e. such that algebraic morphisms (not just continuous ones) into the product correspond to pairs of morphisms into the factors.

now suppose you have two morphisms of X into Y. Then you get a morphism of X into YxY, and the pullback of the diagonal is the set where the two morphisms agree, and if the diagonal is closed then the pullback is clsed, so the two morphisms agree on a closed set.

isnt that cool?

then compactness is also defined differently, i.e. a hausdorff topological space X is compact if and only if the projection map XxY-->Y is a closed map for every (hausdorff?) space Y. [I do not want to do the exercise right now.]

anyway, then the right definition of compact, for algebraic varieties, called proper, is that X is proper if and only if X is separated and every projection map XxY-->Y to another (separated?) algebraic variety Y is a closed map.
so the correct way to look at everything is not by what it "is" but what it "does", i.e. the categorical way. via maps, not open sets.

if you do this, as grothendieck emphasized, [and also hausdorff, but not bertrand russell, when hausdorff described numbers by saying he did not care what they were but how they behaved], then everything works.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Halls, that is a great compliment, as physicists are intelligent people who are firmly grounded in reality.

Mathematicians also are on safer ground when they stick to the guidance found in observing natural examples.

As someone said about our mathematical forefathers of previous centuries, something like: they may have been somewhat unrigorous in their methods of proof, but their conclusions were supported by extensive experience and by computations with examples of such fundamental importance that they seldom went astray even when their proofs were lacunary.
 
  • #13
that's a good one, the product zariski, for jasonrox.

Consider R, the zariski topology is defined via: K is closed iff K is the zero set of a polynomial - K_f ={x: f(x)=0}

The zariski topology on R^2 is defined as follows: the zariski closed sets are generated by the K_f {(x,y):f(x,y)=0}

By example show that the zariski topology on R^2 is not the product topology from the zariski topology on two copies of R.

It's not hard but is an (the only?) interesting example of a case where the product topology is not what you think it might be.
 
  • #14
to the OP: I realize this may probably not be the answer that interests you now, but I am like my father, who had me when he was 53 years old: I know you are just starting out, but i don't have time to wait for you to ask the questions I want to answer, I am going to answer them now, and someday when they become the questions you want answered, maybe you will recall the answers.

best wishes,

old poop
 
  • #15
mathwonk said:
to the OP: I realize this may probably not be the answer that interests you now, but I am like my father, who had me when he was 53 years old: I know you are just starting out, but i don't have time to wait for you to ask the questions I want to answer, I am going to answer them now, and someday when they become the questions you want answered, maybe you will recall the answers.
best wishes,
old poop

I think the message is directed towards me.

I'm not sure whether or not this is the direction into topolopy. The author does say the text is aimed at students going in Real Analysis, and that it emphasizes applications to the space of reals (I mentionned earlier).

Topology seems like a very interesting area, but then again, where do I begin. When it comes to learning something new, I'm stuck guiding myself.

When I get home, like tomorrow, I will post the contents of the text.

Although the text might not lead me into topology, but I do think I will benefit from it regardless. The text is short, and only reads 150 pages. I hope to be done shortly, but rightfully.

I just ordered Young's book on Topology from Dover. From the reviews I've read, it sounds like a good text.

Anyways, topology does interest me. I'm most interested in studying infinite-dimensional vector spaces, which I'm still awaiting to do, and topology, but that's hard to say now that I don't really "know" what it is.

My interests to studying infinite-dimensional vector spaces comes from studying finite-dimensional spaces from linear algebra. I'll look into tensors as well when I get there.

Well, I guess that sums up my current interests.

I appreciate that you are all sharing your experiences, which is priceless.

Since, my professor is leading me into the study of infinite-dimensional vector spaces, so I believe he is heading me into the right direction. He has been very helpful on finding a list of books, and in things I should know.

May I ask where to begin for topology?

Maybe if I shared my goal, you can give me better advice.

My current goal is to just garnish enough knowledge to read through articles in math journals that may interest me.

The goal seems pretty straightforward to me, and it can be accomplished. It doesn't have to be a recent article either.

Anyways, that's about it.

Note to matt grime: I had interests in studying elliptic functions, but because the project that I was to follow with my prof, I decide to put it off for now. Since I know nothing about it, it would make no sense to say I'm interested in it. I know nothing about topology, but that's different... I think.

Thanks. :biggrin:
 
  • #16
The thing here is that in some sense you aren't studying what a topologist would call the important bits of topology. Topolgist refers to an algebraic topologist you see, not a pointset top ologist. So the intersting stuff is (co)homology and such ie what you do with the topological space and not separability and those things. It is more the analysts who want to put topologies on strange things so that they can 'do analysis' in odd places. Obviously a topologist does know what pointset topology is, it's just that they almost always study one of very variations on compact, connected, path-connected spaces.
 
  • #17
Well, I looked up some texts and some information online, for algebraic topology.

From what I read, most will atleast assume you know point-set topology and basic algebra, which seems alright if I just finish this text.

I have still yet to come home, and write the contents of the text that I am reading.
 
  • #18
fromm an algerbraic or differential topoilogists point of view the first theorem of interest is the intermediate value theorem, and the second one is that fact that the integral of the angle form around the circle is 2pi and not zero. this implies the fundamental theorem of algebra and if you understand why, then you are on your way.
the first book to read on differential topology is the little volume of milnor on topology from the differentiable viewpoint. no matter how few pages you read you have learned a lot, literally even 2 or 3 pages.
 
Last edited:
  • #19
4220, lecture 1,
First steps, some problems and approaches to them.

The goal of this course is to use calculus (i.e. the concepts of continuity and differentiability) to prove statements such as: a complex polynomial of positive degree always has roots, a smooth self mapping of the disc always has fixed points, or a smooth
vector field on a sphere always has zeroes, and higher dimensional generalizations of them.
These are called existence statements. They are called such because usually we do not produce the solutions whose existence is claimed, rather we deduce some contradiction from the assumption that no solution exists. Thus it is entirely another matter to obtain specific information about these solutions. I want you to give some thought in each case to the problem of actually finding, or at least approximating, these solutions.
On the other hand we will often prove results about the "number" of such solutions. We use quotation marks because again there is no guarantee the actual number of solutions will obey our prediction. We will define at times a "weighting" for each solution, and will prove that either there are infinitely many solutions, or if the number of solutions is finite, the sum of the weights equals our number.
Since a non solution has weight zero, it follows that if our predicted number is non zero, then there is at least one solution. Moreover if there is only one solution, then it must have weight equal to our predicted number. This is a big improvement, since in some cases we can actually find some of the solutions and their weights, and if their sum is deficient from our prediction, we then conclude there must be more solutions. This is a useful tool in plane algebraic geometry called the strong Bezout theorem.
To take advantage of this, poses the challenge of actually computing these weights. In each case we encounter, please give some thought to how to calculate the weights, or the actual number of solutions.

Let's recall one of the earliest cases of an existence theorem of this type, the so called "intermediate value theorem".

Theorem (IVT):
If f:[a,b]-->R is continuous, and f(a) < 0 while f(b) > 0, then there is a number c with a < c < b and f(c) = 0.

This proof is based on the completeness axiom for the real numbers: every non empty set of reals which is bounded above has a real least upper bound.

proof of theorem: Consider the set S = {x in [a,b] such that f(x)
 
Last edited:
  • #20
there seems to be some limit on how much i can post as one post and this has cut off most of my lecture. sorry.
 
  • #21
trying again:

such that f(x) ≤ 0}. S contains a, so S is non empty, and b is an upper bound for S, so S has a least upper bound L with a ≤ L ≤ b. If f(L) < 0 then L < b so f is also negative at some number between L and b, so L is not even an upper bound for S. If f(L) > 0, then L > a, so all members of S are less than L but there is an interval of numbers less than L where f is also positive, i.e. which are not elements of S. Hence every element of that interval is an upper bound of S, so L is not the least upper bound of S. This contradiction proves that f(L) is neither positive nor negative, hence must be zero. QED.

abstract version of this proof: If f is continuous on D, and D is connected, then f(D) is also connected. In R the only connected sets are intervals, thus f([a,b]) is an interval. QED.

Let's extend the argument a bit.
Corollary: If f is a polynomial of odd degree, with real coefficients, then f has a real root.
proof: Assume f is monic. Then the limit of f(x) is ∞ as x-->∞, and is -∞ as x --> -∞. Hence there exist a,b, with a < b and f(a) < 0 and f(b) > 0. QED.

Corollary: If f is a differentiable function with no critical points in [a,b] and with f(a) < 0 < f(b), then f has exactly one root in [a,b].
proof: Uniqueness follows from the MVT. QED.
 
  • #22
Cor: If f is a polynomial of even (odd) degree with real coefficients, and no root is a critical point, then f has a finite even (odd) number of roots.
proof: (even case) By the hypothesis that f'(x)i give up, i cannot post my notes.
 
  • #23
i try again:

Conjecture: suppose f:C-->C is continuous and that the restriction of f to the unit disc {z: |z| = 1} is the identity map. Then we claim f(z) = 0 has at least one solution for |z| < 1.
How would we prove this? Remember the philosophy is to deduce a catastrophe from the falsity of the result, so assume it is false. I.e. that f maps the whole unit disc into C-{0}. Then what could one do? By analogy with the final form above of the IVT, after composing f with a retraction onto the circle, via z --> z/|z|, one could deduce there is a continuous map of the disc to its boundary circle which restricts to the identity on the boundary. Is this possible? Why or why not?

Retraction problem: There is no continuous map D-->oink.
 
  • #24
lol looks like mathwonk isn't satisfied with his math-guru runner-up position... :tongue:
 
  • #25
matt grime said:
Topolgist refers to an algebraic topologist you see, not a pointset top ologist.
Who decided that?
 
  • #26
No one decided it, it just tends to reflect, in my experience, a common theme running through all of the people I've met who describe themselves as topologists. The study of topology at research level is pretty much synonymous with the study of algebraic topology.

http://www.sarah-whitehouse.staff.shef.ac.uk/btconfs.html

is for instance the first hit you get when googling for topology conference UK. Most on the list are algebraic topology, and those that aren't are still studying manifolds but looking at the invariants as analytic ones, which is practically the same thing. Anything that involves calculating homology, or cohomolgy through whatever means is algebraic topology in my book.

And as it says in my sig opinions are mine and no one elses.
 
Last edited:
  • #27
here is a suggestion of a topology book, taht covers metric spaces, =banach spaces and hilbert spaces, for beginners, i.e. from the ebginning, although not for the faint of heart. Foundations of modern analysis, by dieudonne.
 
  • #28
Time to write the contents of the book I'm reading.
1. Elementary Set Theory

(no need for details)

2. Topological Spaces

3. Mappings of Topological Spaces

4. Compactness

5. Product Spaces

6. Metric Spaces

7. More on Product Spaces and Function Spaces

  • Includes Tychonoff Theorem, Cubes and Spaces.

8. Nets and Convergence

9. Peano Spaces

Note: I didn't go into detail of what the chapters cover.
 
  • #29
that's roughly the first 75 pages of dieudonne's 355 page book, except there is a bit more abstract stuff in your book, such as nets and tychonoff theorem.
you, seem to be reading a very dry book on basic point set topology, and I agree with matt grime, point set topology is not a subject of great interest to research in topology today, nor for the last 50 years.
(grothendieck felt obliged to deliver that message to the vietnamese mathematicians during the vietnamese us war.):tongue:

not to say it is unimportant. let's compare point set to a course of grammar, basic but boring, wheareas algebraic topology is more like a course on dickens' novels.
 
Last edited:
  • #30
mathwonk said:
that's roughly the first 75 pages of dieudonne's 355 page book, except there is a bit more abstract stuff in your book, such as nets and tychonoff theorem.
you, seem to be reading a very dry book on basic point set topology, and I agree with matt grime, point set topology is not a subject of great interest to research in topology today, nor for the last 50 years.
(grothendieck felt obliged to deliver that message to the vietnamese mathematicians during the vietnamese us war.):tongue:
not to say it is unimportant. let's compare point set to a course of grammar, basic but boring, wheareas algebraic topology is more like a course on dickens' novels.

The text is only 150 pages at most, so it is relatively short.

Are you recommending jumping right into Algebraic Topology even though most texts expect you to know Point-Set Topology?

Sure, I'd love to jump right in, but I just don't think I have yet acquired the skills to do so, at this point in time.

Note: I never expected to get into research with Point-Set Topology.
 
  • #31
Yes, jump in. Grab Maunder's Dover reprint if you can ($11.95), or perhaps Massey though a lot of people don't get on with it.

As long as you know a tiny amount of pointset topology, enough to define a continuous as function as one pulling back open sets to open sets and say what compact is, you'll be fine, and even if not you can always look back at what you need to know. Do you want to guess how long the chapters on such analytic topology as you're studying are in maunder's book? it runs to less than 7 pages of treatment. do you know what connected is? hausdorff? compact? then you're good to go.

Why? Because any intro to algebraic topology will only really try to deal with manifolds and their properties; it turns into algebra problems about 'real life' topological spaces. Stuff like nets, ultrafilters and so on really won't come anywhere near it, nor will half the material in that book you've got. It should deal with some kinds of complexes, be they simplicial or CW, try and find out what Cech homology is.

i think others would be better placed to say, but most of the pointset topology in that book is more suited to doing analysis not algebra. so it would depend on what you wanted to do.
 
Last edited:
  • #32
How does this book look?

http://www.math.cornell.edu/~hatcher/AT/ATpage.html

I'm reading Abstract Algebra by Herstein as well as the Topology text.

I'm skeptical about jumping in right now though. It just feels that I shouldn't rush into things. If I finish the two texts I have above, which Topology should be done by April, and Abstract Algebra by let's say August. I feel that if I wait, I will acquire lots of skill and knowledge taking this route. I want to be somewhat rounded, so that if decisions change, I'm not far far off.

Anyways, I have more questions.

First, what kind of topics (readable for me) should I look for in my first Algebraic Topology text?

Second, what kind of neat things will these topics teach me? In a language I can understand if possible.

Third, what neat things are happening today in the area of Algebraic Topology? (I believe some things are now being, or may always have been, applied to number theory.)
 
  • #33
Well, I did a google search about Algebraic Topology.

I have a rough idea of the things I can do, and sounds interesting.

I guess the only question I need answered now is the first one.
 
  • #34
I did a little bit more reading, and yes I must say it is very interesting.

There is still no doubt in my mind that I would gain by waiting a little bit longer. Let's say until Chapter 6 - Metric Spaces.
 
  • #35
I suppose the first thing to look for is the definition of the fundamental group.

This is the most intuitive and easy to understand thing there is in topology. It measures the number of ways you can embed a closed loop (ie a path) starting and ending at some fixed point in your space up to the equivalence of being able to deform paths by continuous operations.

It measures, approximately, the number of holes in your space.

The fundamental group of the circle is the integers. You can wrap around the circle n times, and up to this equivalence that specifies all of the paths.

The fundamental group of two circles that are joined at one point (so called bouquet of two circles) is the free group on two elements. For n elements it is the free group on n elements. Each has n holes.

The fundamental group of the torus is the integers. It is the abelianization of the fundamental group of the bouquet of two circles for a very interesting reason.

It is intuitive, nice, and familiar since it is the analogue of the winding number in complex analysis. The link being if you integrate 1/z round a path that loops round the origin in C you are talking about loops round a path... if two paths were continuously deformable into each other (ie not going through 0) then they'd have the same winding number.
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
1
Views
505
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
2
Views
742
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
7
Views
3K
  • Calculus and Beyond Homework Help
Replies
12
Views
1K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
12
Views
4K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Replies
3
Views
850
Back
Top