atyy said:
But you like Consistent Histories, which means your dislike of BM is only a matter of tase - unlike vanhees71, which is a technical disagreement. If we apply vanhees71's view, Consistent Histories is also pointless.
I don't think it's just a matter of taste to reject Bohmian mechanics. I think the situation is comparable to the epicycle theory. People just couldn't imagine that the Earth might not be in the center of the universe, so they had to come up with contrieved explanations for the motion of the planets. Bohmian mechanics is very similar: People don't want to give up the naive idealization that particles can be modeled as points in ##\mathbb R^3##, so they have to invent absurd mechanisms in order to maintain this idealization. Rationally, there is just no good reason for why nature could be mapped to points in ##\mathbb R^3## (especially if you recognize that ##\mathbb R^3## is just a mathematical object, whose properties depend on the choice of the underlying set theory axioms). It's just an idealization, whose domain of applicability is exceeded in the quantum regime. Progress in science depends on recognizing wrong ideas and replacing them by something better. Adhering to wrong ideas has never led to scientific progress and indeed, I'm not aware of a single relevant discovery that has emerged from Bohmian mechanics. On the other hand, great advances (such as QFT and the standard model) were made by taking the quantum formalism seriously. If the only positive thing that can be said about a theory is that it is not technically excluded by observations, then it's pretty clear that it is a dead end.
From reading vanhees' posts, I think he is secretly a consistent histories advocate without knowing it yet.
vanhees71 said:
Can you summarize, what Consistent Histories claims beyond the minimal interpretation? Perhaps, I'm too pragmatic to realize, where the problem with the minimal interpretation is, but I just don't get, why it should help to introduce any elements of interpretation that go beyond Born's rule, which establishes the meaning of the formalism concerning observable (and observed!) facts about nature.
Consistent histories is essentially the minimal interpretation stated with more conceptual clarity. It keeps all the concepts from Copenhagen, but it interprets time evolution as a stochastic process, much like classical Brownian motion. The insertion projection operators between the time evolution doesn't correspond to any physical process. Instead, it just selects a subset of histories from the path space, whose probability of occurring is to be calculated. It's completely analogous to the insertion of characteristic functions in the case of Brownian motion. No explicit references to measurements remain and all quantum paradoxes are resolved.
In Brownian motion, the Wiener measure on the space of Brownian paths is constructed by specifying it on so called cylinder sets of paths ##x(t)##:
$$O^{t_1 t_2 \ldots}_{B_1 B_2 \ldots}=\{x : x(t_1)\in B_1, x(t_2) \in B_2, \ldots \}$$
For example, the probability for a path (with ##x(t_0)=x_0##) to be in the cylinder set ##O^{t_1 t_2}_{B_1 B_2}## is (up to some normalization factors) given by
$$P(O^{t_1 t_2}_{B_1 B_2})=\int dx_2 dx_1 \chi_{B_2}(x_2) e^{-\frac{(x_2-x_1)^2}{t_2-t_1}} \chi_{B_1}(x_1) e^{-\frac{(x_1-x_0)^2}{t_1-t_0}} \hat = \lVert P_{B_2} U(t_2-t_1) P_{B_1} U(t_1-t_0)\delta_{x_0 t_0}\rVert$$
Here, I have defined the projections ##(P_B f)(x)=\chi_B(x) f(x)## and the time evolution operators ##U(t)=e^{-t\Delta}##, which are just expressed as integrations against the heat kernel in the above integral. Of course, nobody would think of the projectors ##P_B## as a form of time evolution in the totally classical case of Brownian motion. The Brownian particle just follows some random path and the the probability for a given set of paths just happens to involve this projector.
In quantum mechanics, the situation is completely analogous. The projectors of the position operator ##\hat x## are also given by characteristic functions ##\chi_B(x)## and the time evolution of the Schrödinger equation (for example for the free particle) is given by ##U(t)=e^{-it\frac{\Delta}{2m}}##. This suggests in a very compelling way that the projections are not "a different form of time evolution", like the Copenhagen interpretation suggests. Measurements don't play any distinguished role.