harrylin
- 3,874
- 93
Interesting further input from another thread:
Bell relied on the fact that deterministically A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) = A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w); and while it is generally held that the sign isn't important, De Raedt reproduced similar observables in his illustration. However:
I had overlooked that the inequality that De Raedt gave as example is one of Boole - and not exactly one of Bell. Thanks for pointing that out!
So, he merely wanted to illustrate how that kind of inequalites (Boole/Bell) can be broken with local realism, if applied in the peculiar manner of Bell. And it appears to me that Boole did not assume a certain outcome result; according to the presentation, the Boole inequality of eq.113 in De Raedt's paper must be valid for all proper pair combinations, no matter what the products are. But instead of lingering on that point, for this discussion it will be interesting to test Bell's inequality (his equation no.15) on De Raedt's illustration.
Now, it looks to me that your representation here above of Bell's original inequality is still not quite right: an absolute sign is lacking. According to my copy, Bell's eq.15 for locations 1 and 2 is (rearranged):
<br /> \begin{eqnarray}<br /> |\langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle| - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,. \qquad<br /> \end{eqnarray}<br />
And the same for location pairs (1,3) and (2,3).
Here are the fictive measurement results once more, for locations 1-3 on even and odd days:
... Even ...|.. Odd
L ...1...2...3.|..1...2...3
Aa +1 +1 +1.| -1. -1. -1
Ab +1. -1 +1.| -1 +1. -1
Ac. -1. -1. -1.|+1 +1 +1
Computing from the results for location pair (1,2), I obtain as outcomes: +1, -1.
That location pair does not break Bell's inequality, the average is 0.
For location pair (2,3), I obtain as outcomes: +1, +1. Average +1.
Also no breaking of Bell's inequality.
For location pair (1,3), I obtain as outcomes: +3, +3. Average +3.
If I'm not mistaken, this pair very strongly breaks Bell's inequality!
Thus it's easy to modifiy De Raedt's illustration for Bell's original inequality: just take Lille=1, Lyon=3.
Now, it's a bit of a weak point that this effect is not homegeneous; but while unrealistic for Lille and Lyon, we can imagine a random fluctuation of such funny properties between all locations. Let's see what that gives for the average result of all locations:
(0 + 1 + 3) / 3 = 4/3
Thus, Bell's inequality applied on that refined illustration, gives according to me (I may have made an error of course):
4/3 <= 1
Obviously that inequality is broken.
In conclusion, it still looks to me that De Raedt's modified illustration with patients does show how inequalites like those of Bell can be broken with local realism.
wle said:That's not a counter-example.
What they claim to violate is Bell's original 1964 inequality. Bell's original inequality is something of an odd duckling in the zoology of Bell inequalities in that it relies on an extra (but entirely observable) assumption. Specifically, in their notation, and putting the locations back on (Lille = 1, Lyon = 2), the Bell inequality uses the assumption that A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) = A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w). This is observable, since it implies that \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) \rangle = 1, and it just means that the correct way to state Bell's inequality should really be something like
\langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}}(w) \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}}(w) \rangle \geq -1 \quad \text{given that} \quad \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) \rangle = 1 \,.
Their counter-example isn't a counter-example because it has \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) \rangle = -1. Incidentally, if you try to read the inequality above in the same way as other Bell inequalities (i.e. without imposing a condition like A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) = A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w)), then it's easy to see that its local bound is actually -3 (the same as the algebraic bound) instead of -1. [..]
Bell relied on the fact that deterministically A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}(w) = A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}}(w); and while it is generally held that the sign isn't important, De Raedt reproduced similar observables in his illustration. However:
wle said:[..] Bell derived some inequalities for the case where \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = -1. You can alternatively derive some similar but not identical inequalities for the case where \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = +1. The particular inequality that de Raedt et. al. considered is derived assuming \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = +1, and there is simply no reason to expect it should be satisfied if \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = -1.
Specifically, if you assume \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = -1, you can derive the following four inequalities:
<br /> \begin{eqnarray}<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\geq& -1 \,, \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\geq& -1 \,, \qquad (*) \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,, \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,. \qquad (*)<br /> \end{eqnarray}<br />
The second and fourth of these inequalities, which I've marked (*), are the ones Bell derived in 1964. Specifically, they're equivalent to Eq. (15) of Bell's 1964 paper [1]. The other two can easily be derived in an analogous manner (or, alternatively, just by flipping the sign of A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}}).
If you instead set \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle = +1, you get four slightly different inequalities, which you can basically all derive by flipping the sign on A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}}:
<br /> \begin{eqnarray}<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\geq& -1 \,, \qquad (\#) \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\geq& -1 \,, \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,, \\<br /> \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle + \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,.<br /> \end{eqnarray}<br />
The first of these, (#), is the one that de Raedt et. al. tested.
[..][1] J. S. Bell, Physics 1 3 195--200 (1964).
I had overlooked that the inequality that De Raedt gave as example is one of Boole - and not exactly one of Bell. Thanks for pointing that out!
So, he merely wanted to illustrate how that kind of inequalites (Boole/Bell) can be broken with local realism, if applied in the peculiar manner of Bell. And it appears to me that Boole did not assume a certain outcome result; according to the presentation, the Boole inequality of eq.113 in De Raedt's paper must be valid for all proper pair combinations, no matter what the products are. But instead of lingering on that point, for this discussion it will be interesting to test Bell's inequality (his equation no.15) on De Raedt's illustration.
Now, it looks to me that your representation here above of Bell's original inequality is still not quite right: an absolute sign is lacking. According to my copy, Bell's eq.15 for locations 1 and 2 is (rearranged):
<br /> \begin{eqnarray}<br /> |\langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{b}} \rangle - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{a}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle| - \langle A^{1}_{\mathbf{b}} A^{2}_{\mathbf{c}} \rangle &\leq& +1 \,. \qquad<br /> \end{eqnarray}<br />
And the same for location pairs (1,3) and (2,3).
Here are the fictive measurement results once more, for locations 1-3 on even and odd days:
... Even ...|.. Odd
L ...1...2...3.|..1...2...3
Aa +1 +1 +1.| -1. -1. -1
Ab +1. -1 +1.| -1 +1. -1
Ac. -1. -1. -1.|+1 +1 +1
Computing from the results for location pair (1,2), I obtain as outcomes: +1, -1.
That location pair does not break Bell's inequality, the average is 0.
For location pair (2,3), I obtain as outcomes: +1, +1. Average +1.
Also no breaking of Bell's inequality.
For location pair (1,3), I obtain as outcomes: +3, +3. Average +3.
If I'm not mistaken, this pair very strongly breaks Bell's inequality!
Thus it's easy to modifiy De Raedt's illustration for Bell's original inequality: just take Lille=1, Lyon=3.
Now, it's a bit of a weak point that this effect is not homegeneous; but while unrealistic for Lille and Lyon, we can imagine a random fluctuation of such funny properties between all locations. Let's see what that gives for the average result of all locations:
(0 + 1 + 3) / 3 = 4/3
Thus, Bell's inequality applied on that refined illustration, gives according to me (I may have made an error of course):
4/3 <= 1
Obviously that inequality is broken.
In conclusion, it still looks to me that De Raedt's modified illustration with patients does show how inequalites like those of Bell can be broken with local realism.