Can grandpa understand the Bell's Theorem?

  • #151
JesseM said:
...If you look at what Einstein was hoping for when he talked about a more complete explanation for QM, it seems he was thinking of a hidden variable theory based on exactly the same type of assumptions that physicists now call "local realism", the type of theory I was describing in 1) and 2) in [post=3245651]this post[/post]. I can give you quotes from Einstein's writings to support this, if you request.

Please provide quotes from Einstein's writings to support this.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #152
miosim said:
Please provide quotes from Einstein's writings to support this.
OK. In this post my comments will be in blue, quotes from Einstein and other authors in normal black text. Here are some quotes from a letter Einstein wrote to Schrödinger immediately after the EPR paper, saying that he thought the paper did not do such a good job explaining his point, and trying to clarify his own meaning with use of a helpful analogy. This is from pp. 167-168 of The Age of Entanglement by Louisa Gilder:[/color]

Einstein had not yet received Schrödinger's letter, when, on June 17, he wrote to him of Bohr's point of view: "I consider the renunciation of a spatio-temporal setting for real events to be idealistic, even spiritualistic. This epistemology-soaked orgy ought to burn itself out." He was not sure where Schrödinger stood in all of this: "No doubt, however, you smile at me and think that, after all, many a young whore turns into an old praying sister, and many a young revolutionary becomes an old reactionary."

The next day, Schrödinger's letter arrived, and Einstein thanked him for it, explaining that he had not written the paper himself and apologizing that it "did not come out as well as I had originally wanted; rather the essential thing was, so to speak, smothered by the formalism." For example, he explained, "I don't give a sausage" whether or not incompatible observables--Bohr's favorite subject--are involved.

It all came down to the relationship of Schrödinger's equation to reality. What is the connection between the mathematical description of events, and the events themselves? In what way does the Schrödinger wavefunction, ψ, reflect the actual state that a particle found itself in? Reality, or the particle's real situation, is represented in these discussions by the word state or the phrase state of affairs. The wavefunction, ψ, must represent this real state of affairs somehow. But it was hard to even articulate what was meant by such a connection to reality, or even what was meant by reality or state.

In his letter to Schrödinger, Einstein characteristically cut through this briar patch of linguistics with a parable. He wanted to illuminate the main point that had been obscured in the EPR paper. "In front of me stand two boxes, with lids that can be opened, and into which I can look when they are open. This looking is called 'making an observation.' In addition there is a ball, which can be found in one or the other of the two boxes where an observation is made. Now I describe a state of affairs as follows: The probability is one-half that the ball is in the first box." (This is all the Schrödinger equation will tell you.) "Is this a complete description?" asks Einstein, and then gives two different answers.

"NO: A complete description is: the ball is (or is not) in the first box...

"YES: Before I open the box the ball is not in one of the two boxes. Being in a definite box only comes about when I lift the covers...

"Naturally, the second 'spiritualist' or Schrödingerian interpretation is absurd," Einstein continued tactfully, "and the man on the street would only take the first, Bornian, interpretation seriously." Born might not have recognized his interpretation, which Einstein seemed to be using in this description only as far as he wanted to, but presumably Bohr would have recognized himself, even without being named: "But the Talmudic philosopher whistles at 'Reality' as at a bugaboo of naïveté, and declares that the two conceptions differ only in their mode of expression...

"One cannot get at the Talmudist if one does not make use of a supplementary principle: the separation principle," Einstein explains. "The contents of the second box are independent of what happens to the first. If one holds fast to the separation principle, only the Born description is possible, but not it is incomplete."

So I think it's fairly clear that Einstein is saying that if you have a scenario like this:

--Experimenters are performing a certain type of measurement on two objects (boxes or particles) and we find that they are guaranteed to get perfectly correlated results with probability 1 (like the guarantee that if one experimenter opens his box and gets the result "saw a ball", that must mean that when the other experimenter opened her box she got the result "didn't see a ball)

Then if we believe in the "separation principle" saying that any properties of one object immediately before measurement are independent of what happens to the other object, we must conclude that before measurement both objects had properties which predetermined the results they'd give, with the predetermined results being perfectly correlated (in terms of boxes, this just means that before either was opened there was already a definite truth that one had a ball inside and the other didn't, and the property of having a ball inside predetermines the measurement result "saw a ball" while the property of not having a ball inside predetermines the measurement result "didn't see a ball"). So the separation principle and the perfectly correlated results together imply there are local properties associated with each object before measurement, properties that predetermine their responses to being measured. And if the wavefunction does not specify these properties, then either the wavefunction is giving an incomplete description of the full physical state of each object, or the separation principle is false. But it's clear from the above that Einstein was on the side of the separation principle being true and the completeness of the wavefunction being false, he calls it "absurd" to advocate an interpretation where there is no definite truth about what's in each box until they're opened, and mocks this interpretation as being the argument of a "Talmudic philosopher".

Arthur Fine also talks about this letter in his book The Shaky Game: Einstein Realism and the Quantum Theory, and after describing Einstein's two-box scenario, goes on to say on pp. 36-37:[/color]

Einstein continues in this letter to give a technical reformulation of the EPR argument. It is a little confusing because it introduces a further refinement of the idea of completeness (this time in terms of state functions correlated to real states of affairs). But I think there is enough material contained, as it were, in Einstein's boxes to give at least one formulation of some of the essentials of EPR that were obscured by Podolsky's exposition.

Consider the system of two particles correlated via the conservation law for total linear momentum. Separation is the claim that whether a physical property holds for one of the particles does not depend on measurements (or other interactions) made on the other particle when the pair is widely separated in space. Completeness is the claim that if a certain physical property in fact holds for one particle at a given time, then the state function for the combined system at that time should yield probability one for finding that the property does hold (i.e., the subsystem consisting of the particle should have a state function which is an eigenstate for the property in question).

One can now copy Einstein's box argument as follows. Suppose the two particles (A and B) are far apart and I measure, say, particle A for linear momentum (in a certain direction). Using the conservation law I can infer the linear momentum of particle B from the result of this measurement on A. Thus after the A measurement, the B particle has a certain linear momentum. By separation, this real property of B must have held already at the time when I began my measurement on A (or just before, in the case of instantaneous measurement). For otherwise I would have created the momentum at B by measuring A, in violation of separation. But at the initial moment of the A measurement, the state of the composite system does not yield probability one for finding any momentum value for B, for that state is a nontrivial superposition of products of "momentum eigenstates" for the A and B subsystems. Hence the description provided by the state function given by quantum theory is incomplete. Here, as in the illustration, the argument establishes the incompatibility of separation and completeness.

It is this incompatibility that I take to be the central conclusion, which got obscured in EPR. Many years later, in Schilpp (1949, p. 682) Einstein put it succinctly in these words:

the paradox forces us to relinquish one of the following two assertions:
(1) the description by means of the ψ-function is complete
(2) the real states of spatially separated objects are independent of each other.


It is important to notice that the conclusion Einstein draws from EPR is not a categorical claim for the incompleteness of quantum theory. It is rather that the theory poses a dilemma between completeness and separation; both cannot be true. It is also important to notice that the argument I have drawn from Einstein's illustration does not depend in any way on simultaneous measurements or even attributions of position and momentum. The argument depends on the satisfaction of a single conservation law and the inferences drawn from that concerning the measurement of a single variable. This feature of the situation, I believe, is completely buried in the original paper and, because of that, Einstein's ideas concerning completeness and separation have become needlessly entangled with discussions of the uncertainty formulas and hidden variables. In his letter to Schrödinger of June 19, 1935, Einstein says that if the argument he gives applies to pairs of incompatible observables "ist mir wurst," which I would translate loosely as "I couldn't care less." The argument nowhere depends on that, nor do the basic ideas.

Although Fine says that the basic argument was just to show the incompatibility of completeness and separation, as I noted above Einstein clearly favored keeping separation and throwing out the idea that the wavefunction provides a complete description (i.e. there must be other properties not specified by the wavefunction)...on p. 38 Fine also writes:[/color]

Einstein wanted to use the dilemma posed by EPR to show that if we maintain the ideas of action-by-contact embodied in the separation principle, then we must view quantum theory as providing no more than a statistical account of the realm of objects whose properties outstrip the descriptive apparatus of the theory. As we have seen, he felt that the concepts needed to describe these properties adequately would be other than the dynamical concepts of classical physics. Thus, although Einstein took the incompleteness to be a sign that something better was required, he never showed any interest in the hidden variables program for filling out the theory from within.

I think the point being made here is that although he thought that the wavefunction description was incomplete so some form of extra variables (whether "hidden" or potentially measurable by some technique not dreamed of by quantum physicists) would be needed in a more complete description, probably he didn't think this was likely to just involve assigning values to the conventional quantum variables like position and momentum in cases where the wavefunction doesn't specify their values, he was hoping the variables would be of some new type.

In terms of the box analogy, one might imagine that instead of one box containing a ball before being opened, they both contain computers connected to holographic projectors, and the computers can sense when the lid is being opened and depending on their programming they will either respond by projecting an image of a ball, or projecting the image of an empty box. In this case the local variables associated with each box would not consist of "ball" or "no ball", but rather would be a detailed specification of the programming of each computer. But it would still be true based on the separation principle and the perfect correlation between results that if one was programmed to project a ball when the box was opened, that must mean the other was programmed to project an empty box, so the local variables (the program of each computer) would still predetermine the fact that one would give the measurement result "saw a ball" and the other would give the result "didn't see a ball".

Note that this sort of thing is quite possible in my assumptions 1) and 2) (which as I said I think are just a restatement of Bell's assumptions), since 1) says nothing specific about what the "local facts" actually are. In the example of measuring the momentum of two entangled particles, all that's necessary for a perfect correlation is that whatever the local facts are that cause a measurement of one particle to reveal a momentum p, the local facts associated with the other particle must also such that if a momentum measurement is made on it, it will yield result -p.

The idea that Einstein didn't want the "extra" (possibly hidden) variables to just be specification of the values of unmeasured quantum-mechanical properties is also suggested by this quote from p. 57, which is discussing Einstein's idea that the wavefunction just stands for a statistical ensemble of possible complete descriptions of the state:[/color]

This suggestion, that his remarks about ensembles constitute a kind of hidden variables theory, was actually put to Einstein in a letter from Aron Kupperman (November 10, 1954). In his reply Einstein does not deny the connection but rather downplays its significance by writing as follows, "I think it is not possible to get rid of the statistical character of the present quantum theory by merely adding something to the latter, without changing the fundamental concepts about the whole structure" (letter of November 14, 1954; from the English draft).

And on p. 58 Fine quotes Einstein's "Autobiographical Notes":[/color]

It is my opinion that the contemporary quantum theory by means of certain definitely laid down basic concepts, which on the whole have been taken over from classical mechanics, constitutes an optimal formulation of the connections. I believe, however, that this theory offers no useful point of departure for future developments. (Schilpp 1949, p. 87)

Finally on pp. 60-61 Fine describes what he understands as Einstein's idea of locality:[/color]

Einstein's several reworking of the EPR situation certainly involve a locality principle. It is this:

Einstein-locality. The real, physical state of one system is not immediately influenced by the kinds of measurements directly made on the second system, which is sufficiently spatially separated from the first.

I think my citations in the paper establish that this formulation is Einstein's. It differs from Bell's just over what it is that is not supposed to be influenced at a distance. For Bell it is the outcomes of the measurements of certain quantum observables (like spin). For Einstein it is the "real, physical states." In his various writings Einstein says even less about the nature of these postulated real states than the says about his ensemble interpretation, and for good reason. He was urging others, and struggling himself, to build a new theory that would "discover these states, i.e. invent them. Whatever these states are, they would indeed (in Einstein's conception, at least) determine the real physical variables and, most likely, the outcomes of measurement of these. But Einstein is very clear that, in his opinion, the quantum mechanical variables (the "observables") are the wrong ones. They are not the real physical variables, and that is why it is hopeless to try to complete quantum theory from within.

I agree with Fine about the idea that the real physical states need not involve conventional QM observables like momentum (again think of my analogy in which the real state is the programming of a computer which can either project an image of a ball or an empty box when the box is opened), but I disagree that Bell's formulation was any different, see my comments in the second-to-last paragraph of [post=3264303]post #142[/post] explaining why I think that my notion of a theory involving an unspecified collection of "local facts" is equivalent to Bell's talk of "local beables".

I should also note that Fine thinks there is some possibility of getting around Bell's theorem by use of a "prism model" in which some particles are intrinsically "defective" for certain types of measurements, so if we try to measure a given property (like spin in a particular direction) some fraction of the particles just won't show up in our measurements and thus won't be included in our dataset, which means the choice of what to measure can no longer be considered independent of the properties that the particle had immediately before measurement in our dataset (if this is unclear, billschnieder explained this type of model in terms of my own lotto card analogy in posts [post=2767632]113[/post] and [post=2767828]115[/post] on an older thread). Bell does assume in most of his proofs that there is no correlation between particle properties before measurement and the choice of detector setting, but it seems to me that these prism models would be themselves contradict the predictions of QM, so they aren't really relevant to a theoretical proof showing that local realism is incompatible with QM. But in terms of the possibility that something like this could be true experimentally, I think this loophole is just one version of what's called the"detection efficency loophole", and there are modified versions of Bell inequalities which take into account that not all particle pairs are successfully measured, see here. There have been Bell tests with ions that managed to close the detector efficiency loophole, see [post=2851208]this post[/post], although they didn't simultaneously close the locality loophole (though experiments with photons have closed that one, none have yet closed both simultaneously. It seems pretty unlikely that we could have a non-contrived-looking local realist theory where both types of loopholes were being exploited at once, though.)[/color]
 
Last edited:
  • #153
JesseM said:
[..] There's another paper here which responds to that one and claims to discount its conclusions:
http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/andp.201010462/abstract
http://arxiv.org/abs/0910.4740

And then Schulz responds here:
http://arxiv.org/abs/0910.5660

Thanks Jesse for trying; however it's besides the point. Schultz, Schmelzer and the reviewers accept Nelson's critique/precision concerning "passive locality". Regretfully I still don't understand what it means. As nobody here could answer that question I now started a dedicated thread on it.
https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=494057
Please don't further comment on my question in this thread.

Regards,
Harald
 
Last edited:
  • #154
JesseM said:
"One cannot get at the Talmudist if one does not make use of a supplementary principle: the separation principle," Einstein explains. "The contents of the second box are independent of what happens to the first. If one holds fast to the separation principle, only the Born description is possible, but not it is incomplete."
Little typo here which makes the last part of Einstein's quote confusing, it should read "but now it is incomplete".
 
  • #155
JesseM,

Sorry for the late response.
I don’t see how the references you presented demonstrate that Einstein rejected the mathematical formalism of QM as incorrect. Only in this case Bell could justify that his “local realism” matches with Einstein views.
From http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/EPR_paradox
“…Einstein struggled to the end of his life for a theory that could better comply with causality, protesting against the view that there exists no objective physical reality other than that which is revealed through measurement interpreted in terms of quantum mechanical formalism…”
Regarding Bell’s theorem, the only thing I don’t understand is how his theory was accepted by the scientific community. His inability to offer a reasonable model of “local realism” that would match Einstein’s views, his jumping to a conclusion about the non-existence of the realistic model that would match with QM formalism, and the end jumping to a conclusion about the “influence over distance” that at the same time contradicts with the widely accepted theory of relativity – all this seemed childish to me.
I am done with Bell’s theorem. You may not believe this but I didn’t understand it when I started this thread, so I wasn’t faking in my introductory post asking for help.

Thanks,
Mark

P.S.
I hope to return in a month or so to discuss new interpretation of quantum mechanics including my interpretation of Bell’s experiment.
 
Last edited:
  • #156
miosim said:
JesseM,

Sorry for the late response.
I don’t see how the references you presented demonstrate that Einstein rejected the mathematical formalism of QM as incorrect. Only in this case Bell could justify that his “local realism” matches with Einstein views.
Sigh. Why would Einstein have needed to think "the mathematical formalism of QM is incorrect" even if he had the same notion of local realism as Bell? Bell hadn't yet proved that there needed to be any inconsistency between Einstein's version of local realism--identical to my 1) and 2), and identical to Bell's "local causality--and "the mathematical formalism of QM". I already explained this concept to you, read it again a few times until it sinks in:
JesseM said:
No, it isn't. You're missing the elephant in the room, which is that Einstein didn't know that it would be impossible for a local realistic theory to reproduce QM predictions, because Bell hadn't proved that while Einstein was alive. If you look at what Einstein was hoping for when he talked about a more complete explanation for QM, it seems he was thinking of a hidden variable theory based on exactly the same type of assumptions that physicists now call "local realism", the type of theory I was describing in 1) and 2) in [post=3245651]this post[/post]. I can give you quotes from Einstein's writings to support this, if you request.
Then after I wrote that last sentence there, you took me up on the offer to actually post some quotes, but now in your most recent post I see you've completely dropped the subject of whether Einstein's assumptions were the same as 1) and 2) (the specific claim I was offering to provide evidence for when I said "I can give you quotes from Einstein's writing to support this"), and instead decided to just mindlessly repeat the same confused arguments you made before. Guess I shouldn't have wasted my time, should have known better than to confuse you with a person who is actually interested in thoughtful discussion of the issues.
miosim said:
Regarding Bell’s theorem, the only thing I don’t understand is how his theory was accepted by the scientific community. His inability to offer a reasonable model of “local realism” that would match Einstein’s views
So you aren't even going to tell me if you think Einstein's conception is any different from my 1) and 2), or whether you think Bell's conception is different from my 1) and 2)? It's easy to stick with the same preconceptions you had from the start if you refuse to actually answer detailed questions or think about specifics, and just stick to vague sweeping statements and pompous claims about it being "childish".
miosim said:
I am done with Bell’s theorem. You may not believe this but I didn’t understand it when I started this thread
I believe you still don't understand it, as evidenced by the fact that you thought my 1) and 2) were not equivalent to it, and the fact that you were continually making false statements like that it assumes a "classical deterministic corpuscular model of the photons" (it doesn't).
 
Last edited:
  • #157
2. The local facts about any given point P in spacetime are only causally influenced by facts about points in the past light cone of P, meaning if you already know the complete information about all points in some spacelike cross-section of the past light cone, additional knowledge about points at a spacelike separation from P cannot alter your prediction about what happens at P itself (your prediction may be a probabilistic one if the laws of physics are non-deterministic).

It is a logical contradiction to say you will still make a probabilistic prediction even if you already have complete information about the event. Unless by probabilistic you mean a probability of 0 or 1, which is infact not a 'probability' but a 'certainty'. Assigning a probability to an event implies there is a degree of uncertainty involved which means there is missing information. You can therefore not claim to know everything (ie have complete information) about the event at the same time! Determinism has nothing to do with this, as incomplete information about deterministic laws will give you probabilistic results.

The words "complete" as used by EPR in the phrase "complete theory" and as used in the phrase "complete information" above have the same meaning. As concerns what the EPR claims about the meaning of reality, the following statement is quite clear:

Whatever the meaning assigned to the term complete, the following requirement for a complete theory seems to be a necessary one: every element of physical reality must have a counterpart in the physical theory.
...
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (ie with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity.
So clearly, any definition of "element of physical reality" which is "probabilistic" is foreign to the EPR one.

As concerns locality, it has been shown that Bell's inequality can be satisfied by a system in which non-local information transfer is imposed, contrary to popular belief, and calling into question claims that Bell's inequality somehow faithfully represent the EPR requirement for locality.

Bell's inequality violation due to misidentification of spatially non-stationary random processes
Louis Sica. Journal of Modern Optics, 1362-3044, Volume 50, Issue 15, 2003, Pages 2465 – 2474
----

The connection between Bell's inequalities based on probabilities and those based on correlations
Author: Louis Sicaa

Abstract
Violation of Bell inequalities is widely regarded as a definitive test for non-locality. However, Bell correlational inequalities must always be satisfied by all jointly present, cross-correlated data. The correlations of variable pairs obtained in repeated runs are not cross-correlated in this way and are not required to satisfy the Bell inequality. In addition, by using information regarded as non-local, proper joint correlations may be computed among counterfactual and measured variables. These correlations satisfy the Bell inequality, but are spatially non-stationary in angle. By using a simple symmetry condition, such considerations may be extended to inequalities in probabilities. The latter may be derived directly from correlational inequalities developed by Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt (CHSH). Violation of either correlational or probabilistic Bell inequalities then implies that the Bell correlation cannot be accounted for by a stochastic process that is spatially stationary in angle coordinates. However, other processes may still be allowed.

An additional point to be made about point (2) above is the fact that is conflates or does not clearly distinguish between single events and multiple events. QM does not and can not make predictions about single individual events. It only makes predictions about the results obtained when many different events have been accumulated.

It has been shown by Barut almost 10 years ago, that carefully distinguishing between individual events and ensembles of events is sufficient to debunk the "no-hidden variable theorems".

A. O. Barut Foundations of Physics, Vol. 22, No. 1, 1992 "How to Avoid "Quantum Paradoxes"
Conclusion:
We have seen that all major "no-hidden variable theorems" involve two or more spins, and make use of the tacit assumption (not even stated that it is an assumption) that each individual spin component has dichotomic +/- 1/2 value for every single event. We believe that this assumption, which is correct for repeated events, i.e., for polarized beams, is not correct for single events. Modifying it, we not only obtain correct EPR-spin correlations, but also avoid the so-called quantum paradoxes, without changing the results of standard quantum theory which only applies to repeated events.
 
  • #158
billschnieder said:
... As concerns locality, it has been shown that Bell's inequality can be satisfied by a system in which non-local information transfer is imposed, contrary to popular belief.

It has been shown by Barut almost 10 years ago, that carefully distinguishing between individual events and ensembles of events is sufficient to debunk the "no-hidden variable theorems".

A. O. Barut Foundations of Physics, Vol. 22, No. 1, 1992 "How to Avoid "Quantum Paradoxes"

Your references are grossly inadequate and go against generally accepted science. I notice that you are again hijacking a thread to make arguments against Bell, when the purpose here was to understand Bell.

Please stick to forum guidelines and take this to Independent Research. Or write a paper and get it published.
 
  • #159
billschnieder said:
JesseM said:
2. The local facts about any given point P in spacetime are only causally influenced by facts about points in the past light cone of P, meaning if you already know the complete information about all points in some spacelike cross-section of the past light cone, additional knowledge about points at a spacelike separation from P cannot alter your prediction about what happens at P itself (your prediction may be a probabilistic one if the laws of physics are non-deterministic).
It is a logical contradiction to say you will still make a probabilistic prediction even if you already have complete information about the event.
Try reading more carefully, I didn't say anything about "complete information about the event", I said "if you already know the complete information about all points in some spacelike cross-section of the past light cone, additional knowledge about points at a spacelike separation from P cannot alter your prediction about what happens at P itself".

Bell also defined local causality in terms of complete cross-sections of the past light cone of events, see my summary of his "La nouvelle cuisine" paper in [post=3248153]this post[/post] which includes links to the majority of the text of the paper on google books. In particular, look at the diagram Bell includes at the top of this page, where either boundary of region 3 of the diagram represents the type of "spacelike cross-section of the past light cone" I was referring to, and Bell defines local causality to mean that if you know the complete set of information about all local facts in region 3 (he calls them "local beables"), then further information about region 2 will not alter your predictions about what happens in region 1. He formalizes this idea on this later page, where the combination of c and λ represent all local beables in region 3, "a" represents some detector setting in region 1 while "A" represents some measurement outcome in region 1, similarly "b" is a detector setting in region 2 while "B" is a measurement outcome in region 2...then local causality can be expressed as the condition that P(A|B,a,b,c,λ)=P(A|a,c,λ).
billschnieder said:
The words "complete" as used by EPR in the phrase "complete theory" and as used in the phrase "complete information" above have the same meaning. As concerns what the EPR claims about the meaning of reality, the following statement is quite clear:
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (ie with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity.
So clearly, any definition of "element of physical reality" which is "probabilistic" is foreign to the EPR one.
Nonsense, they only say that if you can predict with probability 1 what a measurement will yield (as is true if you measure one member of an entangled pair and are making a prediction about the other member), then "there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity". This does not imply the converse, that if there is an element of physical reality corresponding to what you are going to measure, it must automatically be possible to predict with probability 1 what the result will be at some time prior to the measurement. The EPR statement is true under my assumptions 1) and 2) about "local realism" which you are responding to (for reference they are detailed in [post=3231977]this post[/post]), the converse statement is not true under my assumptions, if you know of any statement in the EPR paper suggesting they would disagree please point it out.
billschnieder said:
As concerns locality, it has been shown that Bell's inequality can be satisfied by a system in which non-local information transfer is imposed, contrary to popular belief
Again you seem confused about some principles of logical reasoning, saying "X implies Y" does not automatically mean "Y implies X" or equivalently "Y cannot be true if ~X" (here Y=Bell inequalities satisfied, X=local realism, and ~X=failure of local realism...in your earlier misconceived argument, Y=an element of physical reality corresponding to some quantity, and ~X=impossible to predict value of that quantity in advance)
billschnieder said:
An additional point to be made about point (2) above is the fact that is conflates or does not clearly distinguish between single events and multiple events.
I defined "local facts" to mean facts about a single point in spacetime, but I added the following clarification to show we could still talk about facts involving an extended region:
Keep in mind that 1) doesn't forbid you from talking about "facts" that involve an extended region of spacetime, it just says that these facts must be possible to deduce as a function of all the local facts in that region. For example, in classical electromagnetism we can talk about the magnetic flux through an extended 2D surface of arbitrary size, this is not itself a local quantity, but the total flux is simply a function of all the local magnetic vectors at each point on the surface, that's the sort of thing I meant when I said in 1) that all physical facts "can be broken down into a set of local facts". Similarly in certain Bell inequalities one considers the expectation values for the product of the two results (each one represented as either +1 or -1), obviously this product is not itself a local fact, but it's a trivial function of the two local facts about the result each experimenter got.
 
Last edited:
  • #160
DrChinese said:
Your references are grossly inadequate and go against generally accepted science. I notice that you are again hijacking a thread to make arguments against Bell, when the purpose here was to understand Bell.

Please stick to forum guidelines and take this to Independent Research. Or write a paper and get it published.
Everything mentioned above is material published in peer-reviewed journals and I have provided the citations to back them up. There is nothing independent in that. Perhaps you could point to what criteria you use for "adequacy" of references which hopefully is more than the fact that you do not like them.

There were claims made in this thread about what EPR meant by local realism, and what Bell meant by Local realism and how equivalent the two are. My response simply highlighted and emphasized aspects of the EPR position (in their own words) which I believe were being overlooked, with additional references backing up my points.

I understand that you do not like what I wrote. Which is not equivalent to violating forum guidelines.

It was stated that according to EPR you can know complete information and still your prediction may be a probabilistic one if the laws of physics are non-deterministic. I simply quoted the words from the original EPR paper to show that this statement is false and at best contrary to published EPR position. Do you have anything to say about this? Or you would rather I shut up let false statements like these stand.
 
Last edited:
  • #161
JesseM said:
Whatever the meaning assigned to the term complete, the following requirement for a complete theory seems to be a necessary one: every element of physical reality must have a counterpart in the physical theory.
...
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (ie with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity.
Nonsense, they only say that if you can predict with probability 1 what a measurement will yield (as is true if you measure one member of an entangled pair and are making a prediction about the other member), then "there exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quantity". This does not imply the converse, that if there is an element of physical reality corresponding to what you are going to measure, it must automatically be possible to predict with probability 1 what the result will be at some time prior to the measurement.
After adding back the full quote, including the first part which you conveniently left out, it is clear from the quoted EPR statements above that there is no place for "probabilistic" predictions in a complete theory, if you have complete information.

If every element of physical reality is present in the theory and you can predict every one of them with certainty, then you have complete information. Obviously according to the second part of the quote, you will not call it an element of physical reality if you can not predict it with certainty. Where then will your "probabilistic" prediction come from?

Any thing else is at odds with the EPR position, that's all I'm saying.
 
  • #162
billschnieder said:
After adding back the full quote, including the first part which you conveniently left out, it is clear from the quoted EPR statements above that there is no place for "probabilistic" predictions in a complete theory, if you have complete information.
You're still misunderstanding, if you know all the elements of reality in a given region of spacetime then you know the results of all measurements in that region with probability 1, but that doesn't imply if you know all the elements of reality in the past of that region (like "region 3" in the past of "region 1" in Bell's diagram), the results of measurements in the region must always be "determined" with probability 1. The idea of the EPR paper is that if you know with probability 1 what result you will get before you actually make the measurement, then there must already be elements of reality which determine that measurement result. This could still be true in a theory which contained some stochastic elements, just look at Einstein's example of the ball that's placed in one of two boxes, he's saying that since opening one box allows you to predict with probability 1 the result of opening the other, that means that even before you open the other box there are "elements of reality" inside that box which predetermine what you'll see--in this example, these would be assumed to just be the presence or absence of a ball inside the closed box. But that doesn't imply every aspect of the inside of the box is deterministic, for example the ball might be vibrating slightly and the vibrations could contain a genuinely random element. If there was no way to predict with probability 1 how it would vibrate at a time before we actually measured the vibrations, then prior to the time of measurement there need not have been any element of physical reality that predetermined what measurement result we would later get.
 
  • #163
JesseM said:
...You can't just declare two setups "equivalent" when they clearly aren't, Bell's setup involved two measurements with polarizers made at a spacelike separation, not two successive measurements with polarizers on the same light beam. As I said there is no way in classical electromagnetism to reproduce the QM prediction of the cos^2 relationship for the correlations of these two spacelike-separated measurements, despite Malus' law, so it would simply be false to claim that a completely different setup with non spacelike-separated measurements was "equivalent" and therefore that the QM prediction could be "derived" from Malus' law.

I think I may have lost myself in this discussion, would you mind explaining or posting a link for the type of setup you have in mind?
 
  • #164
edguy99 said:
I think I may have lost myself in this discussion, would you mind explaining or posting a link for the type of setup you have in mind?

JesseM is correctly pointing out that Malus' cos^2 and the QM prediction of cos^2 - are the same only by "coincidence" (there is a relationship but it is not straightforward to obtain). An LR model can - in fact must - deliver other results. The devil is in the details. If you have an LR model, it is on you to demonstrate it is local realistic as no one will believe you. Well, billschnieder might.
 
  • #165
edguy99 said:
I think I may have lost myself in this discussion, would you mind explaining or posting a link for the type of setup you have in mind?

http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0205171

"We use polarization-entangled photon pairs to demonstrate quantum nonlocality in an experiment suitable for advanced undergraduates. The photons are produced by spontaneous parametric downconversion using a violet diode laser and two nonlinear crystals. The polarization state of the photons is tunable. Using an entangled state analogous to that described in the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen ``paradox,'' we demonstrate strong polarization correlations of the entangled photons. Bell's idea of a hidden variable theory is presented by way of an example and compared to the quantum prediction. A test of the Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt version of the Bell inequality finds $S = 2.307 , in clear contradiction of hidden variable theories. The experiments described can be performed in an afternoon. "
 
  • #166
JesseM said:
You're still misunderstanding,
No you are.
if you know all the elements of reality in a given region of spacetime then you know the results of all measurements in that region with probability 1, but that doesn't imply if you know all the elements of reality in the past of that region (like "region 3" in the past of "region 1" in Bell's diagram), the results of measurements in the region must always be "determined" with probability 1.

The idea of the EPR paper is that if you know with probability 1 what result you will get before you actually make the measurement, then there must already be elements of reality which determine that measurement result.
What you are misunderstanding is the fact that the idea of hidden variables/elements of reality is tightly coupled with determinism and completeness. In a deterministic theory, if any two histories (or models) in the theory have identical state variables at time t=t0, then they have identical state variables at all times. (see Determinism and Probability in Physics, Peter Clark and Jeremy Butterfield, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 61, (1987), pp. 185-243 )

In such a theory, if you know the complete state of the system at a given point, it will be possible in principle to predict with certainty the state at any future point. Probabilities or uncertainties only arise in such a theory, if you do not have complete information.

This could still be true in a theory which contained some stochastic elements
This is not true. To say that the theory is stochastic and at the same time say that you can predict with certainty is a contradiction. On the one hand you are saying you have complete information, and on the other hand you are saying you do not.

just look at Einstein's example of the ball that's placed in one of two boxes, he's saying that since opening one box allows you to predict with probability 1 the result of opening the other, that means that even before you open the other box there are "elements of reality" inside that box which predetermine what you'll see --in this example, these would be assumed to just be the presence or absence of a ball inside the closed box. But that doesn't imply every aspect of the inside of the box is deterministic, for example the ball might be vibrating slightly and the vibrations could contain a genuinely random element. If there was no way to predict with probability 1 how it would vibrate at a time before we actually measured the vibrations, then prior to the time of measurement there need not have been any element of physical reality that predetermined what measurement result we would later get.
But this is misleading because the "theory" in this example is simply presence or absence of the ball, and has nothing to do with vibrations of the ball in the Box. Even so, complete information about the the ball in the box will then have to include more state variables specifying it's vibration, in which case you will still not obtain "probabilistic" results. If you mean that you can have complete information about presence of the ball and yet not have complete information about the vibrations of the ball, then you are effectively using a different theory for presence and a different one for vibrations. And since the presence or absence in a box have nothing to do with vibrations, additional information about the vibrations will not alter your prediction about presence or absence of the ball in the box. Therefore, it still doesn't make sense why you will give this example to back up your claim that your prediction can be probabilistic even with complete information.

You can not escape from the fact that "complete information/certainty" and "uncertainty/probability" are incompatible concepts. Unless you are referring to complete information about one thing, and uncertainty about an entirely different thing.

The main point remains therefore that according to EPR there is no place for "probabilistic" predictions in a complete theory, if you have complete information.
 
  • #167
billschnieder said:
What you are misunderstanding is the fact that the idea of hidden variables/elements of reality is tightly coupled with determinism and completeness. In a deterministic theory, if any two histories (or models) in the theory have identical state variables at time t=t0, then they have identical state variables at all times. (see Determinism and Probability in Physics, Peter Clark and Jeremy Butterfield, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, Vol. 61, (1987), pp. 185-243 )
Yes, I know what "determinism" means, it's pointless to provide an academic citation for this since we are not disagreeing on the basic definition of determinism.
billschnieder said:
This is not true. To say that the theory is stochastic and at the same time say that you can predict with certainty is a contradiction.
I didn't make the over-broad claim you accuse me of, you seem to be implying a false dichotomy between the possibilities "everything is stochastic, nothing can be predicted with certainty" and "everything is deterministic, everything can be predicted with certainty given sufficient knowledge of past conditions". What I was actually arguing was that you could have a theory where there are some stochastic elements but in certain situations it may still be possible to predict the outcome of a measurement with complete certainty. And I was also trying to make my definition of local realism as broad as possible, so it could be used to derive inequalities that would apply even in a situation where you don't see perfect correlations between separated measurements, for more on this point see below.
billschnieder said:
But this is misleading because the "theory" in this example is simply presence or absence of the ball, and has nothing to do with vibrations of the ball in the Box.
I didn't say the two were related! Similarly in the case of a stochastic local realistic theory that attempts to explain perfect correlations between measurements of some property like momentum, the stochastic element of the theory would have nothing to do with the momentum of these particles, which must be predetermined prior to measurement. Did you think I was saying otherwise? If so you misread me, I didn't suggest any stochastic element in the value of a specific quantity that was being found to have a perfect correlation (but that's if such a perfectly correlated quantity is assumed at all, which is something we may not want to assume if we are being as general as possible--again, see below).
billschnieder said:
Even so, complete information about the the ball in the box will then have to include more state variables specifying it's vibration, in which case you will still not obtain "probabilistic" results. If you mean that you can have complete information about presence of the ball and yet not have complete information about the vibrations of the ball, then you are effectively using a different theory for presence and a different one for vibrations.
No, it needn't involve multiple theories. You could have a single theory describing the motion of the molecules that make up the ball, which both allows their paths to have a degree of randomness but also forbids them from "tunneling" through a potential barrier like the walls of the box.
billschnieder said:
Therefore, it still doesn't make sense why you will give this example to back up your claim that your prediction can be probabilistic even with complete information.
Prediction of what can be probabilistic? If there is a perfect correlation between two measurements of some property like momentum, then any local realist theory which attempts to explain this must say that before they were measured, the local variables associated with each particle already completely predetermined what their momentum would be if measured, there is no "probabilistic" element there. But there may be other elements that are probabilistic, and likewise it may not be true in the first place that such a perfect correlation exists. But I think maybe now I see the source of the confusion between us (and I accept some of the blame for it), you were referring to this statement of mine:
2. The local facts about any given point P in spacetime are only causally influenced by facts about points in the past light cone of P, meaning if you already know the complete information about all points in some spacelike cross-section of the past light cone, additional knowledge about points at a spacelike separation from P cannot alter your prediction about what happens at P itself (your prediction may be a probabilistic one if the laws of physics are non-deterministic).
In this statement, I was attempting to be as general as Bell in my definition of local realism--some of the inequalities he derived did not depend on the assumption of a perfect correlation between separated measurements, and thus in some of his papers he defined "local causality" in as broad a way as possible so that knowledge of past conditions would not predetermine the measurement results with perfect certainty. I agree, as would Bell, that if you are looking at one of the inequalities that does assume a perfect correlation between measurements with the same detector setting, in that case it must be true that the measurement outcome was predetermined prior to measurements, that there is no probabilistic element at all. This conclusion can in fact be derived from the more general assumptions about local realism, which is why it doesn't need to be a starting assumption if you want to make your proof as general as possible.

In the "La nouvelle cuisine" paper I referred you to earlier (again see [post=3248153]this post[/post]), Bell was in fact deriving an inequality that doesn't assume perfect correlations, see here:

http://www.scholarpedia.org/article...Bell.27s_theorem_without_perfect_correlations (this article notes that the CHSH inequality is identical to the one Bell derived on p. 7 of this paper, equation 16, and you can see that's the same as the inequality 6.10.4 on this page of the "La nouvelle cuisine" paper)

Of course QM does predict perfect correlations in some situations, so if you're only interested in the theoretical question of whether QM is compatible with local realism, you're free to assume that such correlations exist just as EPR did (and as Bell did in some earlier papers) in that case we must say that complete knowledge of a cross-section of the past light cone of one measurement after the two light cones no longer overlap (like region 3 in Bell's diagram here) must indeed predetermine the outcome of any measurement, I agree that there can be no probabilistic element in the specific case of variables that are perfectly correlated this way. But if you want to come up with an inequality that you intend to test experimentally, it may be more useful to use one that does not assume "perfect" correlations since realistically you may not to be able to verify that this is true experimentally.

Related to this, I recently came across this paper which seems to have a very careful and precise discussion of Bell's assumptions in the "La nouvelle cuisine" paper, and on p. 11 the author notes:
There is, in particular, a tendency for a relatively superficial focus on the relatively formal aspects of Bell’s arguments, to lead commentators astray. For example, how many commentators have too-quickly breezed through the prosaic first section of Bell’s 1964 paper (p. 14-21) – where his reliance on the EPR argument “from locality to deterministic hidden variables” is made clear – and simply jumped ahead to section 2’s Equation 1 (p. 15), hence erroneously inferring (and subsequently reporting to other physicists and ultimately teaching to students) that the derivation “begins with deterministic hidden variables”? (1981, p. 157)
I agree with the author that in both Bell's first paper and in the EPR paper, the idea that the values of measured properties are predetermined is not a starting assumption, but rather something that is concluded if you have perfect correlations between separated measurements and if we assume the underlying theory involves only local causality (i.e. assuming a theory that respects conditions 1 and 2 from my [post=3231977]earlier post[/post], which as I [post=3270631]argued before[/post] are ones that I think Einstein would have accepted based on his comments).

edit: I see Bell also discusses his own and Einstein's opinion on determinism not being assumed at the outset on pp. 7-8 of the Bertlmann's socks paper (starting with the paragraph on p. 7 that begins, "It is important to note that to the limited degree that determinism plays a role in the EPR argument, it is not assumed but inferred.")
 
Last edited:
  • #168
JesseM,

I can’t answer your lengthy comments, because I have a narrow bandwidth of a time and abilities. Therefore I can handle only one task at a time, but and I am not sure to which of your comments I should respond first.

While reading your exchange with billschnieder I am wondering if the mathematics and the formalized logic are adequate tools to prove or disprove a reality. I think that a common language could handle this task much better. For me a reality is the stuff that happens regarding can we observe it or not and this, as I understand, is the position of Einstein about physical reality.

For Bohr and Heisenberg there is no physical reality if we can’t observe or measure it.
According to Bohr "…There is no quantum world. There is only an abstract quantum mechanical description. It is wrong to think that the task of physics is to find out how Nature is”
And for Heisenberg “… the atoms or the elementary particles are not ... real they form a world of potentialities or possibilities rather than one of things or facts”.

For those who faithfully follow Bohr and Heisenberg philosophy, they contradict to them self by trying to describe their non-real universe in term of real processes like influence over distance. They don’t have to do this because their task isn’t about explaining what happens inside this “unreal block box”, because allegedly nothing happens there and therefore their QM is complete.

Fort those who follow the Einstein’s philosophy the QM aren’t complete until they explain what actually happens inside this “real QM black box”. For these scientists there is plenty of work to do.
 
Last edited:
  • #169
miosim said:
I can’t answer your lengthy comments, because I have a narrow bandwidth of a time and abilities. Therefore I can handle only one task at a time, but and I am not sure to which of your comments I should respond first.
My comments to you in [post=3273668]post 156[/post] were not particularly lengthy. Anyway, you could start by addressing whether you see any reason to think Einstein's assumptions (which I quoted in [post=3270631]this post[/post], hopefully you had time to at least read it) differed from my 1) and 2), and if so where exactly.
miosim said:
For me a reality is the stuff that happens regarding can we observe it or not and this, as I understand, is the position of Einstein about physical reality.
Yes, and that's what the "local facts" in my 1) and 2) are supposed to represent, as well as Bell's "local beables". They needn't be anything directly observable, they are the real local facts about each local point in spacetime. They represent things like whether a sealed box has a ball inside it or not before we look in it, to use Einstein's example.
miosim said:
For those who faithfully follow Bohr and Heisenberg philosophy, they contradict to them self by trying to describe their non-real universe in term of real processes like influence over distance. They don’t have to do this because their task isn’t about explaining what happens inside this “unreal block box”, because allegedly nothing happens there and therefore their QM is complete.
You are totally confused if you think Bell was following Bohr, his intent was the opposite, to examine the features a theory would need if it purported to tell us what was really going on with quantum particles when they're not being measured.
miosim said:
Fort those who follow the Einstein’s philosophy the QM aren’t complete until they explain what actually happens inside this “real QM black box”. For these scientists there is plenty of work to do.
Yes, and this was Bell's philosophy as well, but thanks to him we know that anyone who wants a theory of what's really going on must accept that it cannot be a local theory (unless it violates some other of Bell's assumptions, like allowing the experimenter to split into multiple parallel versions, or allowing backwards-in-time causal influences).
 
  • #170
I have trouble with the very basics of what is supposedly being measured. I gather that you're basically measuring polarizations, but I'm not sure it makes sense.

The choice the observer has is to set up an apparatus. And apparently he can set up this apparatus in three different ways. One to detect an up or down, one to detect a left or right, and one to detect a forward and backward.

But as far as I can tell the diagrams don't explain physically what they are setting up...just in the abstract--that there are three different variables that can be measured.

But I never see an actual photograph of the physical set-up of the laboratories where they are doing these measurments. I never hear a description of the physical materials that are being used. For instance, is there a you-tube video where you can actually watch people with actual equipment (not just a cartoon, or animations) performing this experiment?
 
  • #171


miosim said:
Einstein said that you don't truly understand something unless you can explain it to your Grandma. I think that this should apply also to a grandpa.
I am a grandpa who is struggling to understand the Bell's Theorem. I read a number of popular books and articles, tryed Wikipedia, followed discussions on this forum, and even tried to read the original Bells’ paper, but I still cannot grasp the logic and the experimental proof of this theorem. The popular explanation of the experiment in terms of red and blue balls may be a good illustration but still doesn’t make sense to me as an explanation.
Of cause my inability to understand math is a biggest problem, but the controversial concepts of quantum mechanics don’t give me such a problem regardless that they are also based on math.
In spite of my shallow background in math (say high school level) I believe that this shouldn’t prohibit me to understand the physical concept assosiated with this theorem.
Actually, I view math as a formalized logic and logic works only within well defined area of knowledge. Therefore I am careful with the logical and mathematical deductions applied to subatomic events that are obviously not fully understood yet.
So I am asking for a help in understanding the Bell's theorem and its experimental proof in terms of physical concepts (of cause if we truly understand them). For the start I have a specific questions: How come the formalism of quantum theory leads to the Sine correlation while EPR formalism leads to Linear correlation (see Fig.below)?

Bell simply states that a photon or whatever once it is entangled
with another, supersedes time and space and can instantaneously interreact, no matter the supposed time or space distances, as if time and space do not factually exist, because they most likely don't.
 
  • #172
JesseM said:
My comments to you in post 156 were not particularly lengthy. Anyway, you could start by addressing whether you see any reason to think Einstein's assumptions (which I quoted in this post, hopefully you had time to at least read it) differed from my 1) and 2), and if so where exactly…
JesseM said:
1. The complete set of physical facts about any region of spacetime can be broken down into a set of local facts about the value of variables at each point in that regions (like the value of the electric and magnetic field vectors at each point in classical electromagnetism)

2. The local facts about any given point P in spacetime are only causally influenced by facts about points in the past light cone of P, meaning if you already know the complete information about all points in some spacelike cross-section of the past light cone, additional knowledge about points at a spacelike separation from P cannot alter your prediction about what happens at P itself (your prediction may be a probabilistic one if the laws of physics are non-deterministic).
Sorry but I cannot answer this question because 1) and 2) are two “technical” for me and the comments of Arthur Fine are too gossip-like for me to trust him. When I asked you to provide quotes from Einstein's I expect a direct Einstein’s writing and not an interpretation.

As I understand, the main goal of Einstein is to return a reality to physics by providing a meaning interpretation to QM formalism. EPR paper, was just one rhetorical argument (and may be not the best one) in favor of this view.
By the way, I don’t believe that a knowledge about the characteristic (spin, polarization, etc.) of one particle yields the complement characteristic of the the correlated particle (but for different reason than imposed by Copenhagen Interpretation) and I think that Einstein may accept this if this non-deterministic behavior will be explained within the framework of physical reality.
JesseM said:
They needn't be anything directly observable, they are the real local facts about each local point in spacetime. They represent things like whether a sealed box has a ball inside it or not before we look in it, to use Einstein's example.
“Sealed box” and other illustrative examples like Alice, Bob etc. are adding one more layer of interpretation and misinterpretation and in my opinion their use may cause more problems than help.
JesseM said:
You are totally confused if you think Bell was following Bohr, his intent was the opposite, to examine the features a theory would need if it purported to tell us what was really going on with quantum particles when they're not being measured. ).
Indeed it seems that Bell was sympathetic to Einstein ideas. However the passion with which Bell proclaimed impossibility of local realism and existence on non-locality (as inevitable) tell me that his conclusion was predetermined by strong influence of Copenhagen Interpretation.
JesseM said:
Yes, and this was Bell's philosophy as well, but thanks to him we know that anyone who wants a theory of what's really going on must accept that it cannot be a local theory (unless it violates some other of Bell's assumptions, like allowing the experimenter to split into multiple parallel versions, or allowing backwards-in-time causal influences).

Amen
 
  • #173
One problem highlighted by Bell is the paradoxical use of language by theorists
Most seem to use observation and measurement as interchangeable terms when they are not, and for me, it is the non understanding of terms of agreement that causes confusion.

Observations can be said to be commonsense, in as much as each of us, or even a mechanical device, can sense something in some way, and measurement can be said to be a comparison of the observations made.

If I am point A then point B is removed from me, and I can invent a device or tool of measurement to establish the distance of removal.
The same is true of every other measurement, and point A can exist beyond me and others by general agreement with them, and a distance measurement such as one yard between A and B can be established as a tool of imperial measurement.
However, the measurement is not superior to the observation, and in fact the observation is always part of any measurement just as commonsense is.

Tools of measurement, are imagined, invented, replicated, mechanised, atomized, devised and compromised, but the basic facts of point A and B still exist, no matter how many other points are included into one measurement and no matter how many tools of measurement are added together to form a new measurement.
Movement is a commonsense observation, even as speed of movement, and it becomes a complex measurement that uses measurements of time and distance to establish its veracity. Every complex measurement relies on other measurements and all of them rely on the observation of points A and B and the agreements that established the tools of measurement.

Bell’s theorem initially relies on two observations, the observable results of a series reading taken at point A and the observable results at point B. They are different, and the only tool of measurement used to define what exists between them is the % of difference that the reading of B is from A. The same is true in reverse and whatever the % difference that B is from A would be the same that A is from B.

Commonsense says that if these observations and a measurement of the difference between A and B observations in a reversed, handed world were taken, then if what was measured was the same in the non reversed world, the results would be identical.
This is the meat of the EPR experiment, and it allows an observer in the non reversed world to predict what a result will be in a handed and reversed world.

Predictability is an essential part of calculation, 2 + 2 always = 4 and calculating differences is the same as calculating that an addition of two numerically based measurements will always be the same.

In the EPR experiment, all factors in the reversed and non reversed worlds are shown to be identical, therefore the results of the same measurement taken in each world are predictable from the other world.

This predictability is inbuilt into measurements because the tool or device of measurement ensures it.
A yard may fluctuate in the material world due to a changing environment, but the yard of measurement never fluctuates and it never changes because it has been established, by agreement, as the difference between point A and point B in the abstract world of like minded people.
Distance exists as an observation, agreement verifies the distance as a measurement and this like minded agreement gives science an inflexible tool of abstract measurement, but its use still relies on the commonsense observations of A and B.

In the EPR experiment, the difference between A and B is established as a fact in the handed reversed and non reversed worlds, and the problem that Bell comes up with is one of calculations based on these facts, not that the facts exist.
Calculations are predictions, and Bell tries to say that an addition of 2 + 2 as measurements taken in the reversed and non reversed worlds does not = 4.

He does this by first making an assumption, that 2 + 2 = 4, then by saying that this is not proven by experiment, and that an inequality exists which shows that 2 + 2 = (6).
This (6) is said to be proven to exist by an experiment, in which another measurement has been taken between the worlds, and yet all that has happened is that point A of one of the original observations has been moved to a new point C, to give an unrelated result and the measurement has actually been taken between (B reversed which is now C in the non reversed world) and B (non reversed.).
In effect his theory is a slight of hand conjuring trick, a bit like a pea under a nutshell being shifted without anyone noticing it has changed position

What moves faster than light is predictability, the ability to calculate the result of a measurement, even light years away, in a matter of seconds, or even instantly if the calculation has already been made, by the use of inflexibly established, like minded measurement and calculation tools.
This is what the EPR experiment was about, and what it intended to show was that the method of calculating what happens in the quantum world, by using probability, is inadequate to describe the quantum world’s observable and measureable reality.

The quantum world is observable, it’s observations can be measured as points A and B, but the measurements cannot be calculated as a fixed abstract prediction because the tools used to predict its events rely on probability calculations, and not on fixed, established likeminded facts.
Einstein said the quantum world is predictable, Bohr said it is not, and Bell came up with an illusion of his own device to add confusion to their disagreement..

In making calculations today, it seems to be quite easy to ignore points A and B, as Bell’s theory of a non commonsense inequality demonstrates, but without the common sense of observation and the points it establishes, measurement and calculation get lost in the machinations of invented and seemingly established theoretical misunderstandings.
 
  • #174


mayflow said:
Bell simply states that a photon or whatever once it is entangled
with another, supersedes time and space and can instantaneously interreact, no matter the supposed time or space distances, as if time and space do not factually exist, because they most likely don't.
And this way Bell's theorem violates the well accepted theory of relativity and in the same time introduces the mysterious “action on distance” phenomena. Therefore one who introduces (or supports) such “theory” should have a good explanation of this contradiction. Until then it should be treaded as antiscientific or at least as a highly speculative hypothesis only.

However I can’t blame Bell and other with such uncritical acceptance of the “action on distance” concept, because of another famous historical precedent. I mean the “wave function” collapse (the “action on distance” is routed in) that demonstrates that the physical phenomena that define a common sense a logic could be replaced with a ”scientifically sound label” pretending that science accomplished its role in explaining nature.

My main point in this post is that the “action on distance” is just an extreme case of the “wave function collapse” and therefore acceptance or rejection of the Bell’s theorem may depend on our acceptance or rejection of the “wave function collapse.”
 
Last edited:
  • #175


miosim said:
And this way Bell's theorem violates the well accepted theory of relativity and in the same time introduces the mysterious “action on distance” phenomena. Therefore one who introduces (or supports) such “theory” should have a good explanation of this contradiction. Until then it should be treaded as antiscientific or at least as a highly speculative hypothesis only.

You do persist in missing the point, don't you?

Bell's theorem itself is very simple and very robust. It proves that either QM is wrong or the assumption of local realism (which is normally taken as part of Special Relativity) is wrong. It basically boils down to the fact that the differences between sets A and C cannot exceed the sum of the differences between sets A and B and between sets B and C, regardless of the physical models which gave rise to these results.

As the relevant parts of QM are very strongly supported by experiment, this means that it is almost certainly the assumption of local realism which is wrong. This is obviously very disturbing and unexpected, and it does indeed conflict with the principle of relativity. Scientists are therefore interested in trying to understand exactly how QM violates local realism, and whether there might be some underlying inner mechanism that would help to explain how it works.
 
  • #176


Jonathan Scott said:
You do persist in missing the point, don't you?

Bell's theorem itself is very simple and very robust. It proves that either QM is wrong or the assumption of local realism (which is normally taken as part of Special Relativity) is wrong. It basically boils down to the fact that the differences between sets A and C cannot exceed the sum of the differences between sets A and B and between sets B and C, regardless of the physical models which gave rise to these results.

As the relevant parts of QM are very strongly supported by experiment, this means that it is almost certainly the assumption of local realism which is wrong. This is obviously very disturbing and unexpected, and it does indeed conflict with the principle of relativity. Scientists are therefore interested in trying to understand exactly how QM violates local realism, and whether there might be some underlying inner mechanism that would help to explain how it works.

QM is so new to the scene, and Bell's theorem is so awesome, because it breaks old thought barriers. It's not maybe quite understanding how to supersede the speed of light, but it apparently shows it can be done par exellance! :smile:
 
  • #177


Jonathan Scott said:
You do persist in missing the point, don't you?

Bell's theorem itself is very simple and very robust. It proves that either QM is wrong or the assumption of local realism (which is normally taken as part of Special Relativity) is wrong. It basically boils down to the fact that the differences between sets A and C cannot exceed the sum of the differences between sets A and B and between sets B and C, regardless of the physical models which gave rise to these results.

As the relevant parts of QM are very strongly supported by experiment, this means that it is almost certainly the assumption of local realism which is wrong. This is obviously very disturbing and unexpected, and it does indeed conflict with the principle of relativity. Scientists are therefore interested in trying to understand exactly how QM violates local realism, and whether there might be some underlying inner mechanism that would help to explain how it works.

Bell's Theorem is even simpler than you described. It is simply whether:

1. Local Realism holds or not
2. If not hold, then non-locality occurs.

Since Local Realism doesn't hold. Non-local is not necessary. This is because there is nothing to be non-local about. Again the definition of Local Realism (from Wiki) is:

"Local realism is the combination of the principle of locality with the "realistic" assumption that all objects must objectively have a pre-existing value for any possible measurement before the measurement is made. Einstein liked to say that the Moon is "out there" even when no one is observing it."

Bell's Theorem falsifies local realism. But Bohr and company already have in their theoretical structure the nonexistence of local realism. It is only Einstein who wanted to support local realism with hidden variables. But Aspect experiment refuted it and simply supported Bohr original formulation. This is all there is to it about Bell's Theorem. Correct me though if I'm wrong. And why wrong.
 
  • #178
JDoolin said:
I have trouble with the very basics of what is supposedly being measured. I gather that you're basically measuring polarizations, but I'm not sure it makes sense.

The choice the observer has is to set up an apparatus. And apparently he can set up this apparatus in three different ways. One to detect an up or down, one to detect a left or right, and one to detect a forward and backward.

But as far as I can tell the diagrams don't explain physically what they are setting up...just in the abstract--that there are three different variables that can be measured.

But I never see an actual photograph of the physical set-up of the laboratories where they are doing these measurments. I never hear a description of the physical materials that are being used. For instance, is there a you-tube video where you can actually watch people with actual equipment (not just a cartoon, or animations) performing this experiment?

I still don't understand what the experiment entails. All I have direct experience with is polarization. If light comes through polarized lenses, I can either align it left and right, or up and down... But there is no third way I can polarize it. Also, WHEN it's polarized, you don't get "up" or "down" you just get (up/down) I can't polarize it in the direction of the motion. But in the Bell's experiment there are three variables, each with two available settings.

But I don't even know what particles you are talking about, nor the variables involved, nor the description of how to measure those variables. Obviously these experiments have been carried out over and over again, but nobody describes the experiment... Not in any detail anyway. They just talk about what we expect and what the "surprising" results are in an abstract fashion.

I can't tell whether the results are surprising when the experiment isn't even described!
 
  • #179
Aspect's experiments are described in detail in his papers.

An experiment can for example involve a device which generates pairs of photons via a cascade mechanism (which causes the photons to be correlated), some tubes to keep out other sources of light and a pair of observing devices at the ends of the tubes. The observing devices contain devices for splitting polarized light into two separate beams (which could for example simply be a birefringent crystal) with light detection devices (photomultipliers and detectors) to detect photons arriving via each beam. The observing devices can be rotated to different angles around the axis of the tube.

Photons arriving at all four channels (two at each end) are electronically logged. The results are processed afterwards to select relevant events, which are those where a single photon arrived at each end within an interval consistent with the cascade mechanism. Those events are then used to calculate the correlations. Other calculations are done to estimate for example the rate of unmatched single photons and the rate at which those unmatched photons just happened to arrive within the right interval. When all the statistics are sorted out, the result matches QM predictions very well, and in some cases the experiments have been refined to the extent that the raw results violate Bell inequalities without even having to allow for experimental inefficiencies.

Further refinements include inserting a switching device (effectively involving an electronically controlled mirror) that can either let the original photons go to the original observation device or divert it to another observation device configured at a different angle. This device can be switched faster that the light travel time between the ends of the device, ensuring that the results at both ends cannot be determined via communication between the ends.
 
  • #180
DrChinese said:
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0205171

"We use polarization-entangled photon pairs to demonstrate quantum nonlocality in an experiment suitable for advanced undergraduates. The photons are produced by spontaneous parametric downconversion using a violet diode laser and two nonlinear crystals. The polarization state of the photons is tunable. Using an entangled state analogous to that described in the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen ``paradox,'' we demonstrate strong polarization correlations of the entangled photons. Bell's idea of a hidden variable theory is presented by way of an example and compared to the quantum prediction. A test of the Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt version of the Bell inequality finds $S = 2.307 , in clear contradiction of hidden variable theories. The experiments described can be performed in an afternoon. "

Thanks for the link, it has a great quote:
Following a talk by Bohr in 1933, Einstein made a comment, introducing a Gedankenexperiment to question the uncertainty principle. As recounted by Rosenfeld, the argument was this:
“Suppose two particles are set in motion towards each other with the same, very large, momentum, and that they interact with each other for a very short time when they pass at known positions. Consider now an observer who gets hold of one of the particles, far away from the region of interaction, and measures its momentum; then, from the conditions of the experiment, he will obviously be able to deduce the momentum of the other particle. If, however, he chooses to measure the position of the first particle, he will be able to tell where the other particle is.
This is a perfectly correct and straightforward deduction from the principles of quantum mechanics; but is it not very paradoxical? How can the final state of the second particle be influenced by a measurement performed on the first, after all physical interaction has ceased between them?”

In figure 4 it states that a hidden-variable theory will be a straight line. Why is it assumed that any hidden-variable theory would result in a straight line?

FIG. 4: Predicted polarization correlations for a quantum mechanical entangled state (solid curve) and a hidden-variable theory (dashed line).
 
  • #181
JDoolin said:
I still don't understand what the experiment entails. All I have direct experience with is polarization. If light comes through polarized lenses, I can either align it left and right, or up and down... But there is no third way I can polarize it. Also, WHEN it's polarized, you don't get "up" or "down" you just get (up/down) I can't polarize it in the direction of the motion. But in the Bell's experiment there are three variables, each with two available settings.

But I don't even know what particles you are talking about, nor the variables involved, nor the description of how to measure those variables. Obviously these experiments have been carried out over and over again, but nobody describes the experiment... Not in any detail anyway. They just talk about what we expect and what the "surprising" results are in an abstract fashion.

I can't tell whether the results are surprising when the experiment isn't even described!
Apart from orienting your polariser up/down or left/right you can also rotate it to any angle in between the two and it will measure polarisation in that direction. So the 3 variables are the polarisation angle of the incoming light and the 2 angles of the polarisers used to measure that light later on. In a purely classical world, the intensity of light going through the polariser will depend on the angle between the underlying polarisation of the light and the angle of the polariser, e.g. if the angle is 45 degrees, you would expect a certain percentage of the photons to go through and you would expect this to be independent between the two different polarisers at opposite ends of the set-up (the measurement should only depend on the properties of the photon itself and not on what the results of measurements on other photons elsewhere are).

The 'surprising' QM effect is that if you do this experiment with entangled photons and using the same polariser setting of 45 degrees as above on both sides, although each photon individually would still have the same chance of going through either polariser as before, the 2 entangled photons will either both go through their respective polariser or neither of them will - ignoring experimental noise etc.

This result alone could still be explained by adding hidden variables associated with the photons to the classical model. But by going through the other combinations with different angles between the two polarisers, you can find that the combination of all the QM predictions when taken together are inconsistent with Bell's inequalities - which are a more general statistical/information theoretical statement on what kind of correlations between the outcomes on the two sides are possible based on the assumption that each side of the experiment has no prior information about the outcome of the other side.
 
  • #182
miosim said:
Sorry but I cannot answer this question because 1) and 2) are two “technical” for me
Really? Could you say which sentences you find too technical? And if you can't understand 1) and 2) which are really pretty simple for anyone who is familiar with the basics of special relativity and electromagnetism, then it's completely absurd that you claim to understand Bell and see flaws in his thinking (you clearly don't understand the notion of "local realism" if you don't understand my 1 and 2), this would be like someone who doesn't understand algebra claiming to find flaws in the proof of a calculus theorem.
miosim said:
and the comments of Arthur Fine are too gossip-like for me to trust him. When I asked you to provide quotes from Einstein's I expect a direct Einstein’s writing and not an interpretation.
Um, did you actually read my post or did you just skim it? The whole first section was from a book that quoted several paragraphs from Einstein's own letter to Schrödinger about the two-box thought-experiment, then I gave my analysis of what he meant which related his comments to my own 1) and 2), only after all that did I quote Fine's comments.
miosim said:
By the way, I don’t believe that a knowledge about the characteristic (spin, polarization, etc.) of one particle yields the complement characteristic of the the correlated particle
According to QM, knowledge of some characteristic of one particle, like whether it's spin-up or spin-down on a particular axis, can allow you to predict with 100% certainty what result we'll get if we do the same measurement on a second entangled particle. Are you disagreeing with QM, or are you just disagreeing that there must have been local properties of the second particle that predetermined what result it would give immediately before measurement, or are you arguing something else? Anyway if you disagree that there were such local properties of the second particle that predetermined its result for that measurement, you are disagreeing with both Einstein and Bell. Of course you are free to disagree with them, but if so there doesn't seem to be any meaningful sense in which your own beliefs are "local realist" ones. And remember, Bell's proof was only meant to show a conflict between local realism and QM, not to say you couldn't have some non local realist model for what's really going on in QM (Bohmian mechanics would be an example of such a non-local realist model).
miosim said:
“Sealed box” and other illustrative examples like Alice, Bob etc. are adding one more layer of interpretation and misinterpretation and in my opinion their use may cause more problems than help.
The sealed box was Einstein's own analogy, again read the beginning of the post that quotes from Einstein's own letter. If you aren't willing to deal with analogies but also are unwilling to try to understand explanations that are the slightest bit "technical" like my 1) and 2), then I don't see any way to try to explain the concept of "local realism" to you, you need to either change your attitude towards these types of explanations or just give up all attempts to understand either local realism or Bell's argument.
miosim said:
Indeed it seems that Bell was sympathetic to Einstein ideas. However the passion with which Bell proclaimed impossibility of local realism and existence on non-locality (as inevitable) tell me that his conclusion was predetermined by strong influence of Copenhagen Interpretation.
You apparently don't understand the most basic aspects of Bell's argument or the meaning of local realism, so you look completely foolish making these pompous pronouncements about where his conclusions came from. And just for your information, Bell wasn't in the least bit sympathetic to Copenhagen, he much preferred nonlocal hidden-variable theories which try to give an objective picture of what's really going on with quantum systems when they're not being measured, like Bohmian mechanics which I mentioned above.
 
  • #183
Jonathan Scott said:
Aspect's experiments are described in detail in his papers.

An experiment can for example involve a device which generates pairs of photons via a cascade mechanism (which causes the photons to be correlated), some tubes to keep out other sources of light and a pair of observing devices at the ends of the tubes. The observing devices contain devices for splitting polarized light into two separate beams (which could for example simply be a birefringent crystal) with light detection devices (photomultipliers and detectors) to detect photons arriving via each beam. The observing devices can be rotated to different angles around the axis of the tube.

Photons arriving at all four channels (two at each end) are electronically logged. The results are processed afterwards to select relevant events, which are those where a single photon arrived at each end within an interval consistent with the cascade mechanism. Those events are then used to calculate the correlations. Other calculations are done to estimate for example the rate of unmatched single photons and the rate at which those unmatched photons just happened to arrive within the right interval. When all the statistics are sorted out, the result matches QM predictions very well, and in some cases the experiments have been refined to the extent that the raw results violate Bell inequalities without even having to allow for experimental inefficiencies.

Further refinements include inserting a switching device (effectively involving an electronically controlled mirror) that can either let the original photons go to the original observation device or divert it to another observation device configured at a different angle. This device can be switched faster that the light travel time between the ends of the device, ensuring that the results at both ends cannot be determined via communication between the ends.

~So this cascade mechanism... Is it similar to the "Stimulated Emission of Radiation" that goes on inside a laser? Do the two photons come out in exactly opposite directions?

~There would be some doubt as to whether two photons were really coming from the same event, or were just coincidentally happened at the same time. I think you could overcome this doubt via a statistical argument.

~If I follow one beam, if I understand correctly, it comes upon a birefringent crystal. I would expect it would have three possible outcomes; one is to reflect off the surface, two and three are to polarize according to the crystal structure and pass on through. If it reflects off the surface, of course, you don't get a reading on both photons, so it's not counted. (Edit: This possibility seems missing in the scratch-lottery-ticket analogy. When you scratch, you could get a lemon or a cherry, but shouldn't there also be the possibility that the lottery ticket just disintegrates in your hand and is thrown out of the experiment?)

~At the end, if the photon goes through the crystal, it ends up at one of two photomultipliers. Based on which photomultiplier it goes into you can tell which of the available polarizations the photon has.

~the idea that the result of this test could be either "up" or "down" is misleading, since the two possible results of polarization are not 180 degrees from each other, (nor are they opposite) but 90 degrees from one another.

~Your choice of "what" to measure is determined by what angle you place the birefringent crystal.

So if I have this much right, (if not, let me know) then what are your set-ups with the bi-refringent crystals? I know there are angles involved, but are you just using angles like 0, 120, and 240 degrees around the axis (parallel to the light ray), or are you also rotating along an axis perpendicular to the light ray, or are you using different faces of the birefringent crystal?
 
Last edited:
  • #184
JDoolin said:
~So this cascade mechanism... Is it similar to the "Stimulated Emission of Radiation" that goes on inside a laser? Do the two photons come out in exactly opposite directions?

The cascade mechanism involves pumping energy into an atom and then letting it decay via a pair of photons, so there is some resemblance. I don't expect the photons would come out in exactly opposite directions in general, but enough of them would do so to make the experiment work.

JDoolin said:
~There would be some doubt as to whether two photons were really coming from the same event, or were just coincidentally happened at the same time. I think you could overcome this doubt via a statistical argument.

Yes, this is checked via the statistics for unmatched photons.

JDoolin said:
~If I follow one beam, if I understand correctly, it comes upon a birefringent crystal. I would expect it would have three possible outcomes; one is to reflect off the surface, two and three are to polarize according to the crystal structure and pass on through. If it reflects off the surface, of course, you don't get a reading on both photons, so it's not counted. (Edit: This possibility seems missing in the scratch-lottery-ticket analogy. When you scratch, you could get a lemon or a cherry, but shouldn't there also be the possibility that the lottery ticket just disintegrates in your hand and is thrown out of the experiment?)

This is true, and it is very difficult to eliminate this loophole with photons, as non-detection is always an option. Other equivalent experiments have been done involving pairs of atoms in which non-detection is not an option, but in those experiments there are other loopholes. If QM was devious enough to exploit different loopholes in different cases, which of course seems very implausible, then I don't think experiments have been done which would eliminate all possible loopholes in the same experiment.

JDoolin said:
~At the end, if the photon goes through the crystal, it ends up at one of two photomultipliers. Based on which photomultiplier it goes into you can tell which of the available polarizations the photon has.

~the idea that the result of this test could be either "up" or "down" is misleading, since the two possible results of polarization are not 180 degrees from each other, (nor are they opposite) but 90 degrees from one another.
The "up"/"down" terminology is from the equivalent fermion experiment, observing spins. For photons, an example result might be H/V for Horizontal/Vertical polarization, but I think that in practice most experiments use left/right cyclic polarization.

JDoolin said:
~Your choice of "what" to measure is determined by what angle you place the birefringent crystal.

So if I have this much right, (if not, let me know) then what are your set-ups with the bi-refringent crystals? I know there are angles involved, but are you just using angles like 0, 120, and 240 degrees around the axis (parallel to the light ray), or are you also rotating along an axis perpendicular to the light ray, or are you using different faces of the birefringent crystal?

I think again that we have a mixture of the two versions of the experiment here. The whole observation device (including beam splitter - I don't recall whether it really is a birefringent crystal or what) is physically rotated to different angles around the axis. For photon polarization, the interesting angles are 22.5 degrees either way of a reference direction at either end. In practice, one also tries the whole experiment with both ends rotated to different angles to see whether the set-up is rotationally uniform, as it should be.

The interesting sets of results with photons are with both ends aligned to get perfect correlation, one end turned by 22.5 degrees (which should cause approximately 15% of results to be different), the other end turned the other way by 22.5 degrees (again changing 15% of results) and finally with both ends turned, so the angle between them is 45 degrees and 50% of the results should be different, for which Bell's Theorem tells us there is no possible local realistic explanation, as 15%+15% cannot exceed 30%.
 
  • #185


Jonathan Scott said:
You do persist in missing the point, don't you?
Bell's theorem itself is very simple and very robust. It proves that either QM is wrong or the assumption of local realism (which is normally taken as part of Special Relativity) is wrong.
Or you are wrong, because nobody as I know, including Einstein didn't claim that QM is wrong, but incomplete only.

You probably missed my main objection to Bell's theorem that it is based on incorrect initial conditions that is the Bell's misinterpretation of Einstein's "local realism" . It is obvious to me that the Bell's model of the "local realism" is wrong, because it violates the very basic principle of Einstein's argument related to interpretation of QM but not altering its result. And one don't have wait for the "proof" provided by Bell to understand the obvious difference between QM and Bell's "local realism". As soon Bell (or anyone else) found that his "very reasonable" (as he called it) model of "local realism" contradicts with prediction of QM Bell should stop and go back to the drawing board to find out what is wrong with his model.
 
  • #186


miosim said:
It is obvious to me that the Bell's model of the "local realism" is wrong, because it violates the very basic principle of Einstein's argument related to interpretation of QM but not altering its result.
And I've already pointed out that this is a completely silly argument since Einstein had no way of knowing that there was a conflict between his concept of local realism (which was identical to the concept Bell used) and QM, since Bell hadn't proved that when Einstein was alive. I made this point in two previous posts and you never responded, are you just ignoring it?

As an analogy, you might as well say that since Ptolemy didn't intend for his astronomical system to conflict with any astronomical observations, and yet we now have observations that clearly show the Earth revolves around the Sun, this "proves" that Ptolemy couldn't have really believed the Sun revolves around the Earth! Hopefully you can see that this is argument is nonsense because Ptolemy didn't know that after his time we would find a conflict between astronomical observations and Earth-centered astronomical systems.
 
  • #187
JesseM said:
According to QM, knowledge of some characteristic of one particle, like whether it's spin-up or spin-down on a particular axis, can allow you to predict with 100% certainty what result we'll get if we do the same measurement on a second entangled particle. Are you disagreeing with QM...
I am disagree with "... 100% certainty" regardless it is predicted by QM or EPR model. Please prove me wrong and provide the experiment(s) where both (individual) correlated photons were proved to have 100% correlation. The difference I am expecting is within the principle of uncertainly (similar to particle's position/momentum uncertainly). We may discuss the details of this result later.
 
  • #188
miosim said:
I am disagree with "... 100% certainty" regardless it is predicted by QM or EPR model.
My statement was about what is predicted by QM, not an empirical claim. Read it again:
According to QM, knowledge of some characteristic of one particle, like whether it's spin-up or spin-down on a particular axis, can allow you to predict with 100% certainty what result we'll get if we do the same measurement on a second entangled particle.
Of course QM might turn out to be wrong, but this isn't relevant to Bell's theorem (and to Einstein's EPR argument), since Bell's theorem is just dealing with the issue of whether the theory of QM is compatible with an underlying local realist model. Also, as I pointed out in my [post=3275052]last post to billschnieder[/post], Bell did derive a more general inequality known as the CHSH inequality which would still be expected to hold in a local realist theory which does not assume perfect correlations with the same detector setting.
miosim said:
The difference I am expected is within the principle of uncertainly (similar to particle's position/momentum uncertainly). We may discuss the details of this result later.
You should really learn the basics of the areas of physics you're talking about instead of confidently spouting nonsense (your posts seem like a perfect example of the Dunning-Kruger effect), the uncertainty principle only applies to non-commuting operators like position and momentum, in QM there is no uncertainty relation if you measure the same variable twice in quick succession, or if you measure the same variable for two particles which are entangled in that variable.
 
  • #189
miosim said:
It is obvious to me that the Bell's model of the "local realism" is wrong, because it violates the very basic principle of Einstein's argument related to interpretation of QM but not altering its result.
JesseM said:
And I've already pointed out that this is a completely silly argument since Einstein had no way of knowing that there was a conflict between his concept of local realism (which was identical to the concept Bell used) and QM, since Bell hadn't proved that when Einstein was alive. I made this point in two previous posts and you never responded, are you just ignoring it?
It would be a valid point if Bell reproduces Einstein’s concept without any deviations. Instead Bell’s model lacks the major requirement for Einstein’s argument; do not contradict with the predicted result of QM. Bell doesn’t need Einstein to be around to adhere with this basic requirement.
If Bell couldn’t adhere with this requirements, than Bell’s theorem should be exclusively about (his) impossibility to construct such model and not about influence over a distance.

Regarding a possibility to have a model that satisfies both Einstein’s realism and the prediction of QM, I wonder if we can modify the Bell’s model for the Aspect’s experiment as follows:
The EPR correlated photons have 100% predictable polarization before interacting with polarizer, but polarizer rotates this polarization per Malus’ law (as cos^2). Would this model produce the result in agreement with Aspect’s experiment?
JesseM said:
You should really learn the basics of the areas of physics you're talking about instead of confidently spouting nonsense (your posts seem like a perfect example of the Dunning-Kruger effect), the uncertainty principle only applies to non-commuting operators like position and momentum, in QM there is no uncertainty relation if you measure the same variable twice in quick succession, or if you measure the same variable for two particles which are entangled in that variable.
You are right that “I … confidently spouting nonsense”. Thank you for providing links.
JesseM said:
According to QM, knowledge of some characteristic of one particle, like whether it's spin-up or spin-down on a particular axis, can allow you to predict with 100% certainty what result we'll get if we do the same measurement on a second entangled particle. Are you disagreeing with QM, or are you just disagreeing that there must have been local properties of the second particle that predetermined what result it would give immediately before measurement, or are you arguing something else? Anyway if you disagree that there were such local properties of the second particle that predetermined its result for that measurement, you are disagreeing with both Einstein and Bell. Of course you are free to disagree with them, but if so there doesn't seem to be any meaningful sense in which your own beliefs are "local realist" ones. And remember, Bell's proof was only meant to show a conflict between local realism and QM, not to say you couldn't have some non local realist model for what's really going on in QM (Bohmian mechanics would be an example of such a non-local realist model).
Sorry, I miss-read your question first time. To have a complete answer I would need to explore my beliefs that are indeed different from QM and EPR. However my beliefs aren’t relevant to my arguments against Bell theorem and I don’t want to derail this thread. Therefore I shouldn’t mention my disagreement with a “100% certainty.” My fault.

P.S.
Regarding Bell's proof that “..was only meant to show a conflict between local realism and QM…” I am increasingly uncomfortable with the label of “local realism”. You pointed few times to your definition of “local realism” 1) and 2), but do you have Bell’s and Einstein’s definitions (in theirs own words)?
 
Last edited:
  • #190
miosim said:
It would be a valid point if Bell reproduces Einstein’s concept without any deviations. Instead Bell’s model lacks the major requirement for Einstein’s argument; do not contradict with the predicted result of QM. Bell doesn’t need Einstein to be around to adhere with this basic requirement.
But Einstein didn't know his concept of a local and objective model conflicted with QM in the first place! He thought it could be possible to come up with such a model that does not contradict QM, but he was wrong! Do you really not get this?

Einstein: I'm hoping for a theory which has features X and Y, and which reproduces the predictions of QM.

Bell: Here is a proof that any theory with features X and Y must automatically conflict with QM.

What miosim says: But Einstein required a theory which "reproduces the predictions of QM", if Bell's proof shows a conflict between X and Y and QM, that just proves that X and Y were not actually what Einstein meant!

What Einstein would have said: Oh, I didn't realize there was a basic conflict between X and Y and QM. Very interesting, unless QM's predictions are disproven I guess this means I must abandon the hope for a theory with features X and Y.

If you still don't get why Einstein's realism could be identical to Bell's realism, could you address my Ptolemy analogy? Do you agree that Ptolemy designed his astronomical models with the assumption that they should fit with astronomical observations? Do you therefore think the fact that we now know an Earth centered system doesn't fit with astronomical observations is proof that any summary of Ptolemy's system which states that the Sun revolves around the Earth must not really be what Ptolemy had in mind?
miosim said:
Regarding a possibility to have a model that satisfies both Einstein’s realism and the prediction of QM, I wonder if we can modify the Bell’s model for the Aspect’s experiment as follows:
The EPR correlated photons have 100% predictable polarization before interacting with polarizer, but polarizer rotates this polarization per Malus’ law (as cos^2).
Malus' law has nothing to do with "rotating the polarization", it involves reducing the intensity of a polarized beam by cos^2 of the angle between the beam and the polarizer's angle. If you want to fantasize that the polarizers rotate the polarization in a deterministic way that's fine, but then you need to specify how that altered polarization determines which of two results we get (going through the polarizer or deflected by it). If the final angle determines the result in a deterministic way, then if both photons end up with the same final angle you can have 100% correlation, but in this case the original angle predetermines what the final angle will be and what the final angle will be, so you still have each photon having local properties that predetermine what response they will give to any measurement, so Bell's theorem still applies.
miosim said:
Sorry, I miss-read your question first time. To have a complete answer I would need to explore my beliefs that are indeed different from QM and EPR. However my beliefs aren’t relevant to my arguments against Bell theorem and I don’t want to derail this thread. Therefore I shouldn’t mention my disagreement with a “100% certainty.” My fault.
OK, so think about Einstein's box analogy again. Obviously the simplest way to explain the 100% correlation between the results of opening each box is to say that prior to being opened, each box had "hidden" local properties that predetermined their results--one has a ball hidden inside it, one is empty. Einstein said it would be "absurd" to think that there was no definite truth about what was in each box before they were opened. And since he was using this analogy to specifically explain the ideas that he had wanted the EPR paper to explain, do you disagree that he thought the same way about perfect correlations in QM? That he thought, for example, that if two entangled particles are 100% guaranteed to have the same magnitude of momentum, that must mean that even before being measured they both had "hidden" local properties that predetermined they would give that result if their momentum was measured?
miosim said:
P.S.
Regarding Bell's proof that “..was only meant to show a conflict between local realism and QM…” I am increasingly uncomfortable with the label of “local realism”. You pointed few times to your definition of “local realism” 1) and 2), but do you have Bell’s and Einstein’s definitions (in theirs own words)?
Neither of them used the exact term "local realism", it's a later term intended to summarize the type of theories that Einstein and Bell were discussing. Bell did use the similar term "local causality", and if you look at the links and discussion I gave of the La nouvelle cuisine paper in [post=3248153]this post[/post] you can see how Bell assumes "local beables" which are the same concept as my "local facts" in 1) (also see Bell's paper The Theory of Local Beables), and you can also see how he assumes the value of local beables can only be influenced by events in their past light cone, identical to my 2) (you said my discussion was too "technical" for you, do you understand what a "light cone" is? If not you could start here). As for Einstein, it seems he never gave any systematic exposition, but again read the direct quotes about his two-box explanation for perfect correlations in QM in [post=3270631]this post[/post], and Bell also quotes some other relevant comments of Einstein's on p. 7-8 of this paper (starting with the paragraph that begins "If one asks what, irrespective of quantum mechanics, is characteristic of the world of ideas of physics...")
 
  • #191
Jonathan Scott said:
The cascade mechanism involves pumping energy into an atom and then letting it decay via a pair of photons, so there is some resemblance. I don't expect the photons would come out in exactly opposite directions in general, but enough of them would do so to make the experiment work.



Yes, this is checked via the statistics for unmatched photons.



This is true, and it is very difficult to eliminate this loophole with photons, as non-detection is always an option. Other equivalent experiments have been done involving pairs of atoms in which non-detection is not an option, but in those experiments there are other loopholes. If QM was devious enough to exploit different loopholes in different cases, which of course seems very implausible, then I don't think experiments have been done which would eliminate all possible loopholes in the same experiment.


The "up"/"down" terminology is from the equivalent fermion experiment, observing spins. For photons, an example result might be H/V for Horizontal/Vertical polarization, but I think that in practice most experiments use left/right cyclic polarization.



I think again that we have a mixture of the two versions of the experiment here. The whole observation device (including beam splitter - I don't recall whether it really is a birefringent crystal or what) is physically rotated to different angles around the axis. For photon polarization, the interesting angles are 22.5 degrees either way of a reference direction at either end. In practice, one also tries the whole experiment with both ends rotated to different angles to see whether the set-up is rotationally uniform, as it should be.

The interesting sets of results with photons are with both ends aligned to get perfect correlation, one end turned by 22.5 degrees (which should cause approximately 15% of results to be different), the other end turned the other way by 22.5 degrees (again changing 15% of results) and finally with both ends turned, so the angle between them is 45 degrees and 50% of the results should be different, for which Bell's Theorem tells us there is no possible local realistic explanation, as 15%+15% cannot exceed 30%.

~I take this as a correction of post 2 in this thread, where you use 45 and 90 degrees instead of 22.5 and 45 degrees. These new figures are consistent with Malus Law, where cos^2(22.5)=.85, and cos^2(45) = .5


~You could get the same math as above with two polarizers. If you place two polarizers at 22.5 degrees, 85% of the light that gets through the first polarizer will get through the second polarizer. If you place them at 45 degrees, 50% of the light that gets through the first polarizer gets through the second polarizer. In each case, you shouldn't ignore the fact that the first polarizer blocks a significant portion of the light. It also forces the light that goes through into polarization in the same direction. It's only with the second polarizer that you get to apply Malus Law.

It seems to me that in this version of photon entanglement, the results are exactly as should be expected from polarization with a "hidden variable..." No, not even hidden; a variable that you just don't happen to know. The variable is the angle of polarization which is a continuous variable, with some value between 0 and 360 degrees, and a variable which can be changed (if it is not blocked) by running it through a polarizer

But of course, we're going to run into trouble explaining this result if we insist on treating the polarization as a hidden three dimensional binary variable with some value of
{000,001,010,011,100,101,110,111}.

~I don't believe nondetection is as much of an issue as I was thinking before. (Edit: a polarizer either blocks or does not block the light. With birefringent crystal, it appears to pass just about everything, just at different angles.)
 
Last edited:
  • #192
edguy99 said:
In figure 4 it states that a hidden-variable theory will be a straight line. Why is it assumed that any hidden-variable theory would result in a straight line?

FIG. 4: Predicted polarization correlations for a quantum mechanical entangled state (solid curve) and a hidden-variable theory (dashed line).
I don't think the assumption of local hidden variables actually uniquely implies a straight line, rather I think that straight line is just meant to be the closest a local hidden variables theory can get to the curve predicted by quantum mechanics...I don't really understand the details of where they get the straight line, but see [post=3240160]post #20[/post] for some comments by DrChinese that seem to suggest this (perhaps he can comment here and clarify this issue?)
 
  • #193
JDoolin said:
~I take this as a correction of post 2 in this thread, where you use 45 and 90 degrees instead of 22.5 and 45 degrees. These new figures are consistent with Malus Law, where cos^2(22.5)=.85, and cos^2(45) = .5

In that post, I was describing the case of two spin-1/2 particles, which works in exactly the same way except that the angles are doubled. In that case the beam-splitter is a Stern-Gerlach device.

(People often use electrons as an example, but I've heard that this can't be made to work in practice. Atoms can however be used.)

JDoolin said:
~You could get the same math as above with two polarizers. If you place two polarizers at 22.5 degrees, 85% of the light that gets through the first polarizer will get through the second polarizer. If you place them at 45 degrees, 50% of the light that gets through the first polarizer gets through the second polarizer. In each case, you shouldn't ignore the fact that the first polarizer blocks a significant portion of the light. It also forces the light that goes through into polarization in the same direction. It's only with the second polarizer that you get to apply Malus Law.

That would work for single photons passing in succession through two polarizers. It would also apply to pairs of photons emitted from a common source if the initial state happened to be polarized in the direction of one of the two observation devices (as in that case, that one would give 100% correlation with the source and the other would be determined by Malus' law). However, if you change BOTH observations to some other angle relative to the initial angle, then unless there is magic feedback from the observation devices to the source there is no way for the direction of polarization to match one of the devices in all four cases (both same, turn one, turn other, turn both).

People occasionally spot that it is possible to produce a local realistic model which will reproduce Malus' law and match QM if instead of turning both, you simply turn one device twice as much. However, that is simply equivalent to the QM special case where the emitted particles are prepared with polarization aligned with the initial observation devices, and does not cover the general case addressed by Bell's Theorem.
 
  • #194
JesseM said:
I don't think the assumption of local hidden variables actually uniquely implies a straight line, rather I think that straight line is just meant to be the closest a local hidden variables theory can get to the curve predicted by quantum mechanics...I don't really understand the details of where they get the straight line, but see [post=3240160]post #20[/post] for some comments by DrChinese that seem to suggest this (perhaps he can comment here and clarify this issue?)

Regarding http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0205171 and also the DrChinese post here again showing that LR predicts a straight line. It is true that a spinning ball that is not allowed to have any other properties (ie a second direction of spin as in precession) in which you measure every particle will be a straight line, but lots of other particles will have a curved line if not all the particles reach the detectors. From the discussion in the linked article, it appears they are only checking the particles (ie photons) that reach the detectors.

An example of such a particle is posted https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=489944".
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #195
I recall seeing explanations of Bell's inequality that have nothing to do with probability or physical experiments. It was explained as a simple consequence of classifying a set of objects with respect to several properties. It was illustrated it by an inventory office supplies or something that mundane. Can anyone provide a link to that type of explanation?
 
  • #196
Stephen Tashi said:
I recall seeing explanations of Bell's inequality that have nothing to do with probability or physical experiments. It was explained as a simple consequence of classifying a set of objects with respect to several properties. It was illustrated it by an inventory office supplies or something that mundane. Can anyone provide a link to that type of explanation?
Sure, see here for example. But this type of explanation doesn't remove the need to think about probability or the meaning of local realism, because you need local realism to derive the conclusion that each particle must have an identical set of properties that predetermine what result they will give for each possible detector setting (in order to explain why they always give the same result when measured with the same setting), and then you need the assumption that the choice of detector settings isn't statistically correlated with the properties of the particles in order to go from this:

Number(A, not B) + Number(B, not C) greater than or equal to Number(A, not C)

To this:

(Number of trials where particle 1 measured for property A and particle 2 measured for property B, and particle 1 found to have A and 2 found to have not-B)

+

(Number of trials where particle 1 measured for property B and particle 2 measured for property C, and particle 1 found to have B and 2 found to have not-C)

greater than or equal to

(Number of trials where particle 1 measured for property A and particle 2 measured for property C, and particle 1 found to have A and 2 found to have not-C)
 
  • #198
edguy99 said:
Regarding http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0205171 and also the DrChinese post here again showing that LR predicts a straight line.
But in that post DrChinese doesn't say LR automatically predicts a straight line, he says that a straight line is the closest a LR theory can come to the quantum prediction:
The LR(Theta) line, in blue, is a straight line ranging from 1 at 0 degrees to 0 at 90 degrees. This matches the values that an LR would need to come closest to the predictions of QM, shown in Red. Other LR theories might posit different functions, but if they are out there then they will lead to even greater differences as compared to QM. Keep in mind that the QM predicted values match experiment closely.
As for the paper you linked to, they just say the straight line is a prediction for "a hidden-variable theory", not "all hidden-variable theories". They also say on p. 6 that "our HVT is very simple", implying that one could come up with more complex HV theories that give different predictions, although they note Bell's result that no local HVT could match the predictions of QM.
edguy99 said:
It is true that a spinning ball that is not allowed to have any other properties (ie a second direction of spin as in precession) in which you measure every particle will be a straight line, but lots of other particles will have a curved line if not all the particles reach the detectors. From the discussion in the linked article, it appears they are only checking the particles (ie photons) that reach the detectors.

An example of such a particle is posted https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=489944".
It seems like in that thread you are talking about a model where certain particles have properties that make them "defective" for particular measurement settings, if so I commented briefly on such models at the end of [post=3270631]this post[/post]:
I should also note that Fine thinks there is some possibility of getting around Bell's theorem by use of a "prism model" in which some particles are intrinsically "defective" for certain types of measurements, so if we try to measure a given property (like spin in a particular direction) some fraction of the particles just won't show up in our measurements and thus won't be included in our dataset, which means the choice of what to measure can no longer be considered independent of the properties that the particle had immediately before measurement in our dataset (if this is unclear, billschnieder explained this type of model in terms of my own lotto card analogy in posts [post=2767632]113[/post] and [post=2767828]115[/post] on an older thread). Bell does assume in most of his proofs that there is no correlation between particle properties before measurement and the choice of detector setting, but it seems to me that these prism models would be themselves contradict the predictions of QM, so they aren't really relevant to a theoretical proof showing that local realism is incompatible with QM. But in terms of the possibility that something like this could be true experimentally, I think this loophole is just one version of what's called the"detection efficency loophole", and there are modified versions of Bell inequalities which take into account that not all particle pairs are successfully measured, see here. There have been Bell tests with ions that managed to close the detector efficiency loophole, see [post=2851208]this post[/post], although they didn't simultaneously close the locality loophole (though experiments with photons have closed that one, none have yet closed both simultaneously. It seems pretty unlikely that we could have a non-contrived-looking local realist theory where both types of loopholes were being exploited at once, though.)
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #199
edguy99 said:
Regarding http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0205171 and also the DrChinese post here again showing that LR predicts a straight line. It is true that a spinning ball that is not allowed to have any other properties (ie a second direction of spin as in precession) in which you measure every particle will be a straight line, but lots of other particles will have a curved line if not all the particles reach the detectors. From the discussion in the linked article, it appears they are only checking the particles (ie photons) that reach the detectors...

Yes, there are many graphs possible for LR theories. But if you follow the EPR constraint that you always get the same answer at the same angle settings, there is basically just the straight line one as a possibility. (There are more, but they are even further from the Bell test results.)

The example posted by edguy99 fails to meet the basic standards. (It is a bit hard to follow because something called "loss of momentum" is thrown in. While hypothetical effects are nice as an "escape" to Bell, they always fail when you follow the example through.) You still, for example, need to deliver results that match the QM predictions and this model won't do that. As a proof of that, all you need to do is consider the angle settings 0, 120 and 240 degrees. The 0/45/90 degree examples are not meaningful because simple models can approach these predictions.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #200
Jonathan Scott said:
In that post, I was describing the case of two spin-1/2 particles, which works in exactly the same way except that the angles are doubled. In that case the beam-splitter is a Stern-Gerlach device.

(People often use electrons as an example, but I've heard that this can't be made to work in practice. Atoms can however be used.)



That would work for single photons passing in succession through two polarizers. It would also apply to pairs of photons emitted from a common source if the initial state happened to be polarized in the direction of one of the two observation devices (as in that case, that one would give 100% correlation with the source and the other would be determined by Malus' law). However, if you change BOTH observations to some other angle relative to the initial angle, then unless there is magic feedback from the observation devices to the source there is no way for the direction of polarization to match one of the devices in all four cases (both same, turn one, turn other, turn both).

People occasionally spot that it is possible to produce a local realistic model which will reproduce Malus' law and match QM if instead of turning both, you simply turn one device twice as much. However, that is simply equivalent to the QM special case where the emitted particles are prepared with polarization aligned with the initial observation devices, and does not cover the general case addressed by Bell's Theorem.

On further thought, I realized that if the experiment worked to my expectation, then even when the two crystals are perfectly aligned, you would not get perfect agreement. I think this is what you are referring to that I boldfaced above. If the source creates photon pairs of a random polarization with "uniform distribution" then most of the time the photon would not be aligned with either polarizer. For instance if the polarization was 0, or 90 degrees, there would be a 100% agreement, but if the polarization was 45 degrees off, there would only be a 50% agreement. I made up a spreadsheet to take the avereage agreement of all angles from 0 to 357 every 3 degree increment, and found that at best, you can expect a 75% agreement rate. (There's probably a more elegant method of doing this with calculus).

By this method, I also got these values:
Perfectly aligned crystals: 75% agreement
22.5 degrees off: 68% agreement
45 degrees off: 50% agreement


But if I understand correctly, the actual experiment yields:
Perfectly aligned crystals: 100% agreement
22.5 degrees off: 85% agreement
45 degrees off: 50% agreement

...and as you said, that would be "equivalent to the QM special case where the emitted particles are prepared with polarization aligned with [one of] the initial observation devices."

Almost equivalent, but not quite... if the polarizations were aligned, the two would always agree the same way. Both would always be vertical, for instance. If the polarizations are not aligned, then you'd have both always agreeing, but horizontal half the time and vertical the other half the time.
 

Attachments

Similar threads

Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
47
Views
5K
Replies
11
Views
3K
Replies
53
Views
5K
Replies
36
Views
5K
Replies
333
Views
17K
Back
Top