stevendaryl said:
In light of the equivalence principle, it's the only sensible way to define it.
The local definition, in itself, has nothing to do with the equivalence principle. It has to do with the physical meaning of the metric in SR. Locally, if I want to set up an SR inertial frame, the only way I have to figure out which curves are the "straight lines"--curves of constant ##x, y, z##--in that frame is to use freely falling worldlines. Those are the only ones that are locally picked out physically. So if I am restricted to using local measurements only, using the freely falling worldlines as the geodesics of the metric is the only option.
So if I want to construct a theory that says "the metric is Minkowski", but picks out
different curves as the "straight lines"--curves which are not freely falling worldlines--then the only way I can pick out
which curves these are is to use some non-local criterion. In Schild's case, the criterion is to pick the worldlines that are "at rest" with respect to observers very far away, as verified by round-trip light signals. But there's no
local way to tell which worldlines those are; there's no
local way to say, the worldline with
this particular proper acceleration is the "straight line" in this particular local region of spacetime. Only the nonlocal measurement can tell us that.
The equivalence principle amounts to the further claim, in the light of the above, that we should
not use any such nonlocal criterion at all--we should insist on only using local measurements to pick out the "straight lines" (geodesics) of the metric. But I'm not saying that here. I'm only saying that,
if we are going to say the metric is Minkowski but have some "straight lines" that are not freely falling worldlines--which we must do in the presence of gravity--then we have to use a nonlocal criterion to pick out which worldlines are the "straight lines", because there is no local way to do it.