I Entanglement swapping, monogamy, and realism

kurt101
Messages
285
Reaction score
35
TL;DR Summary
I have some questions about entanglement swapping, realistic interpretations, and the monogamy entanglement argument that @DrChinese has been making that I want to ask about in an I-level thread.
For this discussion I would like to continue referring to the entangled pairs 1,2 and 3,4 as we have in previous discussions. For background on this discussion refer to post-selection: pre-existing correlations or action at a distance where @DrChinese describes the entanglement swapping experiments and his monogamy argument.

I think the entanglement swapping experiment is compatible with realistic interpretations that respect cause and effect such as argued in this paper http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9427/1/Delayed_Choice.pdf (Go to chapter 4 for the argument on the entanglement swapping experiment)

This paper is not disputing entanglement between 1 & 4 in the case where the BSM test is done prior to 1 & 4 being measured. I think it is accurate to say the paper and @DrChinese are in agreement here. And in the context of a cause and effect realistic interpretation, I don't see how anyone could argue for a coincidental explanation for this case, because you can always change the way you measure 1, 4 after knowing the result of the BSM test and so you have a cause and effect problem if you are suggesting a coincidental explanation for this case.

Where I think @DrChinese and the paper disagree is the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured. In a realistic interpretation with cause and effect, the cause can't happen after the effect. So while nobody disputes that 1 & 4 have an entangled correlation, the realistic explanation for the entanglement of 1 & 4 is one that requires coincidence between 1 & 4 versus causation; in other words 1 & 4 happened to have just the right initial states where their measurements resulted in an entangled correlation and a change to 2 & 3 so that the BSM test showed maximum entanglement.

It is my understanding that @DrChinese argument using monogamy of entanglement is in dispute with this second case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured. I have read many definitions and gone through the proof that @DrChinese provided and I don't see how this second case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 is being measured is in violation of monogamy.

Taking one of the definitions that @DrChinese has previously referred to from https://www.quantiki.org/wiki/monogamy-entanglement
''Monogamy ''' is one of the most fundamental properties of entanglement and can, in its extremal form, be expressed as follows: If two qubits A and B are maximally quantumly correlated they cannot be correlated at all with a third qubit C.

My first question is how could you practically even test this? If monogamy is true in a realistic sense, then by definition it is untestable, since trying to measure a pair of entangled photons changes the entangled pair and as far as we know they would no longer be entangled after the measurement.

The other question, is in the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured, I can argue that 1 only became entangled with 4 after 1 was measured and after 4 was measured which means at no time was 1 entangled with both 2 & 4 and at no time was 4 entangled with both 3 & 1. So even if I did take the most strict view of entanglement of monogamy, it still is not violated in this case.

So please help me understand:
1) Is @DrChinese and his monogamy of entanglement argument in dispute with this view of cause and effect realism?
2) Assuming we are truly in disagreement, how does his monogamy of entanglement argument refute cause and effect realism in the case where the BSM test is done last?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
kurt101 said:
I think the entanglement swapping experiment is compatible with realistic interpretations that respect cause and effect
The obvious issue with any such interpretation is that the actually observed experimental behavior (which agrees with the QM predictions) is the same regardless of the time ordering of the measurements. Any interpretation that attempts to preserve "cause and effect" therefore has to argue that, even though the actual behavior is exactly the same, which measurement is the "cause" and which is the "effect" depends on the order in which you do the measurements. Such an interpretation seems strained, to say the least.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese and vanhees71
kurt101 said:
My first question is how could you practically even test this?
By preparing two qubits in a maximally entangled state and preparing a bunch of other qubits in whatever state you like, and verifying, by a large number of repeated trials with identical preparations, that the two qubits you prepared in the maximally entangled state show the appropriate correlations with each other, and no correlations with any of the other qubits.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
kurt101 said:
in the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured, I can argue that 1 only became entangled with 4 after 1 was measured and after 4 was measured
Perhaps you can, but that is not the argument others were making in the previous threads on this topic. They were arguing that 1 & 4 were entangled the whole time.
 
Last edited:
  • Skeptical
Likes Nullstein
kurt101 said:
I think the entanglement swapping experiment is compatible with realistic interpretations that respect cause and effect such as argued in this paper http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9427/1/Delayed_Choice.pdf (Go to chapter 4 for the argument on the entanglement swapping experiment)
Realistic interpretations are compatible with cause and effect, but not with locality. This means that causal effects in realistic interpretations can relate events which are spatially separated. The reference to particles that no longer exist is rather naive, because in theories (typically QFT's) in which particles may be destroyed there is no destruction of fundamental degrees of freedom, meaning that something remains even when the particles are destroyed. For example, if a photon is absorbed by an atom, then the atom takes information that was carried by the photon.
 
kurt101 said:
Where I think @DrChinese and the paper disagree is the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured.
While the paper does say that the BSM test does not cause the entanglement of 1 & 4 in this case, it offers no alternative explanation of what does cause the entanglement of 1 & 4.

kurt101 said:
in the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured, I can argue that 1 only became entangled with 4 after 1 was measured and after 4 was measured
But how do 1 & 4 become entangled? If it isn't the BSM measurement (which you say it isn't in this case), what is it? You offer no alternative explanation, any more than the paper does (see above).
 
Demystifier said:
Realistic interpretations are compatible with cause and effect, but not with locality.
What they're not compatible with is not just "locality" but time ordering. In the case under discussion, a BSM measurement, on the realist interpretation @DrChinese has been using, is the reason for photons 1 & 4 being entangled, even if the BSM measurement event is in the future light cone of the 1 & 4 measurement events.
 
Demystifier said:
in theories (typically QFT's) in which particles may be destroyed there is no destruction of fundamental degrees of freedom, meaning that something remains even when the particles are destroyed.
This is an interesting possibility to explore as far as interpretations are concerned, but I am not aware of any significant exploration of it in the literature. Do you know if anyone has tried to construct a realist interpretation along these lines? It wouldn't make the time ordering issue I described in post #7 any less weird, but it might at least offer a different viewpoint on this type of scenario.
 
PeterDonis said:
What they're not compatible with is not just "locality" but time ordering. In the case under discussion, a BSM measurement, on the realist interpretation @DrChinese has been using, is the reason for photons 1 & 4 being entangled, even if the BSM measurement event is in the future light cone of the 1 & 4 measurement events.
Nonlocal realistic theories typically keep time ordering but violate Lorentz covariance. This means that time ordering and causality is not formulated in terms of light cones.
 
  • #10
PeterDonis said:
This is an interesting possibility to explore as far as interpretations are concerned, but I am not aware of any significant exploration of it in the literature. Do you know if anyone has tried to construct a realist interpretation along these lines? It wouldn't make the time ordering issue I described in post #7 any less weird, but it might at least offer a different viewpoint on this type of scenario.
Of course, Bohmian QFT is well developed in the literature. Perhaps nobody analyzed this specific experiment with Bohmian QFT, but in principle it's easy once you understand the general principles of Bohmian QFT.
 
  • #11
Demystifier said:
Perhaps nobody analyzed this specific experiment with Bohmian QFT, but in principle it's easy once you understand the general principles of Bohmian QFT.
Could you give a brief outline of how such an analysis would go?
 
  • #12
PeterDonis said:
Could you give a brief outline of how such an analysis would go?
The most difficult part is to first outline how such analysis would go with standard QFT. If you can present this part by yourself, in a way that you understand well, then I can easily explain to you how your analysis with standard QFT modifies with Bohmian QFT.
 
  • #13
PeterDonis said:
Perhaps you can, but that is not the argument others were making in the previous threads on this topic. They were arguing that 1 & 4 were entangled the whole time.
This is at best misleading. In the entanglement-swapping experiment the initial state is
$$\hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_{12} \otimes \hat{\rho}_{34},$$
i.e., photons 1 and 4 are not entangled, no matter in which state the photon pairs (12) and (34) are, because the (reduced) state of the pair (14) factorizes
$$\hat{\rho}_{14}=\mathrm{Tr}_{23} \hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_1 \otimes \hat{\rho}_2.$$
If now ##\hat{\rho}_{12}## and ##\hat{\rho}_{34}## are Bell states, i.e., each of the pairs is maximally entangled you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (34) to a Bell state, i.e., you select a subensemble from the original ensemble, for which (14) is in a Bell state.

The projection of (34) to a Bell state is, however, not the cause for the entanglement of (14), which can be ensured, if the measurement events ("clicks of detectors") on photons 1 and 4 are spacelike separated from the projection measurement on (34). At least this is, as far as I know, the consensus in the quantum-optics community, and formally that's well justified due to the validity of the microcausality constraint of standard QED, which correctly predicts the outcome of this and all other Bell-test/EPR-type measurements.

The possibility for entanglement swapping is thus due to the entanglement of photon pairs (12) and (34) in the initial state. Of course, to which of the Bell states you project, is completely random. In the most simple case one only selects the polarization-singlet state, because this can be most simply realized by simply selecting those events, when photons 2 and 3 end up at different detectors behind the PBS. This happens completely randomly with a probability of 25%.
 
  • Like
Likes Nullstein
  • #14
vanhees71 said:
This is at best misleading. In the entanglement-swapping experiment the initial state is
$$\hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_{12} \otimes \hat{\rho}_{34},$$
i.e., photons 1 and 4 are not entangled, no matter in which state the photon pairs (12) and (34) are, because the (reduced) state of the pair (14) factorizes
$$\hat{\rho}_{14}=\mathrm{Tr}_{23} \hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_1 \otimes \hat{\rho}_2.$$
If now ##\hat{\rho}_{12}## and ##\hat{\rho}_{34}## are Bell states, i.e., each of the pairs is maximally entangled you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (34) to a Bell state, i.e., you select a subensemble from the original ensemble, for which (14) is in a Bell state.

The projection of (34) to a Bell state is, however, not the cause for the entanglement of (14), which can be ensured, if the measurement events ("clicks of detectors") on photons 1 and 4 are spacelike separated from the projection measurement on (34). At least this is, as far as I know, the consensus in the quantum-optics community, and formally that's well justified due to the validity of the microcausality constraint of standard QED, which correctly predicts the outcome of this and all other Bell-test/EPR-type measurements.

The possibility for entanglement swapping is thus due to the entanglement of photon pairs (12) and (34) in the initial state. Of course, to which of the Bell states you project, is completely random. In the most simple case one only selects the polarization-singlet state, because this can be most simply realized by simply selecting those events, when photons 2 and 3 end up at different detectors behind the PBS. This happens completely randomly with a probability of 25%.
I take it there are some typos here? Do you mean
This is at best misleading. In the entanglement-swapping experiment the initial state is
$$\hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_{12} \otimes \hat{\rho}_{34},$$
i.e., photons 1 and 4 are not entangled, no matter in which state the photon pairs (12) and (34) are, because the (reduced) state of the pair (14) factorizes
$$\hat{\rho}_{14}=\mathrm{Tr}_{23} \hat{\rho}=\hat{\rho}_1 \otimes \hat{\rho}_4.$$
If now ##\hat{\rho}_{12}## and ##\hat{\rho}_{34}## are Bell states, i.e., each of the pairs is maximally entangled you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (23) to a Bell state, i.e., you select a subensemble from the original ensemble, for which (14) is in a Bell state.

The projection of (23) to a Bell state is, however, not the cause for the entanglement of (14), which can be ensured, if the measurement events ("clicks of detectors") on photons 1 and 4 are spacelike separated from the projection measurement on (23). At least this is, as far as I know, the consensus in the quantum-optics community, and formally that's well justified due to the validity of the microcausality constraint of standard QED, which correctly predicts the outcome of this and all other Bell-test/EPR-type measurements.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes DrChinese and mattt
  • #15
Consider the statement
"The subensemble selected by an outcome of the measurement on pair (23) will show entanglement in the pair (14). Given this same subensemble, if the physicist had, for these specific runs, decided not to perform any measurement on (23), there would be no correlation in (14) in these runs"

This is presumably the sense in which people discuss a measurement on (23) doing something to (14) even with spacelike separations. But QM on its own (i.e. without some additional interpretation-dependent commitment) doesn't let us conclude this. It doesn't let us evaluate the above statement as true.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier, mattt and martinbn
  • #16
vanhees71 said:
The projection of (34) to a Bell state is, however, not the cause for the entanglement of (14)
I would like to reformulate the question: can projection ever cause entanglement? I will argue that it can, in a simpler context that does not involve entanglement swapping, but something simpler.

Let initial state be
$$|\Psi\rangle=|\psi\rangle|\psi\rangle$$
where ##|\psi\rangle## is a 1-particle state
$$|\psi\rangle=|L\rangle+|R\rangle .$$
Here ##|L\rangle## and ##|R\rangle## are some orthogonal 1-particle states, and for simplicity I don't care about normalization factors. Clearly, in the initial state ##|\Psi\rangle## there is no entanglement at all. However, ##|\Psi\rangle## can be written as
$$|\Psi\rangle=|{\rm Hardy}\rangle + |R\rangle|R\rangle \;\;\;\;\; (1)$$
where
$$|{\rm Hardy}\rangle=|L\rangle|L\rangle+|L\rangle|R\rangle+|R\rangle|L\rangle$$
is the Hardy state. The Hardy state is entangled. Hence, if we project ##|\Psi\rangle## onto the first term in (1), we get entangled state by projection. Since there was no entanglement at all in the initial state, it seems clear that entanglement was created by projection.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #17
Demystifier said:
I would like to reformulate the question: can projection ever cause entanglement? I will argue that it can, in a simpler context that does not involve entanglement swapping, but something simpler.

Let initial state be
$$|\Psi\rangle=|\psi\rangle|\psi\rangle$$
where ##|\psi\rangle## is a 1-particle state
$$|\psi\rangle=|L\rangle+|R\rangle .$$
Here ##|L\rangle## and ##|R\rangle## are some orthogonal 1-particle states, and for simplicity I don't care about normalization factors. Clearly, in the initial state ##|\Psi\rangle## there is no entanglement at all. However, ##|\Psi\rangle## can be written as
$$|\Psi\rangle=|{\rm Hardy}\rangle + |R\rangle|R\rangle \;\;\;\;\; (1)$$
where
$$|{\rm Hardy}\rangle=|L\rangle|L\rangle+|L\rangle|R\rangle+|R\rangle|L\rangle$$
is the Hardy state. The Hardy state is entangled. Hence, if we project ##|\Psi\rangle## onto the first term in (1), we get entangled state by projection. Since there was no entanglement at all in the initial state, it seems clear that entanglement was created by projection.
But the projection will not result in that state 100% of the trials. So the entanglement will be of a subensemble. Your example is, in this respect, not different than the swapping.
 
  • Like
Likes DrClaude
  • #18
Morbert said:
Consider the statement
"The subensemble selected by an outcome of the measurement on pair (23) will show entanglement in the pair (14). Given this same subensemble, if the physicist had, for these specific runs, decided not to perform any measurement on (23), there would be no correlation in (14) in these runs"
Statements like these are why there continues to be confusion about this issue. How do you make a subensemble of one pair? This makes no sense.
Until the participants in these discussions learn to use language correctly, it is best to shut up and just calculate.
 
  • Like
  • Haha
Likes martinbn, Nullstein, Morbert and 1 other person
  • #19
martinbn said:
But the projection will not result in that state 100% of the trials. So the entanglement will be of a subensemble. Your example is, in this respect, not different than the swapping.
Indeed, it was my intention to construct something very similar to swapping, but simpler. In this way one can better understand what about swapping is essential, and what is not.
 
  • Like
Likes DrClaude and martinbn
  • #20
martinbn said:
So the entanglement will be of a subensemble.
While this is true, I don't see how is this relevant. It does not diminish the strangeness of entanglement.

To demonstrate this, let me consider another example. Consider a machine that first flips a coin, and then, depending on the result of coin flipping, creates a quantum state. If the coin turns out heads, the machine creates an entangled state. If the coin turns out tails, the machine creates a non-entangled state. Here again the entanglement is a property of a subensemble, but it does not make entanglement any less strange.
 
  • #21
lodbrok said:
Statements like these are why there continues to be confusion about this issue. How do you make a subensemble of one pair? This makes no sense.
Until the participants in these discussions learn to use language correctly, it is best to shut up and just ...

What do you mean by one pair?

You need a sufficiently large number of runs of every pair to test anything.

I think what Morbert wrote there is crystal clear.
 
  • #22
Demystifier said:
While this is true, I don't see how is this relevant. It does not diminish the strangeness of entanglement.

To demonstrate this, let me consider another example. Consider a machine that first flips a coin, and then, depending on the result of coin flipping, creates a quantum state. If the coin turns out heads, the machine creates an entangled state. If the coin turns out tails, the machine creates a non-entangled state. Here again the entanglement is a property of a subensemble, but it does not make entanglement any less strange.
Yes, but one point in the older threads was that swapping doesn't bring anything new in terms of strangeness. The strangeness is already there in entangled pairs.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #23
martinbn said:
But the projection will not result in that state 100% of the trials. So the entanglement will be of a subensemble. Your example is, in this respect, not different than the swapping.
You can never have 100% success for swapping to a specific Bell state. That cannot be, because the full ensemble is unentangled by preparation, and indeed it's not different from this example.
 
  • #24
lodbrok said:
Statements like these are why there continues to be confusion about this issue. How do you make a subensemble of one pair? This makes no sense.

The pairings mentioned, like (23) or (14), are pairings that exist in every experimental run. You construct a subensemble by doing many runs.
 
  • #25
You cannot do any such experiments with realizing just one pair. It's about probabilities, which can be tested only on ensembles. I'm a proponent of the ensemble interpretation, i.e., for me a quantum state describes the stastistical properties for the outcome of measurements on ensembles of equally prepared systems.
 
  • Like
Likes lodbrok and Nullstein
  • #26
vanhees71 said:
This is at best misleading.
As a description of the actual math, which you present, it might be. But it's not misleading as a description of what other posters (not you) said in those previous threads. They explicitly claimed that 1 & 4 were entangled in the original prepared state (based on them being able to always pick a "subensemble" that reflected this).
 
  • #27
vanhees71 said:
you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (34) to a Bell state
Not (34), (23). That is the pair that the BSM is done on.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #28
PeterDonis said:
As a description of the actual math, which you present, it might be. But it's not misleading as a description of what other posters (not you) said in those previous threads. They explicitly claimed that 1 & 4 were entangled in the original prepared state (based on them being able to always pick a "subensemble" that reflected this).
No, that's exactly the opposite of what people said in the previous threads. The system 1&4 is always non-entangled, both before and after the BSM at 2&3. The state of the 1&4 system is given by:
$$\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1$$
This state is a product state, so it is not entangled.

What people were trying to explain was that selecting a subensemble of that state does not have any physical effect on system 1&4, so the fact that one can pick an entangled subensemble does not imply that the system 1&4 is entangled. Neither cherry picking nor picking by conditioning on a measurement at 2&3 has any physical effect on the 1&4 system. Selecting a subensemble is something that is done long after the experiment has been performed and the measurement results have become manifest and been recorded. The entanglement in the subensembles is spurious and infering causal relationships from them is an instance of Berkson's fallacy, as explained here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1606.04523

The fact that ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1## also proves that the argument of DrChinese based on monogamy of entanglement is erroneous. Since the system is not entangled, it is in particular not monogamously entangled, so the very premise of DrChinese's argument is violated.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes DrClaude, lodbrok and martinbn
  • #29
mattt said:
What do you mean by one pair?

You need a sufficiently large number of runs of every pair to test anything.

I think what Morbert wrote there is crystal clear.
My issue wasn't with Morbert; it was with the statement he quoted. The statement he quoted was, "The subensemble selected by an outcome of the measurement on pair (23) will show entanglement in the pair (14)." Pair (23) is precisely two particles, and pair (14) is exactly two particles. So where does the subensemble come into it?

The more precise statement would have been: "The measurement on the ensemble of particle pairs (23) allows us to select a subensemble of particle pairs (14) which show entanglement."
The fact that many now consider these statements equivalent is the problem I was highlighting. Just re-read this thread and appreciate the near-universal misuse of "a pair," "the pair," "pair (12)", and "pair (23)" by all sides of the argument. This gives an utterly false impression that during each iteration involving four particles, the measurement performed on two particles changes something about the other two. This impression is furthered even by those who actively argue against this view.

The only thing we know that factually happens in these experiments is that for each iteration of 4 particles, the measurement result from two of them is used later to decide whether or not the other two belong to the desired sub-ensemble.
 
  • Like
Likes Nullstein
  • #30
Morbert said:
The pairings mentioned, like (23) or (14), are pairings that exist in every experimental run. You construct a subensemble by doing many runs.
Correct, but those pairings in each experimental iteration are not the same as what is implied in a statement like the following from this thread:
you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (34) to a Bell state
The sad part is that the person who made this statement does not believe that what happens to two of the four particles in a particular iteration of the experiment changes anything about the other two.
So we keep going around in circles, talking past each other because we don't bother to be precise with our language.
 
  • Like
Likes WernerQH and Nullstein
  • #31
lodbrok said:
My issue wasn't with Morbert; it was with the statement he quoted. The statement he quoted was, "The subensemble selected by an outcome of the measurement on pair (23) will show entanglement in the pair (14)." Pair (23) is precisely two particles, and pair (14) is exactly two particles. So where does the subensemble come into it?

The more precise statement would have been: "The measurement on the ensemble of particle pairs (23) allows us to select a subensemble of particle pairs (14) which show entanglement."
The fact that many now consider these statements equivalent is the problem I was highlighting. Just re-read this thread and appreciate the near-universal misuse of "a pair," "the pair," "pair (12)", and "pair (23)" by all sides of the argument. This gives an utterly false impression that during each iteration involving four particles, the measurement performed on two particles changes something about the other two. This impression is furthered even by those who actively argue against this view.

The only thing we know that factually happens in these experiments is that for each iteration of 4 particles, the measurement result from two of them is used later to decide whether or not the other two belong to the desired sub-ensemble.

Well, yes, it's kind of an "economical way of writing" (not dangerous if everybody knows what we are talking about), after all I think everybody here knows that you need an ensemble of identically prepared particle-pairs (in this case), thousands of them indeed, the to be able to statistically test anything with a given desired statistical significance.
 
  • #32
martinbn said:
Yes, but one point in the older threads was that swapping doesn't bring anything new in terms of strangeness. The strangeness is already there in entangled pairs.
OK, but in my example in #16, do you agree that the strangeness is not already there before projection, and that the projection creates strangeness?
 
  • #33
lodbrok said:
Correct, but those pairings in each experimental iteration are not the same as what is implied in a statement like the following from this thread:
"you can make the pair (14) maximally entangled by projecting the pair (34) to a Bell state"
I see nothing problematic about that statement (if you understand what it means).

It just means that, out of the millions of (1,4) pairs created, the approximately 25% of them that are the "companions" respectively of exactly the (2,3) pairs that ended up in the BSM state, satisfy (this (1,4) subensemble) satisfy the statistics that we call "a Maximally Entangled State", that's what Quantum Mechanics says, and that is what experimenters can test, up to technological limitations.
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question
  • #34
Nullstein said:
The state of the 1&4 system is given by:
$$\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1$$
This state is a product state, so it is not entangled.

What people were trying to explain was that selecting a subensemble of that state does not have any physical effect on system 1&4, so the fact that one can pick an entangled subensemble does not imply that the system 1&4 is entangled.
Thank you for the clarification.

Now let's look at particles 1 & 2. Their "before" state is a maximally entangled state. It was prepared that way. What is their "after" state? By your reasoning, it should be the same, just as the state of 1 & 4 "after" is the same as "before"--which would mean that the BSM done on particles 2 & 3 has no physical effect on anything at all. Is that your position?
 
  • #35
PeterDonis said:
Now let's look at particles 1 & 2. Their "before" state is a maximally entangled state. It was prepared that way. What is their "after" state? By your reasoning, it should be the same, just as the state of 1 & 4 "after" is the same as "before"--which would mean that the BSM done on particles 2 & 3 has no physical effect on anything at all. Is that your position?
No, that's not my position. The state of 1&2 after the BSM does change, it becomes a mixed state, because 2 is now entangled with 3 due to the local action at 2&3. Before the BSM, it was a pure state. It means that some of the initial monogamous entanglement between 1&2 "spilled over" to the 2&3 system. The physical effect of the BSM at 2&3 is to decrease the entanglement between 1&2 and 3&4 and to increase the entanglement between 2&3.
 
Last edited:
  • #36
kurt101 said:
TL;DR Summary: I have some questions about entanglement swapping, realistic interpretations, and the monogamy entanglement argument that @DrChinese has been making that I want to ask about in an I-level thread.

For this discussion I would like to continue referring to the entangled pairs 1,2 and 3,4 as we have in previous discussions. For background on this discussion refer to post-selection: pre-existing correlations or action at a distance where @DrChinese describes the entanglement swapping experiments and his monogamy argument.

I think the entanglement swapping experiment is compatible with realistic interpretations that respect cause and effect such as argued in this paper http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9427/1/Delayed_Choice.pdf (Go to chapter 4 for the argument on the entanglement swapping experiment)

This paper is not disputing entanglement between 1 & 4 in the case where the BSM test is done prior to 1 & 4 being measured. I think it is accurate to say the paper and @DrChinese are in agreement here. And in the context of a cause and effect realistic interpretation, I don't see how anyone could argue for a coincidental explanation for this case, because you can always change the way you measure 1, 4 after knowing the result of the BSM test and so you have a cause and effect problem if you are suggesting a coincidental explanation for this case.

Where I think @DrChinese and the paper disagree is the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured. In a realistic interpretation with cause and effect, the cause can't happen after the effect. So while nobody disputes that 1 & 4 have an entangled correlation, the realistic explanation for the entanglement of 1 & 4 is one that requires coincidence between 1 & 4 versus causation; in other words 1 & 4 happened to have just the right initial states where their measurements resulted in an entangled correlation and a change to 2 & 3 so that the BSM test showed maximum entanglement.

It is my understanding that @DrChinese argument using monogamy of entanglement is in dispute with this second case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured. I have read many definitions and gone through the proof that @DrChinese provided and I don't see how this second case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 is being measured is in violation of monogamy.

Taking one of the definitions that @DrChinese has previously referred to from https://www.quantiki.org/wiki/monogamy-entanglement
''Monogamy ''' is one of the most fundamental properties of entanglement and can, in its extremal form, be expressed as follows: If two qubits A and B are maximally quantumly correlated they cannot be correlated at all with a third qubit C.

My first question is how could you practically even test this? If monogamy is true in a realistic sense, then by definition it is untestable, since trying to measure a pair of entangled photons changes the entangled pair and as far as we know they would no longer be entangled after the measurement.

The other question, is in the case where the BSM test is done after 1 & 4 being measured, I can argue that 1 only became entangled with 4 after 1 was measured and after 4 was measured which means at no time was 1 entangled with both 2 & 4 and at no time was 4 entangled with both 3 & 1. So even if I did take the most strict view of entanglement of monogamy, it still is not violated in this case.

So please help me understand:
1) Is @DrChinese and his monogamy of entanglement argument in dispute with this view of cause and effect realism?
2) Assuming we are truly in disagreement, how does his monogamy of entanglement argument refute cause and effect realism in the case where the BSM test is done last?
I think @PeterDonis, @Morbert , @Demystifier et al have addressed these questions one way or another. But I will recap:
  1. There is no experimental difference when the BSM on 2 & 3 (which is a required event) is performed before OR after the Bell test is performed on 1 & 4. Either way, 1 & 4 entanglement is confirmed by the violation of a Bell Inequality.
  2. Accordingly, from the reference, the following is simply incorrect: "Without delayed choice, this has physical significance, because each (A, D) pair actually is in such a state after the (B, C) measurement. But if the (A, D) measurements precede the (B, C) measurement, the (A, D) pair never is in any
    of these states." The 1 & 4 (Egg's A & D) pairs are entangled if and only if a successful BSM occurs, regardless of when they occur. There are no "coincidental" violations of Bell Inequalities.
  3. Monogamy of Entanglement applies regardless of when the BSM occurs. The timing defies the usual cause and effect relationship/ordering. You cannot reasonably say "The swap occurred at time X". You can only make the statement that "1 was initially entangled to 2, and was later entangled to 4." But at no time was 1 maximally entangled with both 2 and 4, as that defies MoE.
  4. For that to happen means that there was a change in the quantum state. We started with biphoton 1 & 2 and ended with biphoton 1 & 4. A biphoton has temporospatial extent which can exceed the usual Einsteinian limitations.
  5. If you are asking about "local realistic" interpretations, clearly those are long excluded due to Bell anyway. Extending the discussion to swapping with independent sources is simply going to fall further flat. If you want to be "realistic", you need to explain why the Bell State Measurement - which according to your position is NOT responsible for the ultimate entanglement of 1 & 4 (being just to identify 1 & 4 pairs with certain characteristics) - requires indistinguishability between 2 & 3. Because you can easily identify those same characteristics WITHOUT them being indistinguishable - and then 1 & 4 are not entangled! If the BSM is not an actual event responsible for the swap, why would they need to be indistinguishable? After all, you can still apply the same "filter" to identify the Bell State. Same 2 clicks.
 
  • #37
Nullstein said:
The state of 1&2 after the BSM does change, it becomes a mixed state, because 2 is now entangled with 3 due to the local action at 2&3. Before the BSM, it was a pure state. It means that some of the initial monogamous entanglement between 1&2 "spilled over" to the 2&3 system.
No, not "some" of the monogamous entanglement between 1 & 2 -- all of it, because the state of 2 & 3 after the BSM is maximally entangled. So the state of 1 & 2 after the BSM must be a product state. (And similarly for the state of 3 & 4.)

But even that isn't a complete description, because what happens to 2 & 3 is not the same on every run. There are four possible Bell states of 2 & 3 that can be produced by the BSM, each with equal probability, but only one of them leads to an "event ready" signal that is then used to post-select the runs for which 1 & 4 end up maximally entangled. And even the four Bell states taken all together only get produced on a subset of runs, because particles 2 & 3 don't always arrive at the Bell state measurement device in a narrow enough time window for a BSM to happen at all. So actually, there are four different possible maximally entangled 2 & 3 states, each with its own subset of runs, plus another subset of runs (in practice this is by far the largest one) where nothing happens to 2 & 3 at all.

Which means that, in order to justify the logic in what I quoted from you above (with the correction I gave in the first paragraph of mine above), you have to pick out a particular subensemble of the full ensemble, according to the result of the BSM. And this is exactly the same logic that @DrChinese is using to pick out the subensemble in which 1 & 4 are maximally entangled. So either you agree with @DrChinese, or your own position is inconsistent--you allow the picking of subensembles to have a physical effect when it suits you, but not when it doesn't.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and DrChinese
  • #38
Nullstein said:
What people were trying to explain was that selecting a subensemble of that state does not have any physical effect on system 1&4, so the fact that one can pick an entangled subensemble does not imply that the system 1&4 is entangled. Neither cherry picking nor picking by conditioning on a measurement at 2&3 has any physical effect on the 1&4 system. Selecting a subensemble is something that is done long after the experiment has been performed and the measurement results have become manifest and been recorded. The entanglement in the subensembles is spurious and infering causal relationships from them is an instance of Berkson's fallacy, as explained here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1606.04523
I would agree that nothing physical happens to 1&4, which is clear in the post-selection case, especially if one assumes that effects don't travel back in time.

But when you select the subensemble using the swapping procedure before 1&4 are measured, you can use that subensemble to violate Bell inequalities. So it must be entangled; I would say by definition.
 
  • Like
Likes Nullstein
  • #39
PeterDonis said:
No, not "some" of the monogamous entanglement between 1 & 2 -- all of it, because the state of 2 & 3 after the BSM is maximally entangled. So the state of 1 & 2 after the BSM must be a product state.
After the BSM, the state at 2&3 is given by a mixture of 4 fully entangled states.
PeterDonis said:
But even that isn't a complete description, because what happens to 2 & 3 is not the same on every run. There are four possible Bell states of 2 & 3 that can be produced by the BSM, each with equal probability, and even that only happens on a subset of runs, because particles 2 & 3 don't always arrive at the Bell state measurement device in a narrow enough time window for a BSM to happen at all. So actually, there are four different possible maximally entangled 2 & 3 states, each with its own subset of runs, plus another subset of runs (in practice this is by far the largest one) where nothing happens to 2 & 3 at all.
This is why the full ensemble is in a mixture. This mixture is what is relevant for the physical considerations.
PeterDonis said:
Which means that, in order to justify the logic in what I quoted from you above, you have to pick out a particular subensemble of the full ensemble, according to the result of the BSM. And this is exactly the same logic that @DrChinese is using to pick out the subensemble in which 1 & 4 are maximally entangled. So either you agree with @DrChinese, or your own position is inconsistent--you allow the picking of subensembles to have an effect when it suits you, but not when it doesn't.
No, I'm never picking subensembles. I'm only talking about the full ensemble and calculate states of subsystems.

Before the BSM, the full ensemble is given by
$$\rho_{1234,\text{before}}=\rho_{12}\otimes\rho_{34}$$
After the BSM, the full ensemble is given by
$$\rho_{1234,\text{after}}=\sum_i (\mathbb 1_1\otimes P_i\otimes\mathbb 1_4)\rho_{1234,\text{before}}(\mathbb 1_1\otimes P_i\otimes\mathbb 1_4)$$

The states of the subsystems are given by
$$\rho_{ij,\text{after}}=\mathrm{tr}_{kl}(\rho_{1234,\text{after}})$$
where ##(i,j,k,l)## is a permutation of ##(1,2,3,4)##. It's just a mathematical exercise to compute them. I agree with whatever the result of that computation is.
 
  • #40
akvadrako said:
I would agree that nothing physical happens to 1&4, which is clear in the post-selection case, especially if one assumes that effects don't travel back in time.

But when you select the subensemble using the swapping procedure before 1&4 are measured, you can use that subensemble to violate Bell inequalities. So it must be entangled; I would say by definition.
I agree that the subensembles are entangled. I'm just saying that no conclusion about causal relationships can be inferred from the subensembles unless one can exclude Berkson's fallacy, which we can't in the case of entanglement swapping.
 
  • Like
Likes akvadrako
  • #41
lodbrok said:
The more precise statement would have been: "The measurement on the ensemble of particle pairs (23) allows us to select a subensemble of particle pairs (14) which show entanglement."
...

This gives an utterly false impression that during each iteration involving four particles, the measurement performed on two particles changes something about the other two. ...

The only thing we know that factually happens in these experiments is that for each iteration of 4 particles, the measurement result from two of them is used later to decide whether or not the other two belong to the desired sub-ensemble.
This is inaccurate. A BSM absolutely changes the state of remote 1 & 4. That's the essence of our disagreement.

Each and every time there are 2 clicks at the BSM signaling the arrival of photons 2 & 3 within the specified time window, then the corresponding 1 & 4 will be cast into an maximally entangled state (forming a different biphoton). Which of the 4 possible Bell states are identified varies from experiment to experiment, but there is always entanglement - as long as the event does not allow 2 to be distinguished from 3.

And that is another fly in the ointment to this whole debate. If all you are doing is "selecting" whether it is psi+ or psi- entanglement, why require indistinguishability? You can plainly see all of the same characteristics (DoFs) - even if they are distinguishable. Transmit or reflect at the beam splitter, H or V at the PBS, identical wavelengths, and within the time window. That's it. So why do the same selection parameters fail when there is distinguishability? Answer: because a successful BSM IS an event, and it remotely changes the quantum state of both 1 and 4. Without the successful BSM, there is no entanglement between any 1 & 4 pairs.
 
  • #42
DrChinese said:
This is inaccurate. A BSM absolutely changes the state of remote 1 & 4. That's the essence of our disagreement.
There's no experimental evidence for this in any experiment done to date. You are not disagreeing with me. You are disagreeing with the experimental record.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn and Nullstein
  • #43
DrChinese said:
This is inaccurate. A BSM absolutely changes the state of remote 1 & 4. That's the essence of our disagreement.
Nope. The state of the system 1&4 is given by ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4 \mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1##. It is not entangled.
DrChinese said:
And that is another fly in the ointment to this whole debate. If all you are doing is "selecting" whether it is psi+ or psi- entanglement, why require indistinguishability?
Nobody requires indistinguishability. We just write down the prepared state, compute its time evolution according to the axioms of QM and compute the statistical distributions that arise from the resulting state. All of this is interpretation-independent math.
 
  • #44
Nullstein said:
No, that's exactly the opposite of what people said in the previous threads. The system 1&4 is always non-entangled, both before and after the BSM at 2&3. The state of the 1&4 system is given by:
$$\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1$$
This state is a product state, so it is not entangled.

What people were trying to explain was that selecting a subensemble of that state does not have any physical effect on system 1&4, so the fact that one can pick an entangled subensemble does not imply that the system 1&4 is entangled. Neither cherry picking nor picking by conditioning on a measurement at 2&3 has any physical effect on the 1&4 system. Selecting a subensemble is something that is done long after the experiment has been performed and the measurement results have become manifest and been recorded. The entanglement in the subensembles is spurious and infering causal relationships from them is an instance of Berkson's fallacy, as explained here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1606.04523

The fact that ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1## also proves that the argument of DrChinese based on monogamy of entanglement is erroneous. Since the system is not entangled, it is in particular not monogamously entangled, so the very premise of DrChinese's argument is violated.
In the subensemble chosen by projecting (23) to one of the four Bell states (14) are in a Bell state too, i.e., they are entangled. That's why this is called enranglement swapping!
 
  • Like
Likes Nullstein
  • #45
vanhees71 said:
In the subensemble chosen by projecting (23) to one of the four Bell states (14) are in a Bell state too, i.e., they are entangled. That's why this is called enranglement swapping!
I agree. The subensembles are entangled, but the correlations that arise from this entanglement are spurious, i.e. not causal. Inferring a causal relationship from the correlations is a statistical fallacy called Berkson's paradox, as explained in the Spekkens paper I cited above. So it is illegal to conclude any non-local cause and effect relationship from the appearance of correlations in the subensembles.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #46
Nullstein said:
What people were trying to explain was that selecting a subensemble of that state does not have any physical effect on system 1&4,
...and failed. At preparation there is no entanglement (I think you agree with this), at measurement there is some. I think most physicist consider entanglement "physical".

Nullstein said:
so the fact that one can pick an entangled subensemble does not imply that the system 1&4 is entangled.
That sub ensemble cannot exist because 0% of the 1 & 4 pair are entangled. Furthermore 100% of 1 & 4 are fully entangled with another partner (2 & 3 repetitively). Basic QM.

Nullstein said:
Neither cherry picking nor picking by conditioning on a measurement at 2&3 has any physical effect on the 1&4 system.
Yet one sub ensemble is picked, while it "could not exist". Most people call this a change.

Nullstein said:
Selecting a subensemble is something that is done long after the experiment has been performed and the measurement results have become manifest and been recorded.
That's incorrect. The sub ensemble is selected/picked at BSM site. Whatever the place and time.
Furthermore it can ONLY be selected there. This is called a swapping.

Nullstein said:
The entanglement in the subensembles is spurious and infering causal relationships from them is an instance of Berkson's fallacy, as explained here: https://arxiv.org/abs/1606.04523
Why not calling it lucky entanglement than ? What are the chances that anyone, anytime, can pickup that (or those ?) sub-ensemble ? Show me the math.

Nullstein said:
The fact that ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1## also proves that the argument of DrChinese based on monogamy of entanglement is erroneous. Since the system is not entangled, it is in particular not monogamously entangled, so the very premise of DrChinese's argument is violated.
The system is completely entangled, contrary to your claim. It is prepared as such. Just not 1&4, but 1&2 and 3&4.

Can we cut to the chase ? Are you claiming that monogamy of entanglement is wrong ? Are you claiming that swapping is a fluke ? You really need reference here.

Nullstein said:
So it is illegal to conclude any non-local cause and effect relationship from the appearance of correlations in the subensembles.
Well, it will be fun to see the Quantum police arrest the people using those "appearance" (not change of course) to secure your communication.:wink:
 
  • #47
akvadrako said:
1. ... especially if one assumes that effects don't travel back in time.

2. But when you select the subensemble using the swapping procedure before 1&4 are measured, you can use that subensemble to violate Bell inequalities. So it must be entangled; I would say by definition.
1. How do you not see that this is circular reasoning? Swapping is proof (by counterexample) that the quantum mechanical world does NOT obey Einsteinian causality.

2. There is no difference in outcomes - or description of what is occurring - regardless of ordering. That is an experimental fact. There are NO 1 & 4 pairs that are entangled - NO SUBSET or SUBENSEMBLE - unless a BSM occurs.

You must realize that you are saying that there were SOME such entangled 1 & 4 pairs - even if the experimenter insured no BSM occurred. But that actually means that every entangled photon - everywhere, created anytime in all of history - was potentially also entangled with those same 1 & 4 pairs. Because what otherwise connects them? The 1 & 4 photons are created from independent distant sources at completely different times! That same requirement (which is no requirement at all) means any photon could be similarly entangled with either 1 or 4 - if you say that there existed entanglement between 1 & 4 for some subensemble prior to the swap. (Keep in mind that 1 & 4 need not have ever even co-existed for a swap to succeed. And they still be swapped either before or after their Bell test.)

But no, that's not what happens. The swap is a necessary event to the results. It is not "merely" selection.
 
  • #48
Simple question said:
...and failed. At preparation there is no entanglement (I think you agree with this), at measurement there is some. I think most physicist consider entanglement "physical".
No I don't agree with this. Entanglement between which systems? There is entanglement between 1&2 and 3&4 before the BSM. There is no entanglement between 1&4 before the BSM and there is no entanglement between 1&4 after the BSM.
Simple question said:
That sub ensemble cannot exist because 0% of the 1 & 4 pair are entangled. Furthermore 100% of 1 & 4 are fully entangled with another partner (2 & 3 repetitively). Basic QM.
False. The 1&4 system is in the state ##\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1##. Let ##P_i## be projectors onto the Bell basis. The completeness relation says that ##\sum_i P_i=\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1##. So we conclude that ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\sum_i \frac 1 4 P_i##, i.e. a statistical mixture of 4 entangled states.
Simple question said:
That's incorrect. The sub ensemble is selected/picked at BSM site. Whatever the place and time.
Furthermore it can ONLY be selected there. This is called a swapping.
Nope, the post-selection is done once the full data is collected.
Simple question said:
Show me the math.
See above.
Simple question said:
The system is completely entangled, contrary to your claim. It is prepared as such. Just not 1&4, but 1&2 and 3&4.
##\frac 1 4\mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1## is a product state, so not entangled.
Simple question said:
Can we cut to the chase ? Are you claiming that monogamy of entanglement is wrong ? Are you claiming that swapping is a fluke ? You really need reference here.
Nope, I'm claiming none of it.
 
  • #49
Nullstein said:
1. The state of the system 1&4 is given by ##\rho_{14,\text{before}}=\rho_{14,\text{after}}=\frac 1 4 \mathbb 1\otimes\mathbb 1##. It is not entangled.

2. Nobody requires indistinguishability. We just write down the prepared state, compute its time evolution according to the axioms of QM and compute the statistical distributions that arise from the resulting state. All of this is interpretation-independent math.
1. You have really gone off the deep end. After a swap, 1 & 4 are maximally entangled and are not in a Product state. Particles in a Product state do not violate Bell inequalities, and if you don't follow this point, you need to go back a step or two.

2. "Indistinguishability" is an absolute requirement for a swap. There are many ways to distinguish the source for the 2 clicks at the BSM. All of them must be eliminated for the swap to succeed. For example: you need to place a filter from each source to insure the wavelengths of the 2 & 3 photons are the same - otherwise that would distinguish them. They need to arrive close together - otherwise that would distinguish them. And if you placed a polarizer too early in the path, that could distinguish them.

So this requirement - indistinguishability - has no counterpart in the selection criteria being thrown around. Because every other element of the selection criteria can be met and there will be no swap. This requirement is a strictly quantum thing, and the same requirement exists when entangled pairs are created via PDC using BBo crystals. If you know the source of each photon, they won't be entangled. The output cones must be overlapped to hide the source.
 
  • #50
lodbrok said:
There's no experimental evidence for this in any experiment done to date.
You cannot assert this as a fact, since this is precisely what the discussion is about: whether, and under what interpretations, the entanglement swapping experiments provide such evidence.
 
Back
Top