selfAdjoint said:
And I do want to object again: you keep casting the discussion in these social terms, perhaps because you want to have consciousness built into QM, but what I want to talk about is what RQM, and the paper under discussion says. According to my reading, interaction B is a real fact of the universe, which is maybe relevant to interaction A, but the outcomes (measured observables) and their amplitudes and probabilities are NOT. The only outcomes and probabilities that are relative to interaction A are A's own.
So all of this B woulda-coulda analysis just doesn't arise in the context posited by S&R.
Let's repeat my viewpoint here. I'm not criticising RQM per se, it depends upon what one makes of it. I'm criticising the statement that RQM gives a non-solipsist viewpoint that resolves the preferred basis problem and the non-locality problem. It doesn't any of these things. The only thing it takes away is an objective description of the world, and hence has to rely on non-physical subjective worlds containing "information" which are not coded in any physical state.
There are indeed two faces to the measurement problem: the first one is the different treatment between "observer" and "observed" (some aspect of it is the preferred basis problem) and the second one is the non-local correlations that seem to be generated by it.
These are the issues that any view on QM has to address.
In the different families of interpretation, these issues are treated in different ways.
1) in Copenhagen, the first issue is dealt with, by making a distinction between macroscopic, and hence classical objects versus quantum objects. Classical objects have no preferred basis problem because we SAY what are the preferred states: the classical states. The second issue is dealt with by introducing a genuinly non-local process, which is the projection. So, in Copenhagen, QM is nor universal, nor local.
2) there are people who say that QM is just a way of calculating probabilities of outcomes of observation, not an attempt of a description of nature. As such, the concepts of "observer" and "observation" remain outside of a physical description and are based, in the end, upon entirely intuitive conceptions. It is left totally open how to resolve the preferred basis problem: a measurement apparatus that is supposed to measure "position" simply measures "position", because the salesman told you so. There's no detailled physical analysis possible of why this apparatus measures position and not momentum. The only analysis possible is by analysing how the apparatus WOULD work if things were entirely classical. And they don't solve any issue with non-locality as per Bell. One can hardly call such a view "complete", it is just an operational definition of a calculational algorithm, and the algorithm indicates that non-local things go on. One has to introduce by hand what hermitean operator (preferred basis) corresponds to what apparatus, inspired by what the apparatus could do if all things were classical. But as the algorithm has not the pretention to be the description of any phenomenon, it's left to our guessings what is the source of this non-locality (or even of what's nature like, or what our observations are supposed to mean).
3) in MWi-like views, QM is said to be universally applicable, and to be a description of nature. It could pretend to completeness this way, if the issue of what exactly is an observer is dealt with. The concept of observer is now redefined into a set of specific states associated to a subjective experience. It has the merit of being able to explain the *observation* of apparently non-local correlations due to a totally local process. MWI as such, explains why QM acts as an algorithm to produce probabilities of observation from the point of view of an observer which is picked randomly to be one of the states according to the hilbert norm of the term in which it occurs. The price to pay is that there are now multiple potential "observer-subjective realities" and one objective reality.
I noted that Rovelli (as many others btw) think that a "many minds" version is a kind of Copenhagen version, because "minds" are classically-like states - but this is missing the point: minds are not physical objects (minds are not brains, but specific brain-states to which a subjective - non-physical experience is associated, introducing hence a dualist vision).
When looking at RQM, none of the above issues is actually specifically handled.
RQM starts with some postulates concerning "information" an "observer" might possess. However, this begs the question: can an "observer" (being a quantum object) possesses specific information as a bit stream ? Possessing information means: being in one state of several (of a finite number of possibilities), and hence certainly NOT in a superposition or anything of the kind.
As such, the "information" of an observer associated with an object has nothing to do with any "state" of the object, because if it were, the information would be CODED in the physical state of the object, something which is forbidden. As such, the observer is a kind of subjective world ASSOCIATED with a physical object, in exactly the same way as in MWI.
We have to see an "observer" OA attached to a physical object as the information possessed by that physical object A. However, this information is of course NOT coded in the state of the object, because that would mean that the object has an objective state which it is supposed not to have. So this information is present only in a kind of subjective world attached to an object but certainly not in the object itself and there is no physical description of what aspect this information/memory/... might take. All that has been done is the setup of the information that this subjective world has as a result of interactions of the object with the rest of the world (but which, I repeat, is NOT stored in the object itself as a physical state).
If now ANOTHER object B, with ANOTHER observer OB attached to it, interacts with object A, then at most, observer OB gets information about the object A, but not of any "observer" attached to it (given that the information is not coded in a physical state of any object).
Now, my point is: this subjective world OB which possesses information, when asking things about OBJECT A, will in principle not get any answers from the OBSERVER OA, but only from the object A itself according to an independent probability generation (using the formalism of quantum theory). As such, there's no reason to assume that there is any synchronisation between any "information" OA might have, and any answers OB might obtain when asking them to OBJECT A.
This is what I meant: OA might have seen a blue tail and then ask object B what head it saw, and get an answer "blue head", while OB might have seen a pink head, and when asking object A what tail it saw, get the answer "pink tail".
As such, there is in the subjective (information) world of OA, of course OA's information itself and a kind of illusion of what "an" OB saw. In the same way, in the totally distinct subjective world OB, there is of course the information of OB, and the illusion of what "an" OA saw. And these two have a priori nothing to do with one another.
And this is exactly the description MWI gives, except that MWI DOES give a physically objective description of the information possessing unit: namely the specific quantum state of object A or object B, which is entangled with the observer state we are considering, while this is denied to exist in RQM: there are just these subjective, intuitive "information" worlds associated with each object that might serve as an observer, and OF WHICH THE INFORMATION IS NOT CODED IN ANY OBJECTIVE STATE (and as such, NOT accessible to another physical object through a physical interaction).
So the fallacy in this entire construction is to say that there is some kind of objectivity (even though systems don't have objective states, and hence don't have objective memories, and hence don't have objective information) to the "agreement between observers" because in each individual subjective world there seems to be agreement with its own illusions, and the object of this agreement is different in each subjective world.
The only way to have these two subjective worlds agree, is by making their information physically available in an objective state. But this then misses the entire point of RQM.
Now, you accuse me of dragging in "consciousness" in the RQM discussion, but there's no way out: if there is no objective state to be attached to an object, which might correspond to the information possessed in the whole discussion, by said object, then there is no objective physical container for that information, and we are hence FORCED to consider a subjective world that goes with it (call it a consciousness if you want) and where this information "lives", so to say, as there's no room for it in any objective state.
And from the moment that this information IS objective and physical, so that it CAN be asked by another observer to enter its information world, then the entire issue of non-locality rears its ugly head again, because then the answers HERE depend on what objective information was obtained THERE in response to what question.
Really, there's no way around: locality, the predicted probabilities by QM, and Bell's theorem are ONLY compatible when there are multiple sets of results, a potentially different one for each observer. Of course, if there is only one observer, there's no issue. But when there are 2 observers, any talking away of the issue also talks away the non-locality of a FTL telephone.
What RQM describes is ONE such set. As such, it is entirely correct, but needs intuitive concepts for which it doesn't give a physical description, such as "information possessed by an observer" and "the questions asked by the observer to the system" (this last thing is another way of introducing a preferred basis, as in Copenhagen).
From the PoV of one such set, the "rest of the world" can indeed be described as a quantum state to which the Born rule is applied when asking the questions.
MWI gives you exactly all that, PLUS an "objective description of reality", PLUS a description of the state of an observer, plus a way to investigate in an objective physical process that happens during "measurement" (something that doesn't make sense in RQM: an observer just "gets answers to its questions, and how this answer comes about is left in the middle).
So, again, I fail to see what issue RQM resolves, apart from the points that were already dealt with from a single-observer viewpoint in MWI, with which I can identify it, if we leave out all the "objective" talk.
In fact, I would even see RQM as a precursor to MWI. Indeed, let us follow the following reasoning: we take as a first viewpoint, that there is a subjective experience (a la Descartes that seems to correspond to "information" such an experience has about a hypothetical objective world.
And the subjective experience wonders if it can make sense out of any objectively existing reality.
All what is empirical is of course subjective, as in the end it is an experience by the subjective experience. Those empirical observations by the subject make it conclude to the fact that it can "know" stuff (first Rovelli postulate), a kind of complementarity (~ second Rovelli postulate) and the superposition principle (third Rovelli postulate). From this, the subjective experience can deduce an algorithm (= formalism of quantum theory) to calculate probabilities of his future answers to empirical questions, all still within its subjective existence of course.
This is where RQM stops. It explains simply the algorithm the subjective experience has of the probabilities of its future answers to questions. But the subjective experience doesn't know whether this means anything, beyond its own experience.
But we could go further:
The subjective experience wonders if there can be a logical construction which might describe an objective reality from which its subjective experiences are drawn, and then wonders if the "algorithm" could not somehow correspond to some objective world out there.
And lo and behold, it can ! It is sufficient to call a certain set of experiences corresponding to certain answers, his preferred states, of which he experiences (of course) one, and say that there's an objective world corresponding to a unitary structure. If he then draws this conclusion to the end, he arrives at MWI.
There still remains something of the irreducible character of subjective experience in this model, in that the subjective experience now has to identify itself with specific states in the overall wavefunction and declare the probability of being one of the several possible to be the hilbert norm, but this is way better than not assuming even the existence of anything outside its own subjective existence, no ?