Interpretation of QM in the Heisenberg Picture

In summary: C.In summary, the Heisenberg Picture version of Born rule is that a Born rule projection occurs when the state vectors of a system are replaced by the state W =|ψ><ψ| / <ψ|ψ>.
  • #1
Federation 2005
20
2
TL;DR Summary
There is no Heisenberg Picture version of the Born Rule.
This is in reference to a question, never fully resolved, posed here:

https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/interpretation-of-the-heisenberg-picture-in-qm.816449/
The von Neumann postulates for Quantum Theory - Evolution (Schrödinger's equation) and Projection (Born's rule) are always framed in the Schödinger Picture. The Heisenberg Picture version of Evolution is the Heisenberg equations of motion. The essence of the original question is: what about the other postulate, Projection? What is the Heisenberg Picture version of Born rule?

Well, apparently someone fell asleep at the switch there! There is no formulation. It's a gap in the foundations that's never been addressed, and apparently never even been noticed. It looks like nobody's ever gotten around to actually writing down what the Born rule looks like in the Heisenberg Picture!

Do a literature search. You're not going to find anything on "Heisenberg Picture" + "Born Rule". For instance, here's a literature search on arXiv.
https://arxiv.org/search/?query=Heiseberg+Picture+Born+Rule&searchtype=all&source=headerAs of 2019 June, empty. A web search won't do much better.

A Google Scholar search is mostly empty. You may find this entry there:

https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00999722/
which basically notes ... that the Heisenberg picture has no Born Rule (and tries to explain why it's missing). It's a review of one of Born and Heisenberg's early works coming out of Solvay 1927. In fact, you can find the Born-Heisenberg paper right here at Solvay

http://www.solvayinstitutes.be/html/solvayconf_physics.html
in the conference proceedings starting on page 143.

The treatment of the Born rule is the central focus of all divergence of opinion on what quantum theory means and lies at the center of the Measurement Problem. That underscores how serious this gap in the foundation actually is. And the presence of this gap also shows why there is a divergence of opinion in the first place. Einstein was right, Quantum Theory is incomplete, and this is the point where it's incomplete. No Heiseberg Picture-Born Rule exists.

The closest treatment to this that you get are treatments of open systems quantum theory (which hybridize classical and quantum dynamics) or - more generally - treatments that hybridize classical and quantum dynamics. Noteworthy is a recent one found on arXiv, which successfully hybridizes classical gravity with quantum theory

"A Post Quantum Theory of Classical Gravity" https://arxiv.org/abs/1811.03116

Needless to say, its main talking point is that a resolution of the Measurement Problem emerges for free from its hybrid dynamics.

In the Heisenberg Picture, states are timeless. The Born rule is the rule for wave function collapse. But if states are timeless, then what exactly is changing when a Born rule projection occurs? And when and where? So, you can already see there that there's a basic problem with consistency here. How are you going to get a Born or Lueder's projection to happen when Heisenberg states are timeless?

This also puts permanent No Go on all the endeavors to "explain away" the Born rule. For, any attempt to do so will, upon success, end up making everything timeless. If you have nothing but Evolution, then in the Heisenberg Picture this translates into nothing but timelessness; and nothing ever changes. A kind of Zeno's Paradox is waiting at the end of the tunnel for all the {Decoherence, Everett, Consistent Histories} people! And when they get there at the end of the tunnel, it will jump out and say "Hi! Surprised to see me?!"

Here's an attempt from within the Everett camp to address the question
https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0103079
The very thing people want to achieve by these alternate interpretations (removing the Born rule) is the very thing you want to avoid! The beauty of the question "what is the Heisenberg Picture Born Rule" is that it draws focus to the point where the goals conflict.

It gets even deeper than this. The disagreement that supposedly lies between General Relativity (GR) and Quantum Theory (QT), particularly on its treatment of time, is only a gap between General Relativity and the Schrödinger Picture. The Heisenberg Picture's treatment of time already meshes quite well with General Relativity's treatment of time. In particular, the Heisenberg equations when generalized to fields, become partial differential equations whose forms do not single out any dimension of spacetime. They treat time and space on an equal footing.

So, the gap widely held to lie between GR and QT has been misplaced: it's not QT vs. GR, but is actually (Schrödinger QT) vs. (Heisenberg QT & GR).

To try and resolve this discrepancy, you first need to use replace state vectors|ψ> by what may be more properly regarded as the state W =|ψ><ψ| / <ψ|ψ>; and generalize this further to include mixed states. The Schrödinger equation iħ d|ψ>/dt = H|ψ> then becomes iħ dW/dt = [H, W]. The Born rule produces a transition W → Σ_a P_a W P_a upon measure of a quantity A in state W, where A quantizes to the operator  = Σ_a a P_a, with eigenvalues (a) and eigenspace projectors P_a.

A second measurement of, say, a quantity C would then produce a projection Σ_a P_a W P_a → Σ_{ac} P'_c P_a W P_a P'_c where the P'_c are the projectors for C. The dependence on time-ordering can be encapsulated by using the time-ordering pseudo-operator T[] and its reversal T'[] to write this as Σ_{ac} T'[P_a P'_c] W T[P_a P'_c]. All of this will survive intact upon conversion to the Heisenberg picture, except that the operators, projectors will now have the time dependence and W will be time-independent; and the Schrödinger equation on states will be replaced by the Heisenberg equation on the quantized operators that correspond to physical quantities.

This generalizes to space-time form, where the time dependence of the projectors and operators now becomes dependence on space-time points. The most important feature to note is that the space-time coordinates are now on an equal footing, and the only vestige of causal ordering that remains is in the appearance of the T[] and T'[] brackets.

This introduces an effective time dependence on the timeless Heisenberg states. But, unlike the case of the Schrödinger picture, there is no real time dependency remaining in the evolution postulate - at least not for the states. They remain timeless. Instead, the time-dependency has moved over to the other projection postulate. To make this work consistently, you need the following structure:

(1) a point cloud that contains all the points at which applications of the Born rule will occur
(2) a network of Heisenberg states, written as mixed states W in general
(3) associated with each state, a partition of the point cloud into a "before" set and "after" set. Their causal ordering should be consistent so that no point in the after set has a timeline or null curve that leads to a point in the before set.
(4) a transition between any 2 states whose before/after sets agree on all but a finite number of points; the transition being given in a form similar to what described above.

Each state, despite being timeless, encodes a "now" by virtue of how it partitions the point cloud into a before and after set. So, each application of the Born rule bumps up the "now" by a notch. So, in effect, a flow of time is introduced, even though the operators themselves and dynamics do not single out any "now".

This actually gets pretty close to what Smolin described and call out for here in this lecture

Lee Smolin Public Lecture: Time Reborn


in which he presents some of the key talking points of his "Time Reborn" book

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Time_Reborn
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Well it's pretty simple. You have the quantum state ##\psi## giving the probabilities for various outcomes of an observable ##A##.

You can either hold ##A## fixed in which case the state evolves as ##\psi(t)## giving time dependent values for ##A##'s outcomes, or ##\psi## is fixed but assigns probabilities to each member of the indexed family ##A(t)## which are time evolutions of ##A##.

The end result is the same: time dependent probabilities for each of ##A##'s outcomes.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes microsansfil, bhobba and Nugatory
  • #3
small correction: “same: time”
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #4
Quantum theory is independent of the picture of time evolution. You can define everything in a completely general picture (Dirac), where both the operators representing observables and the statistical operator are time dependent. Born's rule is valid in the same form in all pictures. That's, because the transformation from one picture to another is given by a (time-dependent) unitary transformation, and quantum theory is invariant under arbitrary unitary transformations.

Born's rule always is the same. If the system is prepared in a state described by the statistical operator ##\hat{\rho}(t)## and ##O_j## are a complete set of independent compatible observables, represented by self-adjoint operators ##\hat{O}_j(t)## and ##|t,o_j \rangle## are a complete set of orthonormal eigenvectors, then the probability to find the values ##(o_j)## when measuring the ##O_j## at time ##t## is given by
$$P(t,o_j)=\langle o_j,t|\hat{\rho}(t)|o_j,t \rangle,$$
which is the most general form of Born's rule.

For a pure state you have ##\hat{\rho}=|\psi,t \rangle \langle \psi,t \rangle,##
where ##|\psi,t \rangle## is a normalized ket. Then it boils down to the original Born's rule for pure states,
$$P(t,o_j)=|\langle o_j,t|\psi,t \rangle|^2.$$
The Heisenberg picture is the one, where the time dependence of the operators is chosen such that ##\hat{\rho}## is time-independent (except for explicit time dependence, which I don't discuss here at all for simplicity) and ##\hat{O}_j(t)##.
 
  • Like
Likes microsansfil and bhobba
  • #5
DarMM said:
Well it's pretty simple. [...] ##\psi## is fixed but assigns probabilities to each member of the indexed family ##A(t)## which are time evolutions of ##A##.
But the original question was
Federation 2005 said:
The Born rule is the rule for wave function collapse. But if states are timeless, then what exactly is changing when a Born rule projection occurs?
Thus the question is not about the part of Born's rule specifying the probabilities, but about the second part specifying the state reduction.

At a state reduction, the discontinuous time evolution of the position and momentum operator fails to preserve the canonical commutation rule.
 
  • #6
Doesn't it just work the same though? In the Heisenberg picture your state ##\psi## is an assignment of expectations for all future times. When you make a measurement you simply assign a new state ##\phi## with different expectations for future times.

I don't think anything really changes.
 
  • #7
DarMM said:
Doesn't it just work the same though? In the Heisenberg picture your state ##\psi## is an assignment of expectations for all future times. When you make a measurement you simply assign a new state ##\phi## with different expectations for future times.

I don't think anything really changes.
But this is not the Heisenberg picture in the sense of post #1, where the state is time-independent, hence never changes. This is related to our discussion starting here of the inequivalence of the Schrödinger and the Heisenberg picture observed by Fröhlich.
 
  • #8
I mean ultimately it's going to be just the non-commutative generalization of conditional expectations, i.e. a map ##\mathcal{E}## from one algebra ##\mathcal{M}## to a subalgebra ##\mathcal{N}## obeying:
$$\phi(PM) = \phi(P\mathcal{E}(M))$$
where ##P \in \mathcal{P}(\mathcal{N})##, the projectors onto the subalgebra in analogue with the classical formula.
Due to states being dual to the algebra you can simply transfer this map onto the state to get collapse.

However I never took the Heisenberg picture to be that the state literally never changes even upon measurement, but that the state does not undergo unitary evolution.
 
  • #9
DarMM said:
Doesn't it just work the same though? In the Heisenberg picture your state ##\psi## is an assignment of expectations for all future times. When you make a measurement you simply assign a new state ##\phi## with different expectations for future times.
This is the subjective view, where one assigns states based on ones knowledge, and hence treats the collapse as conditional expectation. But there are objective observations of state reduction in continuous measurement, where collapse is most naturally part of the dynamics, and proceeding in this way seems inappropriate.
DarMM said:
However I never took the Heisenberg picture to be that the state literally never changes even upon measurement, but that the state does not undergo unitary evolution.
With this interpretation, the riddle in post #1 is of course solved. But one needs to make precise what the Heisenberg picture should mean in a nonunitary context, and there are several possibilities, depending on which property one wants to preserve. You picked the trivial one.
 
  • #10
A. Neumaier said:
But the original question was

Thus the question is not about the part of Born's rule specifying the probabilities, but about the second part specifying the state reduction.

At a state reduction, the discontinuous time evolution of the position and momentum operator fails to preserve the canonical commutation rule.
No matter, whether you believe in state collapse or not, mathematically the wave function is always the same in all pictures of time dependence since
$$\psi(t,o_j)=\langle o_j,t|\psi,t \rangle$$
is picture independent (modulo phases, which are irrelevant since not the wavefunction is a physical quantity but it's modulus squared).
 
  • #11
A. Neumaier said:
This is the subjective view, where one assigns states based on ones knowledge, and hence treats the collapse as conditional expectation. But there are objective observations of state reduction in continuous measurement, where collapse is most naturally part of the dynamics, and proceeding in this way seems inappropriate.

With this interpretation, the riddle in post #1 is of course solved. But one needs to make precise what the Heisenberg picture should mean in a nonunitary context, and there are several possibilities, depending on which property one wants to preserve. You picked the trivial one.
Is there a good reference for this ambiguity of the Heisenberg picture? The "trivial one" is the only one I've ever heard of.
 
  • #12
DarMM said:
Is there a good reference for this ambiguity of the Heisenberg picture? The "trivial one" is the only one I've ever heard of.
There seems to be no discussion of this in the literature, as post #1 noticed. Before Fröhlich's paper I didn't even realize the trivial possibility you mentioned as "the only one you heard of".

But a lot is known about the nontrivial choice that fixes the Heisenberg state once and for all and puts the stochasticity usually associated with the state into the Heisenberg dynamics. See the book by Accardi, Lu, and Volovich. This is interesting math and physics!
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #14
But there are objective observations of state reduction in continuous measurement, where collapse is most naturally part of the dynamics, and proceeding in this way seems inappropriate.

Wouldn't we just stochastically evolve our operator? Consider the operator
$$|o_j,t_0\rangle\langle o_j,t_0|$$
If we are interested in the likelihood of measuring ##o_j## at time ##t_2##, we would evolve our operator using normal unitary time-evolution
$$U_{t_0\rightarrow t_2}$$
But if we wanted to evolve the operator to ##t_2## given some measurement ##p_j## at time ##t_1##, we would instead use the non-unitary evolution
$$U_{t_0\rightarrow t_1}|p_j,t_1\rangle\langle p_j,t_1|U_{t_1\rightarrow t_2}$$

[edit] - clarified
[edit 2] - Added quote I was responding to
 
Last edited:
  • #15
SFXMan said:
if we wanted to evolve the operator to ##t_2## given some measurement ##p_j## at time ##t_1##, we would instead use the non-unitary evolution
$$U_{t_0\rightarrow t_1}|p_j,t_1\rangle\langle p_j,t_1|U_{t_1\rightarrow t_2}$$
This cannot work well. The problem is that for consistency one must assume that measurements may have already been taken in the past, unknown to us. Then the operators undergoing the nonunitary evolution no longer have the properties of the original operators, as commutation relations are not invariant under nonunitary evolution; so it is not clear how we have to represent the observables of interest at the time we begin to model the evolution.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes eloheim, bhobba and dextercioby
  • #16
I might be misunderstanding the problem but: In the Schroedinger picture, we would handle uncertainty about whether a measurement has occurred by replacing a sharp wavefunction collapse with a nonunitary time-evolution into a mixed state. In the Heisenberg picture, we would presumably apply the analogous time-evolution to the observable in question.

More generally, since in both pictures we are ultimately computing amplitudes for sequences of measurements at different times (a la some histories formalism), I think there's always an equivalence between folding time-evolution into the last observable (Heisenberg) and the initial quantum state (Schroedinger)

But there is likely some subtlety I am missing to the conversation.
 
  • #17
Again, there's no dependency of quantum theory on the picture of time evolution used. By construction (sic!) quantum theory is picture independent. It's only a different but equivalent mathematical description of the dynamics. Different pictures are transformed from one to each other by unitary transformations, and QT is invariant under unitary transformations. This is a mathematical fact and has nothing to do with any obscure interpretational problem.

It's a nuissance that in this forum any quantum-mechanics question is deformed into some pseudo-problem of interpretation, and then students eager to learn physics get confused by those pseudo-problems rather than first learning the math and physics as it is really applied in real-world labs!

It's as in classical electrodynamics: The physics is completely invariant under gauge transformations. Describing the same physical situation in, say the Coulomb gauge leads to precisely the same physics outcome as when describing the same situation in the Lorenz gauge. There's no direct physical meaning of the potentials to begin with, and there's thus no problem with an apparent instantaneous interaction in describing the scalar potential in the Coulomb gauge. All the instantaneously-looking interactions cancel out when finally calculating the physical fields, which contain only retarded integrals, no matter whether you do the calculation in Coulomb or Lorenz gauge.

The same holds for QT: It's invariant under picture transformations (i.e., time-dependent unitary transformations), and if there were a fundamental problem in the Heisenberg picture there'd be a fundamental problem in any other picture either, because all pictures are equivalent!
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #18
SFXMan said:
But there is likely some subtlety I am missing to the conversation.
Position and momentum should be conjugate at all times, ##[q(t),p(t)]=i\hbar##. This is the case when ##p(t)## and ##q(t)## transform unitarily with time but not when they undergo your proposed nonunitary change.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba and vanhees71
  • #19
A. Neumaier said:
Position and momentum should be conjugate at all times, ##[q(t),p(t)]=i\hbar##. This is the case when ##p(t)## and ##q(t)## transform unitarily with time but not when they undergo your proposed nonunitary change.
Ok I think I better understand what you are looking for. The nonunitary evolution I suggested earlier actually describes a sequence of probabilistic measurement outcomes, rather than just the outcome ##o_j##, and so it is not just a description of ##o_j##.
 
  • #20
Non-unitary time evolution comes into the game of QT only if you consider effective theories for describing open quantum systems ignoring some information (on purpose and necessity to handle very complex systems like the interaction of a single particle with a many-body system), which usually leads to quantum master equations (e.g., Lindblad equations), kinetic theory, Langevin/Fokker-Planck Eqs. etc. etc. This is a very wide and important as well as very interesting topic, but it's fully consistent with standard QT, and indeed as @A. Neumaier said, on the fundamental QM level, there's no problem with Born's rule and all the consequences, including the Heisenberg-Robertson uncertainty principle within the Heisenberg (or any other) picture of time evolution.
 
  • #21
vanhees71 said:
Non-unitary time evolution comes into the game of QT only if you consider effective theories for describing open quantum systems ignoring some information (on purpose and necessity to handle very complex systems like the interaction of a single particle with a many-body system), which usually leads to quantum master equations (e.g., Lindblad equations), kinetic theory, Langevin/Fokker-Planck Eqs. etc. etc.
The non-unitarity appears only in the Schrödinger or interaction picture, where the equations you mention reside.

In the Heisenberg picture, only unitary evolution is sensible since commutation relations must be preserved, and the appropriate unitary formulation for open systems in the Heisenberg picture is the one in terms of random operators, as in Accardi's book.
 
  • #22
No, the equations are picture independent, as is the Schrödinger wave equation, ##\langle o_j,t|\psi,t \rangle## is the same, no matter how you "distribute the mathematical time dependence" to state kets and observable-operators or, equivalently, their complete eigen bases ##|o_j,t \rangle##.

Commutation relations are the same in any picture, because any two pictures are by definition (sic!) related through unitary transformations.
 
  • #23
vanhees71 said:
No, the equations are picture independent, as is the Schrödinger wave equation, ##\langle o_j,t|\psi,t \rangle## is the same, no matter how you "distribute the mathematical time dependence" to state kets and observable-operators or, equivalently, their complete eigen bases ##|o_j,t \rangle##.

Commutation relations are the same in any picture, because any two pictures are by definition (sic!) related through unitary transformations.
In a dissipative system, the Hamiltonian is not self-adjoint, hence the equivalence of the pictures makes no longer sense. If one transforms by a similarity transform to preserve commutation relations, one destroys the symmetry between bras and kets assumed in the Schrödinger picture.
 
Last edited:
  • #24
Can't we just construct histories in either picture and assign them probabilities (provided certain consistency conditions are met)? Each possible history would then represent a possible stochastic evolution of our system, no?
 
  • #25
SFXMan said:
Can't we just construct histories in either picture and assign them probabilities (provided certain consistency conditions are met)? Each possible history would then represent a possible stochastic evolution of our system, no?
The question is how to do it consistently so that the same assignments result for both pictures. This does not seem possible in a Heisenberg picture in which the state remains fixed when a measurement on it is performed.
 
  • #27
A. Neumaier said:
In a dissipative system, the Hamiltonian is not self-adjoint, hence the equivalence of the pictures makes no longer sense. If one transforms by a similarity transform to preserve commutation relations, one destroys the symmetry between bras and kets assumed in the Schrödinger picture.
Dissipative systems can sometimes be modeled by Hamiltonians which are not self-adjoint but the Hamiltonian in the Lindblad equation is. And the Lindblad equation can also be written in the Heisenberg picture. How does this relate to your argument?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #28
kith said:
Dissipative systems can sometimes be modeled by Hamiltonians which are not self-adjoint but the Hamiltonian in the Lindblad equation is. And the Lindblad equation can also be written in the Heisenberg picture. How does this relate to your argument?
The Heisenberg dynamics you linked to is mathematically fine but conceptually flawed, as it does not preserve commutation rules. In particular, if ##X## stands for the position or momentum operator at the initial time, one of the two cannot be a position or momentum operator at later times. What then assures us that it is allowed to be one at the initial time?
 
  • #29
A. Neumaier said:
In a dissipative system, the Hamiltonian is not self-adjoint, hence the equivalence of the pictures makes no longer sense. If one transforms by a similarity transform to preserve commutation relations, one destroys the symmetry between bras and kets assumed in the Schrödinger picture.
This has nothing to do with the joice of the picture, but it's how to build an effective many-body theory. Of course the effective dynamics of an open system is not described by unitary time evolution, but that's why you deal with picture-independent quantities to begin with to build effective theories. E.g., to get the Boltzmann equation from QFT you work with Green's functions, which are picture independent as well (correlation functions, i.e., averages over field-operator products ).
 
  • #30
vanhees71 said:
Of course the effective dynamics of an open system is not described by unitary time evolution, but that's why you deal with picture-independent quantities to begin with to build effective theories. E.g., to get the Boltzmann equation from QFT you work with Green's functions, which are picture independent as well (correlation functions, i.e., averages over field-operator products ).
The only point I wanted to make is that because of the lack of unitarity, the Lindblad equations for open systems have no good Heisenberg picture, but only a mathematical rewrite without consistent interpretation.

The Boltzmann equations are equations for expectation values, not (as the Heisenberg equations) for observables.
 
  • #31
The Heisenberg equations are equations for operators that represent observables in the Heisenberg picture. The operators themselves are not observables, for the very reason of not being picture independent. For the analogous reason the potentials are not observable fields in classical electrodynamics for the very reason not being gauge independent.

Now I'm a bit confused about your statement about the Lindblad equation. Are you saying it's picture dependent? How can it then be a proper quantum master equation? I guess, I've to refresh my memory about it. I think, Weinberg has a good presentation of it in his QM book...
 
  • #32
vanhees71 said:
for operators that represent observables in the Heisenberg picture.
This is nitpicking. I follow the usual practice that tolerates an abuse of language and identifies the two.

vanhees71 said:
Now I'm a bit confused about your statement about the Lindblad equation. Are you saying it's picture dependent?
The Lindblad equation is a differential equation for density matrices generalizing von Neumann's equation for the unitary case to open systems. So it is tied to the Schrödinger picture. Dropping the double commutator terms in the equation leaves a nonhermitian effective Hamiltonian.

Of course one can rewrite anything in the Schrodinger picture into something that seemingly looks like a Heisenberg picture, but for open systems there is no natural self-adjoint Hamiltonian to make such a rewriting natural (producing operators that have a meaningful interpretation) or useful (never saw it used in practice).
vanhees71 said:
How can it then be a proper quantum master equation?
All quantum master equations are equations for density matrices or probability distributions, hence in the Schrödinger picture.
 
  • #33
If it's for probability distributions or matrix elements of the statistical operator, i.e., in the notation used already above,
$$\rho(t,o_j,o_{j'}) = \langle o_j,t|\hat{\rho}(t)|o_j',t \rangle,$$
it should be picture independent, since this matrix element is picture independent.

If it's for statistical operators ##\hat{\rho}(t)##, then making approximations, it's picture dependent. Then, of course, you have to stick to this one picture used to derive the approximation, but sounds pretty dangerous to me as a physicist, because approximations need some physical intuition, which can go easily astray if you work with unphysical quantities. I guess, however, that's not the case for the Lindblad equation since it's pretty well established as a working approximation to describe open quantum systems. I've to reread Weinberg's chapter on it.
 
  • #34
vanhees71 said:
If it's for probability distributions or matrix elements of the statistical operator, i.e., in the notation used already above,
$$\rho(t,o_j,o_{j'}) = \langle o_j,t|\hat{\rho}(t)|o_j',t \rangle,$$
it should be picture independent, since this matrix element is picture independent.

If it's for statistical operators ##\hat{\rho}(t)##, then making approximations, it's picture dependent. Then, of course, you have to stick to this one picture used to derive the approximation, but sounds pretty dangerous to me as a physicist, because approximations need some physical intuition, which can go easily astray if you work with unphysical quantities. I guess, however, that's not the case for the Lindblad equation since it's pretty well established as a working approximation to describe open quantum systems. I've to reread Weinberg's chapter on it.
The derivation is usually performed in the interaction picture of the big, unitary system. But the reduced dynamics is formulated as Lindblad equation in the Schrödinger picture of the reduced, open system.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #35
A. Neumaier said:
But this is not the Heisenberg picture in the sense of post #1, where the state is time-independent, hence never changes. This is related to our discussion starting here of the inequivalence of the Schrödinger and the Heisenberg picture observed by Fröhlich.
For the searches I've done up to now, apart from Rubin's 2001 ArXiv on the Heisenberg Picture version Everett and some earlier discussions I posted on this in s.p.r, you're the only one I've found discussing this in any depth. I decided to go back to the 1927 Solvay Proceedings and examine the more closely. There's a good retrospective/translation for this
https://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0609184Section 5 deals with the measurement problem; although the discrepancy I raised is absent from its discussion.

This gap is wider than I initially described: for instance, where are the Heisenberg Picture (HP) versions of the canonical quantizaton of General Relativity (GR)? What does the Problem of Time look like in HP? Is it even a paradox when written in HP form (given that the operators' space-time dependence still remains intact)? If the HP version remains intact without any problems, then the Problem of Time is, itself, signalling a non-equivalence of the two pictures for canonically quantized GR and a proof by contradiction that there is no meaningful Schrödinger Picture at all in that setting. Gauge invariance (diffeomorphism) is the key issue there; so this reference might be relevant.

The Heisenberg versus the Schroedinger picture and the problem of gauge invariance
Dan Solomon
2007 June 26
https://arxiv.org/abs/0706.3867
Excerpted from the abstract:
"We will show that, although the two pictures are formally equivalent, the Heisenberg picture is gauge invariant but that the Schroedinger picture is not. This suggests that the proper way to formulate QFT is to use the Heisenberg picture."
 

1. What is the Heisenberg Picture in quantum mechanics?

The Heisenberg Picture is one of the two main formalisms used in quantum mechanics to describe the evolution of a quantum system over time. In this picture, the operators representing physical quantities, such as position and momentum, are time-independent, while the state of the system evolves with time.

2. How does the Heisenberg Picture differ from the Schrödinger Picture?

In the Schrödinger Picture, the operators are time-dependent and the state of the system remains constant over time. In contrast, the Heisenberg Picture has time-independent operators and the state of the system evolves with time. This leads to different mathematical formulations and interpretations of quantum mechanics.

3. What is the significance of the Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle in the Heisenberg Picture?

The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle states that certain pairs of physical quantities, such as position and momentum, cannot be known simultaneously with perfect accuracy. In the Heisenberg Picture, this is reflected in the fact that the operators representing these quantities do not commute, meaning their values cannot be determined simultaneously with certainty.

4. How does the Heisenberg Picture handle time evolution of observables?

In the Heisenberg Picture, the time evolution of observables is described by the Heisenberg equation of motion, which relates the time derivative of an observable to its commutator with the system's Hamiltonian. This allows for the prediction of how an observable will change over time without explicitly solving the Schrödinger equation.

5. What are some criticisms of the Heisenberg Picture?

One criticism of the Heisenberg Picture is that it can be difficult to interpret physically, as the operators do not represent directly observable quantities. Additionally, some argue that the time-independent operators in this picture do not accurately reflect the dynamic nature of quantum systems. However, the Heisenberg Picture remains a valuable tool for calculating and predicting the behavior of quantum systems.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
33
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
40
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
398
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
758
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
76
Views
5K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
8
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
15
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
16
Views
2K
Replies
8
Views
984
Back
Top