A Is Bohmian mechanics a convenient ontological overcommitment?

gentzen
Science Advisor
Gold Member
Messages
1,101
Reaction score
833
Collapse theories (like GRW) only need extremely few collapses to reproduce macroscopic observations, and actually must limit themselves to extremely view collapses to avoid being experimentally distinguishable with current technology from standard QM. Being too generous with world splitting in MWI is also a (not uncommon) mistake, as Lev Vaidman indicates with words like "has been justly criticized".

Therefore, the fact that Bohmian mechanics can get away with having a precise trajectory for every particle fascinates me. When I first became familiar with Bohmian mechanics, it was rather the opposite: I found it confusing why Bohmian mechanics doesn't need trajectories for inner degrees of freedom of the particles like spin. Today, I rather wonder whether Bohmian mechanics could not easily get away with ommiting some of its precise trajectories, for example all trajectories for photons. This is what I mean by my question whether Bohmian mechanics a convenient ontological overcommitment.

However, the reason why I ask this question now is that Demystifier's paper Solipsistic hidden variables also seems to raise this question: what happens if many of the precise trajectories are omitted from Bohmian mechanics? But the paper seems mostly concerned about what can be gained by omitting trajectories, for example in terms of reducing the non-locality of the theory. I would rather like to know what is lost by omitting (a subset of the) trajectories, and whether anything important is lost at all, i.e. whether is it just a matter of convenience that every particle has a trajectory?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
Physics news on Phys.org
You can omit some trajectories, e.g. those of photons as you suggested, without loosing much. But if you omit all trajectories, then you have to explain why measurements have outcomes at all.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
Photons cannot have trajectories. They don't even have a position observable. I don't think that we have a convincing Bohmian reinterpretation of local relativistic QFT yet. For non-relativistic QT in the first-quantization formulation BM is a consistent theory without much additional merit compared to standard statistically interpreted QT. At least I've not seen any experiment that depicts the Bohmian trajectories of slow massive particles, e.g., in a double-slit experiment or something equivalent.
 
  • Like
Likes CelHolo and jbergman
Demystifier said:
You can omit some trajectories, e.g. those of photons as you suggested, without loosing much.
Do I just lose some convenience and elegance, or also something more substantial. For example, the trajectories in BM are continuous (probably even infinitely differentiable) and deterministic. (Those properties would be hard to recovered, if you start with the consistent histories framework, and then try to complete it by position based refinements.) And there is a canonical probability distribution on the particle positions in BM, plus typicality arguments why we are allowed to assume that the actual particle positions are consistent with that distribution, if the system is sufficiently big. (Those properties are absent in some other "deterministic non-local hidden variable" interpretations.)

Demystifier said:
But if you omit all trajectories, then you have to explain why measurements have outcomes at all.
My purpose with this question is not to omit all trajectories, or mutilate BM in other ways. It is rather the opposite: how much would I mutilate BM, if I just tried to omit a subset of the trajectories. The example with the photons was just to make the question more concrete.
 
gentzen said:
I would rather like to know what is lost by omitting trajectories, and whether anything important is lost at all, i.e. whether is it just a matter of convenience that every particle has a trajectory?
Strange question. What is lost by dropping superfluous metaphysical baggage? Trajectories are (occasionally useful) classical fiction, but they are also a burden. How can you make sense of the idea that electrons are identical, when each has its own trajectory? Nature would always "know" which electron interacted with which photon. But there are no such facts of the matter. Nature uses a different kind of bookkeeping.
 
WernerQH said:
Strange question. What is lost by dropping superfluous metaphysical baggage?
Well, the mathematical model might become more complicated. From my perspective, analyzing fictional mathematical models can provide useful insight:
I believe in a principle of 'conservation of difficulty'. This allows me to believe that mathematics stays useful, even if it would be fictional. I believe that often the main difficulties of a real world problem will still be present in a fictional mathematical model. Therefore analyzing that model and understanding the difficulties in that context will provide useful insight into the real world problem.
... physicists ... trust in 'conservation of difficulty' is often less pronounced. As a consequence, physics fictionalism has a hard time (...). So instead of accepting Bohmian mechanics as a useful fictional model with huge potential for analyzing various difficulties of quantum mechanics (and extracting insights about the real world from it), it was initially dismissed for being too obviously fictional.

WernerQH said:
How can you make sense of the idea that electrons are identical, when each has its own trajectory?
Well, BM provides you a model were the QM predictions are still satisfied, despite this paradox. So it provides you the opportunity to analyse how that is possible, in one specific fictional model. (I am a bit less keen on creating or destroying particles, because the original BM proposal doesn't include those effects.)
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
gentzen said:
It is rather the opposite: how much would I mutilate BM, if I just tried to omit a subset of the trajectories. The example with the photons was just to make the question more concrete.
If you do that, it's still (a version of) Bohmian mechanics.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #10
vanhees71 said:
As expected they measure the position of photon-detection events. There is no photon-position observable you can measure.
So what? Are you saying that what they measure is not a trajectory?
 
  • Haha
Likes WernerQH
  • #11
gentzen said:
Well, the mathematical model might become more complicated.
Wouldn't you call Minkowski's formulation of electrodynamics simpler than Maxwell's? Of course, the actual calculations remain essentially the same.
 
  • #12
WernerQH said:
Wouldn't you call Minkowski's formulation of electrodynamics simpler than Maxwell's? Of course, the actual calculations remain essentially the same.
I have now edited the question to make it even clearer that I was only talking about omitting a subset of the trajectories, not of omitting all trajectories. (Even Demystifier himself also included that interpretation of my question in his answer, so apparently it was not clear enough from context.)

The point of having the trajectories in the model is that it allows you to get rid of the concept of "objective randomness" in your model. So you reduced mysterious "quantum randomness" to familiar "classical randomness". But interestingly, your model became quite non-local by doing so. So by "conservation of difficulty", you might start to wonder whether this connection between non-locality and randomness is also important for the real world problem. And answering that question is what Bell did.
 
  • #13
Demystifier said:
So what? Are you saying that what they measure is not a trajectory?
How can something have a trajectory which doesn't even have a position observable? To think about photons as little particle-like bullets is always wrong!
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy
  • #14
vanhees71 said:
How can something have a trajectory which doesn't even have a position observable? To think about photons as little particle-like bullets is always wrong!
So no experimental result could refute your theoretical argument that photon can't have a trajectory? Then your theoretical argument is not falsifiable in the Popper sense, and hence it's not scientific.
 
  • #15
If cannot measure something it's simply not defined. In this sense it's not scientific indeed, and that's my argument all the time.
 
  • Like
Likes CelHolo
  • #16
vanhees71 said:
If cannot measure something it's simply not defined.
But they measured something. And that something is even theoretically defined. It's just not defined the way you are used to.
 
  • #17
It's just another interference pattern. But if you are so inclined, you see photon trajectories. It's a kind of Rohrschach test. ;-)
 
  • Haha
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, DennisN, vanhees71 and 2 others
  • #18
vanhees71 said:
Photons cannot have trajectories. They don't even have a position observable. I don't think that we have a convincing Bohmian reinterpretation of local relativistic QFT yet.
For fields a field ontology is more appropriate. The standard reference is

Bohm.D., Hiley, B.J., Kaloyerou, P.N. (1987). An ontological basis for the quantum theory, Phys. Reports 144(6), 321-375.

For a field ontology, the photons are similar to phonons in condensed matter theory, and nobody cares if they have position operators or not. What should have a trajectory is the field itself, ##u(x)##, and its trajectory with be ##u(x,t)##.
vanhees71 said:
For non-relativistic QT in the first-quantization formulation BM is a consistent theory without much additional merit compared to standard statistically interpreted QT.
Except that it solves all the conceptual problems like the measurement problem.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and Demystifier
  • #19
To the original question:

What is lost is some simplicity. What is gained is that it will not matter to you if you don't know how to define the ontology. Say, if you have no idea how to handle fermion fields, because you don't like the particle picture but are influenced too much by the idea that fermion fields themselves are something completely non-classical, you simply don't have to care, the fields where it is already known what to do are sufficient for this variant of Bohmian theory. All what you need is that the measurement devices are visible enough if you can see only those fields where you know how to define the ontology.

So I think this ugly variant is only useful as such an excuse, but has no value as an ultimate theory.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #20
WernerQH said:
Wouldn't you call Minkowski's formulation of electrodynamics simpler than Maxwell's? Of course, the actual calculations remain essentially the same.
The 4-dimensional denotations are a little bit simpler, computations are essentially the same, conceptually it is more complicate because you have to understand how that 4-dimensional formalism translates into what we observe in our 3-dimensional world.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and Demystifier
  • #21
WernerQH said:
How can you make sense of the idea that electrons are identical, when each has its own trajectory?
The idea that "electrons are identical" really means (in Bohmian interpretation) that the pilot wave does not distinguish particles, not that the particles are identical by themselves.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #22
Demystifier said:
The idea that "electrons are identical" really means (in Bohmian interpretation) that the pilot wave does not distinguish particles, not that the particles are identical by themselves.
Of course you can have the personal belief that electrons are distinguishable, that you could label them uniquely, and that these labels would have an objective meaning. But in view of the fact that the wave functions are constructed as determinants (where any dependence on these labels is carefully removed), it strikes me as a strangely uneconomical description.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #23
WernerQH said:
it strikes me as a strangely uneconomical description.
Do you have any idea why Bohmian mechanics is studied in the first place? Certainly not for economic reasons. :oldlaugh:
 
  • Haha
Likes vanhees71
  • #24
Demystifier said:
Do you have any idea why Bohmian mechanics is studied in the first place?
Of course. The plethora of interpretations of QM is a strong indication that we lack true understanding. And I share the view that it is yet to be found. I cannot accept Bohr's philosophy that QM cannot be formulated without the complementary concepts of classical physics, which has somehow rendered fundamental physics as transcendental, beyond human understanding.

Bohmian mechanics, in my opinion, is not radical enough. Its adherents are too strongly tied to the classical concepts of particles and fields.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby and vanhees71
  • #25
WernerQH said:
Bohmian mechanics, in my opinion, is not radical enough. Its adherents are too strongly tied to the classical concepts of particles and fields.
I think they are not strong enough ties to classical concepts. Classical concepts should never be given up without strong enough evidence.
 
  • Like
Likes AndreiB
  • #26
WernerQH said:
Of course. The plethora of interpretations of QM is a strong indication that we lack true understanding. And I share the view that it is yet to be found. I cannot accept Bohr's philosophy that QM cannot be formulated without the complementary concepts of classical physics, which has somehow rendered fundamental physics as transcendental, beyond human understanding.

Bohmian mechanics, in my opinion, is not radical enough. Its adherents are too strongly tied to the classical concepts of particles and fields.
All you need from classical physics for the physics of QT are the spacetime symmetries of Newtonian or special relativistic physics and the general structure of QT as defined on (rigged) Hilbert space and the observable algebras, whose concrete structure follows from the spacetime symmetries. There's nothing transcentdental but just a "symbolism of atomistic measurements", as Schwinger puts it.

That many people after 100 years of modern QT still have a problem to accept that Nature is behaving fundamentally random is not a problem of physics but rather of psychology and philosophy of these individual people. The natural sciences are not to please your epistemological prejudices but to figure out how Nature behaves as objectively and quantitatively observed.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #27
vanhees71 said:
The natural sciences are not to please your epistemological prejudices but to figure out how Nature behaves as objectively and quantitatively observed.
I fully agree. I also believe that Nature behaves fundamentally random, although "randomness" is something that can never be strictly defined. But probability theory and statistics are invaluable.

What Q(F)T is still lacking is a convincing ontology. We disagree what it is about. I think "measurements" cannot be the answer. The formal structure is here to stay, but as physicists we should not only consider the relations between the basic concepts of the theory, but how they relate to the real world.
 
  • Like
Likes Lynch101 and vanhees71
  • #28
WernerQH said:
Bohmian mechanics, in my opinion, is not radical enough.
What's your favored interpretation?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #29
WernerQH said:
although "randomness" is something that can never be strictly defined. But probability theory and statistics are invaluable.

What Q(F)T is still lacking is a convincing ontology.
I guess that "randomness" can still be a bit better defined than in the currently dominant frequentist interpretations and subjective Bayesian interpretations.

For a convincing ontology, accepting true indistinguishabiliy and developping appropriate mental images for both bosons and fermions seems crucial to me. You argued against the Bohmian ontology on that basis, but I believe that trying to understand how this paradox is solved in the Bohmian ontology would actually bring you closer to your goal. (My guess is that if you would do the computation, it is the forced symmetry of the wavefunction together with the non-locality of the particles that restores indistinguishability. Would be interesting whether there is a difference between particles that had a close interaction before, and arbitrary particles.)
 
  • #30
What do you need an "ontology"? At the end you can only observe what you can observe. It's at least not subject of the natural sciences to speculate what further may be "behind" that observable facts.
 
  • #31
vanhees71 said:
What do you need an "ontology"?
It helps to develop an intuitive mental image. It's a very useful thinking tool.
 
  • Like
Likes Lynch101, WernerQH, gentzen and 1 other person
  • #32
vanhees71 said:
What do you need an "ontology"?
For me, the original Bohmian mechanics is an existence proof of a mathematical model. In a sense this is the minimal requirement for an "ontology", but some people expect more.
But not all mathematical models are equally nice as an "ontology". Often mathematical models contain quotient structures. If too much work is hidden in those implicit equivalence relations, then the model risks to become trivial and meaningless. But some of those quotient structures are there to stay, especially those caused by topological constraints.

Understanding such details can give hints why certain things are difficult. For example, A. Neumaier thinks it is possible that non-separable Hilbert spaces might be required for QFT. But that non-separability could also be a hint that some topological information is missing (for example the surfaces in solid state physics), and that different possibilities for that missing information could lead to different results.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #33
vanhees71 said:
At the end you can only observe what you can observe. It's at least not subject of the natural sciences to speculate what further may be "behind" that observable facts.
Also experiments need interpretation! It is not clear what exactly the observable facts are in experiments that claim to simulate "Wigner's friend" or reveal "photon trajectories".
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #34
vanhees71 said:
That many people after 100 years of modern QT still have a problem to accept that Nature is behaving fundamentally random is not a problem of physics but rather of psychology and philosophy of these individual people.
Essentially nobody has a problem with Nature behaving random. I have never seen anybody with conceptual problems in thermodynamics because of randomness.

You seem to have a problem not understanding that your "fundamentally" is your personal metaphysical preference, nothing more. This can be even proven: There exists a deterministic interpretation, thus, fundamental randomness is not interpretation-independent, thus, a metaphysical preference.
vanhees71 said:
The natural sciences are not to please your epistemological prejudices but to figure out how Nature behaves as objectively and quantitatively observed.
Looks more like you think they have to please, instead, your own epistemological prejudices.
 
  • Like
Likes physika and Demystifier
  • #35
Demystifier said:
What's your favored interpretation?
It's a blend of the statistical and the transactional interpretation. But without the "offer" and "confirmation" waves, and also without particles. In my view, it's only the interactions between photons and electrons (events) that are real. As John Bell once wrote:
A piece of matter then is a galaxy of such events.
("Are there quantum jumps?")
 
  • Informative
Likes gentzen and Demystifier
  • #36
gentzen said:
I guess that "randomness" can still be a bit better defined than in the currently dominant frequentist interpretations and subjective Bayesian interpretations.
Yes, there are still debates about the meaning of probability. I consider probability theory an indispensable ingredient of almost all physical theories, much like geometry. My understanding of probability was profoundly changed after my encounter with Jaynes's book "Probability Theory. The Logic of Science". His position is that, given the same facts, all users of probability, if they apply it correctly, must draw the same conclusions.

gentzen said:
For a convincing ontology, accepting true indistinguishabiliy and developping appropriate mental images for both bosons and fermions seems crucial to me.
Absolutely. I think of photons and electrons as useful fiction: lines that we draw between short-lived localized currents (events) that are the real stuff of which the world around us is made. Photons and electrons exist only as correlation functions (propagators) helping us to describe the patterns of events that we observe in space-time. The S-matrix is a tool to predict the likeliness of certain patterns of events, and I think it's significant that all the different diagrams that can be drawn connecting a given set of vertices contribute. There is no fact of the matter whether "this" or "that" electron interacted with "that" photon.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and gentzen
  • #37
WernerQH said:
Also experiments need interpretation! It is not clear what exactly the observable facts are in experiments that claim to simulate "Wigner's friend" or reveal "photon trajectories".
Well, you have a setup and the data. One should be aware that particularly for photons "trajectories" are not defined, because as you say you need also a theory for the interpretation of these data, and the definition of the photon today is QED and not the old quantum theory a la Einstein, where photons are misinterpreted as localizable particles, but the modern definition of a photon implies that there is no position operator for photons to begin with. Even for massive particles, as defined by relativistic QFT, there are limits of their localizability due to the creation and annihilation processes inevitably occurring when trying to localize them, although they admit the definition of a position observable.
 
  • Like
Likes WernerQH
  • #38
vanhees71 said:
Even for massive particles, as defined by relativistic QFT, there are limits of their localizability due to the creation and annihilation processes inevitably occurring when trying to localize them, although they admit the definition of a position observable.
Is this definition Lorentz covariant?
 
  • Like
Likes Sunil and vanhees71
  • #40
vanhees71 said:
Yes, that's the important point. Have a look at Arnold Neumaier's physics FAQ and the references quoted therein:

https://arnold-neumaier.at/physfaq/topics/position.html
https://arnold-neumaier.at/physfaq/topics/localization
As far as I can see, this is not Lorentz covariant. Indeed, it explicitly says: "Note that the position operator is always observer-dependent, in the sense that one must choose a timelike unit vector to distinguish space and time coordinates in the momentum operator. This is due to the fact that the above construction is not invariant under Lorentz boosts"
 
  • #41
In this sense any split of space and time is of course not manifestly Poincare invariant. This holds for classical relativistic physics too.
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
In this sense any split of space and time is of course not manifestly Poincare invariant. This holds for classical relativistic physics too.
But classical position can be defined without a split, as a position in 4-dimensional spacetime. Can a position without split be defined in quantum physics? For instance, if it is defined through ##|x\rangle \equiv \hat{\phi}(x)|0\rangle##, then why exactly such a construction does not work in the massless case?
 
  • #43
It doesn't work on the operator level: You cannot construct a position operator, fulfilling the commutation relations of the operator algebra, from the generators of the massless irreps. of the proper orthochronous Poincare group for spin ##\geq 1##.
 
  • #44
vanhees71 said:
You cannot construct a position operator, fulfilling the commutation relations of the operator algebra
What algebra are we talking about here? Heisenberg algebra ##[x_i,p_j]=i\hbar\delta_{ij}##?
vanhees71 said:
from the generators of the massless irreps. of the proper orthochronous Poincare group for spin ##\geq 1##.
What about massless spin=0; is there a position operator for relativistic massless scalar particle?
 
  • #46
vanhees71 said:
There are position operators for massless scalar and spin-1/2 particles.
Is there a physically intuitive hand-waving argument why position operator doesn't exist for massless higher spins?
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #47
I don't know of any intuitive argument. It may have to do with the fact that the irreps of higher spin are necessarily "gauge fields". The reason is that the little group for the massless representations is ISO(2), i.e., the symmetry space of 2D Euclidean affine space. The little group is the subgroup of the Poincare group which leaves one arbitrarily choosen four-momentum, which for the massless representations is light-like, invariant.

Now you need the unitary transformations of the little group to build the irrep. of the full orthochronous proper Poincare group a la Frobenius/Wigner. The ISO(2) is generated by 2 translations and 1 rotation. The corresponding generators for the translations have of course continuous a continuous spectrum. Realizing this would mean you'd describe massless particles with continuous polarization-like degrees of freedom, which is physically not observed. Thus you consider only such representations, for which the translations of this ISO(2) are represented trivially. This leaves only the rotations of the ISO(2) as non-trivial (the trivial one leads to scalar massless fields though). From the point of view of the entire Poincare group these are the rotations with the rotation axis around the three-momentum defined by the arbitrarily chosen light-like four-momentum, i.e., the generator of these rotations is the helicity, and together with the triviality of the translations of the said little group this implies that you'd have all possible helicities ##h \in \mathbb{R}##, but at the end you use the Frobenius-Wigner method to build the representation of the entire Poincare group including the usual rotations as a subgroup, and this means that the helicities can only be ##0## (scalar fields), ##\pm 1/2##, ##\pm 1##, etc. leading to the representations corresponding to spin ##s=0##, ##s=1/2##, etc. for the rotation group as a subgroup of the Poincare group. So for any non-zero spin of your massless field you get only 2 polarization-degrees of freedom instead of ##2s+1##. For spin 1/2 you get both ##\pm 1/2## for each spin component. For ##s \geq 1## you get more spin-like degrees of freedom than the two physical polarization referring to the helicities ##\pm s## for each energy-momentum eigenmode, i.e., you have to deal with unphysical degrees of freedom, making your theory a "gauge theory" when expressed in terms of local fields.

That's why for the electromagnetic field for each energy-momentum eigenmode you have only the two transverse polarization states corresponding two left- and right-circular polarization (i.e., ##h=\pm 1## helicities) and not 3. Of course you want to work with local fields (in both classical and quantum electrodynamics). That's why you introduce a four-vector ##A^{\mu}##, but all fields connected by a "gauge transformation" ##A^{\prime \mu}=A^{\mu} +\partial^{\mu} \chi## with an arbitrary scalar field ##\chi## are considered to describe the very same physical situation. Only such a description with redundant, unphysical field degrees of freedom allow for a local description, and that's why we have to deal with the problems connected with gauge invariance when quantizing the theory. One way is to fix the gauge completely (e.g., by choosing the Coulomb gauge) and loosing manifest covariance (leading nevertheless to a covariant field theory as far as the physical fields and the observables built from them are concerned) of to use the tricky Faddeev-Popov quantization by introducing more unphysical ghost fields which precisely cancel the contributions from the also unphysical parts of the vector potentials. This modern path-integral method is equivalent to the manifestly covariant operator method. For the Abelian gauge-theory case of QED that's equivalent to Gupta-Bleuler quantization, but for the non-Abelian case you need the Faddeev-Popov ghosts for a gauge-fixed manifestly covariant formulation and the associate Becchi-Rouet-Stora-Tyutin (BRST) symmetry of the gauge-fixed action. Here, I'd say, the original path-integral formulation aka Fadeev-Popov quantization is more straight-forward.

For massive particles the little group is simply SO(3), and there you have all ##(2s+1)## spin eigenvalues as physical states.

Maybe it's this difference between the massless and massive irreps. which allow for the development of some intuitive argument for the non-existence of proper position observables in the massless case for spin ##s \geq 1##.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and Demystifier
  • #48
vanhees71 said:
Photons cannot have trajectories. They don't even have a position observable. I don't think that we have a convincing Bohmian reinterpretation of local relativistic QFT yet. For non-relativistic QT in the first-quantization formulation BM is a consistent theory without much additional merit compared to standard statistically interpreted QT. At least I've not seen any experiment that depicts the Bohmian trajectories of slow massive particles, e.g., in a double-slit experiment or something equivalent.
Demystifier said:
Is there a physically intuitive hand-waving argument why position operator doesn't exist for massless higher spins?
Is that so? I mean i know it's not formally defined, but it doesn't seem hard to derive a working definition from the framework i would think.

Looking at how Maxwell is quantized and taking a look at what creation/annihilation operators do in the example of a Fock space. For the EM-field these are mostly a solutions of Maxwell. It is convenient that Maxwell knew Born's rule long before Born did (not really) just if you look at how energy density of a EM-field ist calculated. That allows it to make the 6-dim vector composed of the ##E## and ##B## fields work very analogue to a wave function and normalizing it to the energy of a single photon makes sense. Like in QT this means either putting it into a finite box (or localize it by deforming it into a wave package with a gaussian profile?)

Anyhow, classic EM-energy density shows just the interference patterns we need when superposing solutions... so call me naive but i would think that looking for a photon where its energy is located is a canonical idea. Thus you can just assume the position probability distribution to be directly proportional to the energy density. That said, it implies how to define the position observable. Given how impulse observable is related and knowing what impulse we expect it seems clear how it needs to be set up, too.
 
Last edited:
  • #49
Killtech said:
so call me naive but i would think that looking for a photon where its energy is located is a canonical idea.
It makes perfect sense in laboratory, but I wouldn't call it canonical. Canonical has something to do with canonical commutation relation between position and momentum.
 
  • #50
Demystifier said:
It makes perfect sense in laboratory, but I wouldn't call it canonical. Canonical has something to do with canonical commutation relation between position and momentum.
Canonical is a word relative to the perspective i guess.

Anyhow, The energy density of a EM-wave and it's continuity equations are well established in every frame, not just the laboratory. Since this approach just derives the observables directly from there, this statement applies to them as well. It's merely that their transformation behavior is somewhat untypical because the normalization needed for probabilities changes and since those observables do that translation, they have to also hold that scaling factor.

But as Hamilton, position and momentum operators go, their commutators work as expected. On a curios note, when i wrote down Maxwell equations in terms of a Hamilton operator for this E-B-field-wave function, i just noticed they look almost like a massless Dirac equation. Or rather the mass term is replaced by a coupling to the charge field.
 
Last edited:
Back
Top