I Math Myth: The rationals are numbers

  • I
  • Thread starter Thread starter Greg Bernhardt
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Numbers
  • #51
stevendaryl said:
That was my point. If naturals are singletons and rationals are equivalence classes of pairs, then they can never be equal, or even equivalent. But you can always "coerce" a natural to the corresponding rational.
My point was that only that you can, but you do. And there is no coercion. It is part of the definition.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Field_of_fractions
..
The embedding of ##R## in ##Frac(R)## maps each ##n\in R## to the fraction ##\frac{en}e## for any nonzero ##e\in R## (the equivalence class is independent of the choice ##e##). This is modeled on the identity ##\frac n1 = n##.
..
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #52
stevendaryl said:
There's probably a way to introduce real numbers "all at once" without starting with naturals, proceeding to integers to rationals to reals.

Couldn't we just say:
  • 0 is a real
  • 1 is a real
  • if ##x## and ##y## are reals, then so are ##x+y## and ##x \times y## and ##x - y##.
  • If ##x## and ##y## are reals, and ##y \neq 0##, then ##x/y## is a real.
  • Then basic facts about ##+##, ##\times## and ##-## and ##/##.
This way, ##/## is not an operation for forming rationals from integers, it's just a binary operation on reals.
Without some additional flesh behind the "basic facts", the two element field GF(2) fits the above definition.

If you want the reals, you could ask for a "complete, ordered, archimedean field". If you want the rationals, you could skip the "complete" and, perhaps, require that it be "countable" instead.

The utility of constructions such as equivalence classes is, to me, that they provide some assurance that the asked-for structure exists. [Or "has a model" or whatever the appropriate term would be].
 
Last edited:
  • #53
martinbn said:
My point was that only that you can, but you do. And there is no coercion. It is part of the definition.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Field_of_fractions
The definition of what? If you define fractions to be equivalence classes of ordered pairs of naturals, then a natural is not a fraction. Every natural can be associated with a fraction (the article uses the term "embedding"; if you are embedding one set into another, that does not mean that the first set is a subset of the second set).

Actually, in category theory, maybe it does? In category theory, there is no such thing as "the" naturals or "the" rationals. There are just objects that work like the naturals, or the rationals, etc. So it's pointless to ask whether the naturals is a subset of the rationals.
 
Last edited:
  • #54
jbriggs444 said:
Without some additional flesh behind the "basic facts", the two element field GF(2) fits the above definition.
Well, yes, a structure can't be pinned down without axioms.
 
  • #55
jbriggs444 said:
The utility of constructions such as equivalence classes is, to me, that they provide some assurance that the asked-for structure exists. [Or "has a model" or whatever the appropriate term would be].
That's exactly right.
 
  • #56
stevendaryl said:
That was my point. If naturals are singletons and rationals are equivalence classes of pairs, then they can never be equal, or even equivalent. But you can always "coerce" a natural to the corresponding rational.
Yes, this. When we use the = sign it is implicit that the the thing on the LHS is a member of the same set as the thing on the RHS. To say that ## 1 = \dfrac{12}{12} ## is not a theorem because we must interpret the LHS as an integer and the RHS as a quotient pair is nonsense IMHO.

Similarly I do not accept that if we admit ## 1 = \dfrac{12}{12} ## then we must admit ## -2 = 5 ##: clearly these are not the same element of the set of integers and if we interpret 5 as an element of the set of integers modulo 7 then -2 is not even in the set.

I recognise that @fresh_42's Insight article was intended to be provacative, but of all the contentious propositions this one seems to me to be particularly unattractive.
 
  • Like
Likes SolarisOne and PeroK
  • #57
pbuk said:
Similarly I do not accept that if we admit ## 1 = \dfrac{12}{12} ## then we must admit ## -2 = 5 ##: clearly these are not the same element of the set of integers and if we interpret 5 as an element of the set of integers modulo 7 then -2 is not even in the set.
There's always an ambiguity as to whether something like ##-2## is supposed to be a canonical name for an element, or whether it is to be interpreted as the unary minus operator applied to the number 2. With the latter interpretation, ##-2## is an element of the integers modulo 7.

There are different philosophies about the foundations of mathematics. In some approaches, it's assumed that for anything more complicated than the naturals, you're always dealing with an equivalence relation, rather than equality (or rather, a congruence relation, because all the operations have to respect the equivalence relation).
 
  • Like
Likes pbuk
  • #58
stevendaryl said:
There's always an ambiguity as to whether something like ##-2## is supposed to be a canonical name for an element, or whether it is to be interpreted as the unary minus operator applied to the number 2. With the latter interpretation, ##-2## is an element of the integers modulo 7.

Hmm good point. But integers modulo 7 are an equivalence class not a set and it is therefore correct to write ## (-2) \equiv 5 ##, or alternativey ## 0 - 2 \equiv 5 ## but still not ## (-2) = 5 ## nor ## 0 - 2 = 5 ##.

stevendaryl said:
There are different philosophies about the foundations of mathematics. In some approaches, it's assumed that for anything more complicated than the naturals, you're always dealing with an equivalence relation, rather than equality (or rather, a congruence relation, because all the operations have to respect the equivalence relation).
That seems irrational, or at least unnecessarily complex. Surely in the real world a thing can be equal to itself, not just equivalent?
 
  • #59
We could endlessly debate the words rational number, representative of an equivalence class, quotient, or whatever. Probably without ever coming to a conclusion. It is hard to think about new ideas for what has been taught for centuries. The usage of wrong in the context was a rhetorical mean, less a mathematical statement. I see ##\mathbb{Q}## as ##\left(\mathbb{Z}-\{0\}\right)^{-1}\mathbb{Z}## (Atiyah, MacDonald: Introduction to Commutative Algebra, Chp. 3). Yes, it is an algebraic approach, because I think that the curriculum at school follows the embeddings semigroup - ring - field: ##\mathbb{N} \subseteq \mathbb{Z} \subseteq \mathbb{Q}##, such that it is natural to follow this algebraic way once it has been entered.

Anyway. I remember names like endoplasmic reticulum from biology at school. Mainly because of the teacher's accent rather than what it means. I remember that I had to learn those horrible names like 2,6,8-trihydroxypurin in chemistry. And we learned about the double-slit experiment and the weak decay in physics.

Only in mathematics, we refuse to teach anything other than triangles, and calculations. It is (normally) not mathematics, it is counting. What I wanted to initiate with this article was a discussion, why we don't teach mathematics more scientifically as we do in other STEM areas? Mathematics seems to prefer to be the big surprise at university. A habit that is wrong in my opinion, and that fails to inspire kids. Instead, we are hunting them down in algorithms. One after the other.
 
  • Like
Likes etotheipi, dextercioby and Greg Bernhardt
  • #60
pbuk said:
That seems irrational, or at least unnecessarily complex. Surely in the real world a thing can be equal to itself, not just equivalent?
I don't remember the details of the construction, but I will try to give a little bit of the flavor.

Start with a term language, which is defined by a collection of constant symbols and function symbols of various numbers of arguments. A term is anything you can form starting with constant symbols and applying function symbols. Then a "type" is such a term language together with a partial equivalence relation on terms. "Partial" because some terms don't denote any element of the type (for example, ##0/0## doesn't denote any element of the rationals). A term ##t## is in the type ##T## is ##t \approx t## according to the partial equivalence relation of ##T##.

Then if ##A## are types and ##B## are types, and you have a function ##f## that takes terms of ##A## and returns terms of ##B##, then we say ##f## is of type ##A \rightarrow B## if whenever ##t_1 \approx t_2## is true according to the equivalence relation of ##A##, then ##f(t_1) \approx f(t_2)## according to the equivalence relation of ##B##. The equivalence relation for ##A \rightarrow B## is extensionality:

##f \approx g## if and only if for all ##t##, ##f(t) \approx g(t)##

Etc.

This is different from the construction in terms of equivalence classes because you are always dealing with concrete objects, terms, rather than equivalence classes. And as long as objects are always identified with exactly one type, there is no confusion in using ##=## for ##\approx## in that type.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #61
Is there a widely accepted official definition of "number". If so then the question of whether or not the rationals are numbers has nothing to do with whether or not they are also an equivalence class. The question of whether or not they are numbers is determined only by whether or not they fit the definition of number.

That said, I don't know the official definition of number. Does anyone else?
 
  • Like
Likes weirdoguy and Mark44
  • #62
Is "one" different from "1" or "I"(Roman)?
 
  • #63
nLab said:
Throughout mathematics there are various entities referred to as “numbers”; in modern mathematics it would be more accurate to refer to anyone of various types called “number systems”, and simply define a number to be a term of such a type.

A numeral on the other hand is a syntactic representation of a number, part of a system of numeration.

It is interesting to try to describe the general conditions under which something comes to be designated as a “number”. After all, such number systems tend to form commutative rings or at least commutative rigs, but not all commutative rigs are considered to consist of “numbers”, or at least that is not how the language is used in practice.

The root notion, known to the great ancient civilizations and particularly ancient Hellenic civilization, is that of (the system of) natural numbers, and in some way or other each of the various number systems are extensions of that one.
https://ncatlab.org/nlab/show/number
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #64
mathman said:
Is "one" different from "1" or "I"(Roman)?
Yes. One can see it. In order to be the same, you have to provide context.
 
  • #65
How do you define rational numbers? As a set, of course, but a set of what?

1st definition: A number ##p## is called a rational number iff is an element of this set:

$$\mathbb Q_1 :=\left\{\frac{a}{b}\vert a\in\mathbb Z, b\in \mathbb Z\setminus\{0\}\right\}$$

According to this definition: ##\left(\frac{1}{1}=:\right) 1_{\mathbb Q_1} \neq \frac{12}{12}_{\mathbb Q_1}##

2nd definition: Let us endow ##\mathbb Q_1## with an equivalence relation, because there are solid reasons to believe ##\mathbb Q_1## has too many elements for the purpose of "clean" mathematics. For this we exploit the fact that ##\mathbb Z## is closed under multiplication.

$$\forall p,q\in\mathbb Q_1, p\equiv \frac{a}{b}, q\equiv \frac{c}{d}$$

$$ \frac{a}{b}\sim \frac{c}{d} \Leftrightarrow a\cdot d =_{\mathbb Z} b\cdot d$$

From here we simply define:

$$ \mathbb Q_2 := \mathbb Q_1 / \sim $$

So we obviously have that ##\left[\frac{1}{1}\right]_{\mathbb Q_2} = \left[\frac{12}{12}\right]_{\mathbb Q_2} ##.

So to say simply that ##1=12/12## is true only by ignoring the very definition of ##\mathbb Q_2## by scrambling the definition of ##\mathbb Q_1##. What @fresh_42 is saying is that the standard mathematics education system (from elementary 1st grade to the end of high-school) simply uses improperly defined mathematical objects and perhaps even the highest level of mathematics education attained (college/university, before specializing to a PhD) does not properly define "rational numbers".
 
  • #66
dextercioby said:
How do you define rational numbers?
First, how do you define numbers?
 
  • #67
As elements of particular sets, i.e. sets with particular properties of their elements.
 
  • #68
Why can't we just say the rational numbers are the smallest field of characteristic 0. We know the integers embed into it, and by axioms of a field 1=12/12.

You might ask how we know this field exists (I.e. there exists one that embeds into all others). It's pretty easy to prove your ##\mathbb{Q}_2## is it, so we're done. But I haven't defined the field as an equivalence class, it just exists, contains integers, and let's you divide by integers as well. Then saying ##1\neq 12/12## is like saying ##9\neq 3^2## because they're only equal after you apply evaluation of functions which you haven't done yet.

The construction of the rationals as equivalence classes is a convenient way to prove everything is on the up and up, but most people don't spend any time thinking about Peano's construction of the integers and it doesn't seem to be an issue either. This is like arguing that we need to teach everyone that 2 is the successor of 1, not just, you know, 2.
 
  • Like
Likes martinbn
  • #69
dextercioby said:
As elements of particular sets, i.e. sets with particular properties of their elements.
By that definition the rationals certainly are numbers.
 
  • #70
Dale said:
By that definition the rationals certainly are numbers.
Sure, that is the definition of ##\mathbb Q_1## in my post. But because of it's void of the equivalence relation, it has "redundant elements", i.e. it has both ##\frac{1}{1}## and ##\frac{14}{14}## as distinct elements.
 
  • #71
The set of rational numbers is a set, and 1/1 is an element of it.

The tuple (1,1) you have in ##\mathbb{Q}_1## most people would say is not a number
 
  • #72
So the set of "rational numbers" is properly the set of all "distinct results of division by non-zero in the integers", so you

a) First take ##\mathbb Z## and define the operator ##/## which is applied to any two elements (tuple), with exception of 0 being the second element of the tuple. Then
b) Define a "rational number" as being the element ##q := a/b##, so that ##q \cdot b \equiv a## and here the multiplication of ##q## by an integer is defined as a repeated addition/subtraction, just like in ##\mathbb Z##.
c) Eliminate all duplicates produced by step b).

This way 1,6 = 8/5 and 1,6 = 16/10 are counted only once, i.e. 8/5 and 16/10 define one number.
 
  • #73
dextercioby said:
Sure, that is the definition of ##\mathbb Q_1## in my post. But because of it's void of the equivalence relation, it has "redundant elements", i.e. it has both ##\frac{1}{1}## and ##\frac{14}{14}## as distinct elements.
But regardless of that it is not a myth that the rationals are numbers by that definition.

Of course, with that definition colors are numbers as are animals and many other things I would not normally associate with numbers.
 
  • #74
A funny side note: ##1## and ##\dfrac{12}{12}## are not equal, in the sense, that someone not knowing the context, cannot see any equality. However, they are of equal value, equal valence. Just saying.

Again, I don't think that a discussion about words is or even can be meaningful. A discussion, why we teach algorithms instead of mathematics seems overdue to me.
 
  • #75
fresh_42 said:
A discussion, why we teach algorithms instead of mathematics seems overdue to me.
May be a separate thread. A lot can be said in that regard.
 
  • #76
dextercioby said:
Sure, that is the definition of ##\mathbb Q_1## in my post. But because of it's void of the equivalence relation, it has "redundant elements", i.e. it has both ##\frac{1}{1}## and ##\frac{14}{14}## as distinct elements.
Ahh. I did not get from that post that ##\frac{x}{y}## was intended as an otherwise uninterpreted notation for an ordered pair of integers.
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #77
If we have a ring ##R## and a multiplicative closed set ##1\in S##, then
$$
S^{-1}R = (R\times S)/\sim \text{ where } (r,s)\sim (p,t) \Longleftrightarrow \exists \,u\in S\, : \,(rt-ps)u=0
$$
 
  • #78
Office_Shredder said:
The set of rational numbers is a set, and 1/1 is an element of it.

The tuple (1,1) you have in ##\mathbb{Q}_1## most people would say is not a number
Do you have a definition of “number” that we can use to claim that? I am not a mathematician, but the definition in post 67 seems overly broad to me. By that definition the Q1 rationals are numbers, but so are colors and animals
 
  • #79
Dale said:
Do you have a definition of “number” that we can use to claim that? I am not a mathematician, but the definition in post 67 seems overly broad to me. By that definition the Q1 rationals are numbers, but so are colors and animals
I don't think you will get a satisfactory answer, because it is not the case that there is something called a number, and then depending on its properties it gets aditional desripstion, as a natural number. It is more the other way around. You have definitions of natural numbers, complex numbers, Gauss numbers and so on. Then a number is an element of any of those sets.
 
  • Like
Likes pbuk and fresh_42
  • #80
Dale said:
Do you have a definition of “number” that we can use to claim that? I am not a mathematician, but the definition in post 67 seems overly broad to me. By that definition the Q1 rationals are numbers, but so are colors and animals
I think the closest you can come is to accept number as a name for what can be counted, the natural numbers. From there on there is a natural way up to the complex numbers, so we call everything in between, plus the complex numbers number.

nLab as quoted in post no. 63 explains the difficulties.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #81
fresh_42 said:
I think the closest you can come is to accept number as a name for what can be counted, the natural numbers. From there on there is a natural way up to the complex numbers, so we call everything in between, plus the complex numbers number.
That isn’t really a definition of “number” but by that heuristic then the rationals would be numbers and colors would not. It is reasonably satisfactory.
 
  • #82
John Conway has given a definition of "number" in terms of two-person games. A game is, set-theoretically, defined as either the empty set (##0##) or a pair ##(L, R)## where L and R are both sets of games. To understand this as a game, you imagine two players, called "Left" and "Right" who alternate turns. On Right's turn, he picks one game out of the set R, and then Left must play that game. A player loses if it's his turn, and the game is the empty set (so he has no next move). So there are 4 types of games. (Assume that each player always makes the best move possible)
  1. Left wins, no matter who starts.
  2. Right wins, no matter who starts.
  3. The first player wins.
  4. The second player wins.
Let's call a game "positive" if it is in category 1, "negative" if it is in category 2, and 0 if it is in category 4.

Now, we can obviously flip a game from a win for Left to a win for Right by just switching L and R all the way down. Call that the "negative" of a game. So for example,

If ##G = 0##, then ##-G = 0##
If ##G = (\{ g^L_1, g^L_2 ...\}, \{ g^R_1, g^R_2 ...\})##, then ##-G = (\{ -g^R_1, -g^R_2 ...\}, \{ - g^L_1, -g^L_2 ...\})##.

We can describe the "sum" of two games ##G_1 + G_2## as follows: The two players are playing two games in parallel. At every move, the player has a choice of making a move in the first game, or the second. Taking a move in a game means replacing that game by a simpler game, until eventually it becomes the empty game. At the point, only one of the two games is left, so players must continue in that one.

Now, we can say that ##G_1 \gt G_2## if ##G_1 + (-G_2)## is positive.

Finally, we are in a position to define a "number". A number is defined recursively as:
##0## is a number
##(L, R)## is a number if for all ##g^L \in L## and ##g^R \in R##, ##g^L \lt g^R##.

According to this definition,
The empty game corresponds to the number ##0##.
The game ##(L,R)## where ##L = \{ 0 \}## and ##R = \{\}## is the number 1.
The game ##(L,R)## where ##L = \{0, 1\}## and ##R = \{\}## is the number 2.
The game ##(L,R)## where ##L = \{0, 1, 2\}## and ##R = \{\}## is the number 3.
Etc.

This notion of number includes almost everything:

The natural numbers.
The integers.
The rational numbers.
The reals.
Transfinite ordinals.
Infinitesimals.

http://www.cs.cmu.edu/afs/cs/academic/class/15859-s05/www/lecture-notes/comb-games-notes.pdf
 
Last edited:
  • Informative
Likes Dale
  • #83
Dale said:
That isn’t really a definition of “number” but by that heuristic then the rationals would be numbers and colors would not. It is reasonably satisfactory.
There is simply no mathematical object that is a number. It is a term that belongs to the common language. It requires an additional name to become mathematics: natural number, real number, p-adic number etc. Perhaps you mean cipher when you say number.
 
  • #84
fresh_42 said:
There is simply no mathematical object that is a number. It is a term that belongs to the common language.
Then it is clearly wrong to claim that the rationals are not numbers. In the common language they are numbers and the term number is a common language term.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK
  • #85
Dale said:
Then it is clearly wrong to claim that the rationals are not numbers. In the common language they are numbers and the term number is a common language term.
By that argument, you have left mathematics. Rationals is short for rational numbers, and with this adjective, they become a mathematical object. How you write them, define them, or otherwise classify them is a different topic. I see them as elements of ##(\mathbb{Z}^\times)^{-1}\mathbb{Z}##, others do not want to distinguish the representatives of a given class, which by the way is more than strange:

I bet that everybody who claims that ##1=\dfrac{12}{12}## is also a person who would not accept ##\dfrac{12}{12}## as a correct answer of an exercise, and who would demand to write it in canceled form.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes weirdoguy
  • #86
fresh_42 said:
By that argument, you have left mathematics. Rationals is short for rational numbers, and with this adjective, they become a mathematical object. How you write them, define them, or otherwise classify them is a different topic. I see them as elements of ##(\mathbb{Z}^\times)^{-1}\mathbb{Z}##, others do not want to distinguish the representatives of a given class, which by the way is more than strange:

I bet that everybody who claims that ##1=\dfrac{12}{12}## is also a person who would not accept ##\dfrac{12}{12}## as a correct answer of an exercise, and who would demand to write it in canceled form.
You lost the bet. I do accept answers like that , and i tell my students that i do accept such answers.
 
  • Like
Likes SolarisOne, PeroK and weirdoguy
  • #87
fresh_42 said:
I bet that everybody who claims that ##1=\dfrac{12}{12}## is also a person who would not accept ##\dfrac{12}{12}## as a correct answer of an exercise, and who would demand to write it in canceled form.
martinbn said:
You lost the bet. I do accept answers like that , and i tell my students that i do accept such answers.
Same here. I would also accept 12/12 as an answer, as long as the problem wasn't "Simplify the rational number ##\frac{12}{12}##."
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes martinbn and weirdoguy
  • #88
fresh_42 said:
By that argument, you have left mathematics.
Sure, but as you already established the statement “the rationals are numbers” never was a mathematical statement to begin with.

fresh_42 said:
I bet that everybody who claims that ##1=\dfrac{12}{12}## is also a person who would not accept ##\dfrac{12}{12}## as a correct answer of an exercise, and who would demand to write it in canceled form.
I also would accept all of those as an answer. I would even accept ##12^0##. I would probably mark ##-e^{i\pi}## wrong but then would give the points back when the student complained
 
  • #89
Dale said:
Sure, but as you already established the statement “the rationals are numbers” never was a mathematical statement to begin with.
Yes, but I also said:
fresh_42 said:
And, yes, I used rhetorical methods, because I wrote a pamphlet and not an article.
But if we really continue to debate on this Wittgenstein level, then let me add:
  1. fresh_42 said:
    Rationals is short for rational numbers
  2. fresh_42 said:
    From there [##\mathbb{N}##] on there is a natural way up to the complex numbers, so we call everything in between, plus the complex numbers number.
Hence, despite being hidden behind common language due to the purpose of the text, the used names can be re-translated into mathematics.

It was a headline, not an abstract!
 
  • #90
fresh_42 said:
It was a headline, not an abstract!
Sure. I have no problem with it being a headline not an abstract. And we can certainly expand it as “the rational numbers are numbers”. That headline is true, hence not a myth.

As you show later they are also an equivalence class and 12/12 and 3/3 are different equivalent elements of that equivalence class. But none of that implies that the headline is in fact a myth. They are both numbers and an equivalence class.

I have no objection to your math whatsoever. Only the headline.
 
  • #91
Dale said:
Sure. I have no problem with it being a headline not an abstract. And we can certainly expand it as “the rational numbers are numbers”. That headline is true, hence not a myth.

As you show later they are also an equivalence class and 12/12 and 3/3 are different equivalent elements of that equivalence class. But none of that implies that the headline is in fact a myth. They are both numbers and an equivalence class.

I have no objection to your math whatsoever. Only the headline.
Well, I do not want to blame others, but my original headline had been: 10 things we all learned wrong at school.
 
  • Haha
Likes Greg Bernhardt
  • #92
fresh_42 said:
Well, I do not want to blame others, but my original headline had been: 10 things we all learned wrong at school.
But “the rational numbers are numbers” is not wrong. They indeed are numbers and they are also an equivalence class.
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK
  • #93
Dale said:
But “the rational numbers are numbers” is not wrong. They indeed are numbers and they are also an equivalence class.
It is wrong in the sense that they are representatives of equivalence classes and as such stand for entire sets, not numbers, because people associate a single element with the word number, not a set.
 
  • Skeptical
  • Like
Likes Motore, PeroK and dextercioby
  • #94
Dale said:
Only the headline.
It was my idea to break them out for dedicated discussion and added the prefix. If there is a more appropriate prefix let me know.
 
  • #95
Many things we call elements are actually equivalence classes: elements in finite fields (modulus), real numbers (Cauchy 0-sequences, Dedekind cuts), complex numbers (factor ring, Riemann sphere). Equality is a very specific equivalence relation, and a rare one, too.
 
  • Skeptical
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, pbuk and PeroK
  • #96
Greg Bernhardt said:
It was my idea to break them out for dedicated discussion and added the prefix. If there is a more appropriate prefix let me know.
This shouldn't be necessary, because Wittgenstein is a forbidden topic. I intended to provoke the question: Why do biologists teach biology, physicists physics, and chemists chemistry, but mathematicians teach triangles in the sand and calculations, simple algorithms which are counting in my opinion, but certainly not mathematics.

It wasn't intended to make a philosophical discussion about the meaning of words out of it. The subject that matters is: Why do we pretend to teach mathematics if it is actually calculating?
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, Greg Bernhardt and Dale
  • #97
fresh_42 said:
This shouldn't be necessary, because Wittgenstein is a forbidden topic. I intended to provoke the question: Why do biologists teach biology, physicists physics, and chemists chemistry, but mathematicians teach triangles in the sand and calculations, simple algorithms which are counting in my opinion, but certainly not mathematics.

It wasn't intended to make a philosophical discussion about the meaning of words out of it. The subject that matters is: Why do we pretend to teach mathematics if it is actually calculating?
Here in the U.S. in the 1960's (when I was in elementary school) there was this thing called the "New Math" where they tried teaching real math. Instead of getting us to memorize our "times tables" and do long multiplication with pencil and paper, they showed us Venn Diagrams and talked about numeric representation with non-decimal bases.

From where I sat in my desk, the whole thing was a waste of time. Every year, we'd spend two weeks at the beginning of the year doing those New-Mathy things. And then we'd be right back doing calculations.

I had a heck of a time memorizing the multiplication tables. I'd keep trying to do arithmetic rather than just spouting the memorized result. [Nine times seven is seven less than ten times seven, so the answer must be 63]. This was decently fast, but not top-of-the-class fast. So my mother, herself an elementary school teacher, drilled me until I'd simply memorized the table instead. Got a decent calculation speed-up out of that].

Finally, I got to college and in my second year took a 400 series course "Advanced Calculus". Turned out to be a course in what I now know to have been real analysis. Did the whole Peano Axiom, construct the real numbers thing. That was the most enjoyment I'd ever had in a math course. So much that had always been pretty obvious was placed on a rigorous footing. [And some stuff that I thought I had grasped had to be re-learned -- the nature of infinite sets, for instance].
 
Last edited:
  • #98
fresh_42 said:
It is wrong in the sense that they are representatives of equivalence classes and as such stand for entire sets, not numbers, because people associate a single element with the word number, not a set.
I am not sure that people in fact don’t associate the entire set with the number. I mean, if I order a large pizza I don’t demand to see the manager if they give me 8/8 of a large pizza or 12/12 of a large pizza or 6/6 of a large pizza. I recognize the entire set as being one large pizza.
 
  • Like
Likes Motore
  • #99
jbriggs444 said:
Here in the U.S. in the 1960's (when I was in elementary school) there was this thing called the "New Math" where they tried teaching real math. Instead of getting us to memorize our "times tables" and do long multiplication with pencil and paper, they showed us Venn Diagrams and talked about numeric representation with non-decimal bases.

From where I sat in my desk, the whole thing was a waste of time. Every year, we'd spend two weeks at the beginning of the year doing those New-Mathy things. And then we'd be right back doing calculations.

Finally, I got to college and in my second year took a 400 series course "Advanced Calculus". Turned out to be a course in what I now know to have been real analysis. Did the whole Peano Axiom, construct the real numbers thing. That was the most enjoyment I'd ever had in a math course. So much that had always been pretty obvious was placed on a rigorous footing. [And some stuff that I thought I had grasped had to be re-learned -- the nature of infinite sets, for instance].
We had this nonsense, too. However, it gave me one of the nicest tutorials I ever had: a grandma who wanted to learn "set theory" to help her grandchildren with their homework.

I admit that this approach was not very well prepared. There is nothing wrong with Venn diagrams, as long as they are taught at an appropriate age and, say, take no longer than maximal a week.
 
  • Like
Likes jbriggs444
  • #100
fresh_42 said:
Many things we call elements are actually equivalence classes: elements in finite fields (modulus), real numbers (Cauchy 0-sequences, Dedekind cuts), complex numbers (factor ring, Riemann sphere).
I don't accept this, it is like looking back through the wrong end of the telescope. We define the set of rationals a priori*, we don't define an equivalence class and then say 'this equivalence class has a representative set which we can call ## \mathbb Q ##'.

Or have I missed something in the last 40 years since I learned this stuff?

*## \mathbb Q: \forall x \in \mathbb Q (\exists a, b \in \mathbb N: x = \frac{a}{b}) ##
 
  • Like
Likes Mark44

Similar threads

Replies
14
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
2K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Replies
4
Views
1K
2
Replies
61
Views
9K
Replies
3
Views
2K
Back
Top