- 24,488
- 15,056
?ftr said:vanhees71, aren't you shooting superposition between the eyes.![]()
?ftr said:vanhees71, aren't you shooting superposition between the eyes.![]()
Ok I will elaborate ( I guess I am summarizing while multitasking my lifevanhees71 said:?
vanhees71 said:I always thought that "minimal statistical" and "ensemble" interpretations are just the name of the same interpretation. If not, what's the difference. Is this again one of these unnecessary confusions due to (unnecessary?) philosophical sophistry?
vanhees71 said:Oh come on, statistical and probablistic is really synonymous if it comes to the application of probability theory
vanhees71 said:The correlations are not caused by the measurements but are due to the correlation following from the preparation in an entangled state.
For a random quantum state on H=Cd⊗Cd obtained by partial tracing a random pure state on H⊗Cs, we consider the whether it is typically separable or typically entangled. For this problem, we show the existence of a sharp threshold s0=s0(d) of order roughly d3. More precisely, for any a>0 and for d large enough, such a random state is entangled with very large probability when s<(1−a)s0, and separable with very large probability when s>(1+a)s0. One consequence of this result is as follows: for a system of N identical particles in a random pure state, there is a threshold k0=k0(N)∼N/5 such that two subsystems of k particles each typically share entanglement if k>k0, and typically do not share entanglement if k<k0. Our methods work also for multipartite systems and for "unbalanced" systems such as Cd⊗Cd′, d≠d′. The arguments rely on random matrices, classical convexity, high-dimensional probability and geometry of Banach spaces; some of the auxiliary results may be of reference value. A high-level non-technical overview of the results of this paper and of a related article arXiv:1011.0275 can be found in arXiv:1112.4582.
Nothing more about a particle than those who are brought to our consciousness. We human beings, let us be aware of the physical phenomena through our senses: f(r,t), g(sound, t), ...Demystifier said:Its pretty tough only if one does not accept that there is nothing more about a particle than a click in a detector.
it's not surprising: QBism and the GreeksDemystifier said:And guess what, many experts in the field do not accept it.
As I said, this definitely seems to be a foreign language speaker issue: the confusion arises from the stem 'certain-'; the word 'certainly' in this context has nothing directly to do with 'certainty', i.e. "certainly suggests" means "it is true that it suggests", which clearly is in contrast to "suggests (with) certainty", which means "suggests that it is true".A. Neumaier said:I'd say that "suggests" and "makes plausible" are synonymous. But there is nothing certain in a plausibility argument. The appropriate wording in the sentence would have been ''suggests to me'',
since plausibility is in the eye of the beholder.
Statistical and probabilistic are not synonymous. Statistics is an empirical methodology based largely on (certain forms of) probability theory, while probability theory is a field in mathematics such as geometry.vanhees71 said:Oh come on, statistical and probablistic is really synonymous if it comes to the application of probability theory to real-world problems, and QT is also a kind of probability theory.
This is not confusion due to philosophical sophistry, but more confusion due to a wrongly assumed equivalence relation between two different classes/sets: the relation between the elements of the set of statistics and the elements of the set of applications of probability theory is not bijective; the latter set is far larger than the former and moreover, the former set has relations with other formal domains as well, e.g. logic.vanhees71 said:I always thought that "minimal statistical" and "ensemble" interpretations are just the name of the same interpretation. If not, what's the difference. Is this again one of these unnecessary confusions due to (unnecessary?) philosophical sophistry?
Your suspicions are of course warranted: entanglement is ubiquitous, almost all quantum states in Nature are entangled states, but decoherence of course breaks these entanglements, which of course is why building a quantum computer is such an engineering challenge.Jimster41 said:You make it sound like entanglement is some rare artificially induced thing, and therefore non-locality ("a-causality" is a term I have heard applied) between entangled elements just an exotic oddity - philosophically curious.
But I've always been confused about where entanglement is naturally found. Is it natural and ubiquitous in addition to being an isolated laboratory phenomenon? I mean isn't it natural and ubiquitous?
but wouldn't that make it possible to have a frame in which the two events occurs simultaneously? even though the two frames can't be Lorentz connected?vanhees71 said:event A can only be the cause of event B if it is time- or light-like separated from B and B is within or on the future light cone of A
Demystifier said:They can accept its truth, but not its completeness. They want to know what happens behind the curtain.
On the other hand, those who are satisfied with the purely epistemic interpretation either
(i) don't care about things behind the curtain, or
(ii) care a little bit but don't think that it is a scientific question, or
(iii) claim that there is nothing behind the curtain at all.
Those in the category (i) have a mind of an engineer, which would be OK if they didn't claim that they are not engineers but scientists. Those in the category (ii) often hold double standards because in other matters (unrelated to quantum foundations) they often think that questions about things behind the curtain are scientific. Those in the category (iii) are simply dogmatic, which contradicts the very essence of scientific way of thinking.
All other scientific accounts of phenomena ever given so far have ultimately turned out to be dynamical. Because the question is still mathematically wide open, i.e. the correct mathematical description to fully describe the problem has not yet been found or proven to not exist, the question is currently an open question in mathematical physics.RUTA said:I believe there is nothing behind the curtain, not because it's irrelevant, but because there really is no thing behind the curtain and there is no dynamical story to tell. QM is providing an adynamical constraint on the distribution of momentum exchange in spacetime without a dynamical counterpart. How is that unscientific? Must all scientific explanation be dynamical?
Auto-Didact said:All other scientific accounts of phenomena ever given so far have ultimately turned out to be dynamical. Because the question is still mathematically wide open, i.e. the correct mathematical description to fully describe the problem has not yet been found or proven to not exist, the question is currently an open question in mathematical physics.
The very fact that Bohmian mechanics even exists at all and may even be made relativistic, is proof that this is a distinctly scientific open problem of theoretical physics within the foundations of QM, let alone the existence of alternate theories waiting to be falsified experimentally and the existence of the open problem of quantum gravity.
It is therefore by all accounts vehemently shortsighted and extremely premature to decide based upon our best experimental knowledge that a dynamical account is a priori impossible; the experimental knowledge itself literally indicates no such thing, instead this is a cognitive bias coming from direct extrapolation of our effective models to arbitrary precision.
vanhees71 said:in my understanding, causality implies a specific time-ordering
vanhees71 said:In other words event A can only be the cause of event B if it is time- or light-like separated from B and B is within or on the future light cone of A.
vanhees71 said:It's not clear to me, how you define causality to begin with.
vanhees71 said:due to microcausality there is no cause-effect relation between space-like separated measurement events
vanhees71 said:In this case the entanglement is due to selection (or even post-selection!) of a subensemble out of an before (in the correct relativistic sense!) created system of two entangled (but not among them entangled) photon pairs. Note however that each of these pairs have been created in an entangled state by causal local interaction (SPDC of a laser photon in a BBO crystal).
kent davidge said:wouldn't that make it possible to have a frame in which the two events occurs simultaneously?
kent davidge said:even though the two frames can't be Lorentz connected?
There are more than one point on which your position is unscientific.RUTA said:I believe there is nothing behind the curtain, not because it's irrelevant, but because there really is no thing behind the curtain and there is no dynamical story to tell. QM is providing an adynamical constraint on the distribution of momentum exchange in spacetime without a dynamical counterpart. How is that unscientific? Must all scientific explanation be dynamical?
It's scientific to say: Maybe there is nothing behind the curtain, it seems very likely to me that it is so.RUTA said:I believe there is nothing behind the curtain, not because it's irrelevant, but because there really is no thing behind the curtain and there is no dynamical story to tell. QM is providing an adynamical constraint on the distribution of momentum exchange in spacetime without a dynamical counterpart. How is that unscientific? Must all scientific explanation be dynamical?
Where did I say this? Entanglement is the rule rather than the exception. Alone from the fact that we have indistinguishable particles and thus Bose or Fermi symmetric/anti-symmetric Fock spaces leads to a lot of entanglement.Jimster41 said:You make it sound like entanglement is some rare artificially induced thing, and therefore non-locality ("a-causality" is a term I have heard applied) between entangled elements just an exotic oddity - philosophically curious.
No, for time- or lightlike events the time ordering is the same in any frame (of course in SRT; in GR it's more complicated and it holds only in a local sense).kent davidge said:but wouldn't that make it possible to have a frame in which the two events occurs simultaneously? even though the two frames can't be Lorentz connected?
Causality is not vague but a fundamental assumption underlying all physics. Locality is another case since there a lot of confusion arises from the fact that too often people don't distinguish between causal effects and (predetermined) correlations. This becomes particularly problematic when it comes to long-range correlations between entangled parts of a quantum system.PeterDonis said:Yes, but that's a statement about your preferred use of ordinary language, not about physics. We all agree on the physics: we all agree that spacelike separated measurements commute and that such measurements on entangled quantum systems can produce results that violate the Bell inequalities. It would be nice if the discussion could just stop there, but everyone insists on dragging in vague ordinary language terms like "causality" and "locality" and arguing about whether they are appropriate terms to use in describing the physics that we all agree on.
Indeed, ignoring weak interactions the Standard Model is T-invariant. Nevertheless the S-matrix provides a time ordering. You define an initial state (usually two asymptotic free particles) and then look for the transition probability rate to a given final state. This reflects how we can do experiments, and there's always this time ordering: Preparation of a state and then measuring something. T invariance then just means that (at least in principle) the "time-reversed process" is also possible and leads to the same S-matrix elements.Where does this requirement show up in QFT? QFT is time symmetric.
I don't understand, what's unclear about this. To motivate the microcausality constraint, which is usually also called locality of interactions, you need the causality principle, and in Q(F)T it's even a weak one, i.e., you need to know only the state at one point in time to know it, given the full dynamics or Hamiltonian of the system, to any later point in time, i.e., it's causality local in time. You don't need to know the entire history before one "initial point" in time.The same way you've been defining it (you sometimes use the term "microcausality", but sometimes not): that spacelike separated measurements commute. But now you seem to be shifting your ground and giving a different definition of "causality" (the one I quoted above), the basis of which in QFT I don't understand (which is why I asked about it).
Microcausality ensures that there are no faster-than-light causal connections. Given the general causality assumption that's a necessary consequence: Two space-like separated events do not define a specific time order and thus one event cannot be the cause of the other.So microcausality means no causal relationship? That seems like an odd use of language.
Of course QFT admits entangled states. We write them down all the time discussing about photons. Measurements are just usual interactions between entities described by the fields, and due to microcausality they are local, i.e., there cannot be any causal influence of one measurment event on another measurement event that is space-like separated. I.e., if A's detector clicks this measurement event can not be the cause of anything outside of the future light cone of this event.The way I would describe all this is not that entangled pairs do not have to be causally connected. The way I would describe it is that QFT, strictly speaking, does not admit the concept of "an entangled pair", because it does not admit the concept of the "state" of an extended system at an instant of "time". It only admits measurement events and correlations between them, and it predicts the statistics of such correlations using quantum field operators that obey certain commutation relations. Each individual such operator is tied to a specific single event in spacetime: that's what makes it "local". Any talk about "entangled systems" measured at spacelike separated events is just an approximation and breaks down when you try to look too closely.
Of course, there are entangled states and there are the correspondingly observed strong correlations between far distant measurements, and all that is describable by relativistic QFT. It's also clear that the localizability also of massive particles, which have a position observable, is much more constrained in relativstic QFT than in non-relativistic QM since rather than localizing a particle better and better by "squeezing" it somehow in an ever smaller region in space you tend to create new particles.Again, this is all about how to describe things in ordinary language, not about physics. Basically many people do not like the extreme viewpoint I just described, which is IMO the proper consistent way to describe what QFT is saying. Many people do not want to give up the notion of "entangled systems" containing multiple spatially separated particles. But that notion IMO is a holdover from non-relativistic physics and needs to be given up in a proper account of what QFT says, if we are going to talk about how best to describe the physics in ordinary language and we aren't willing just to stop at the point of describing the physics in its most basic terms (which I gave at the start of this post).
Of course, QT provides a description of the dynamics of the system and the measurable quantities related with it. That's what QT is all about. I may be buried in many introductory courses, because students tend to get the impression that rather all there is are stationary states (i.e., eigenstates of the Hamiltonian), but that's only "statics" in a sense. Also in hydrodynamics or classical electrodynamics you can stick with static or stationary special cases, but still hydro as well as Maxwell theory are indeed descriptions of the dynamics of the described system (fluids and charges and the em. field, respectively).zonde said:So answering your question: "Must all scientific explanations be dynamical?" - yes, all scientific explanations must be dynamical because only testable explanations are scientific and the process of testing is dynamical, you have initial conditions and then you observe what happens and if your observations agree with predictions.
vanhees71 said:Note that in general the location of an entity described by QFT is determined by the location of a measurement device with a finite spatial resolution; it's not necessary that the measured systems have position observables, as the example of photons shows: All observable there is is that a detector located in some spatial region registers a photon or not.
I think it doesn't make sense. To see why, suppose that the universe contains only a hydrogen atom and nothing else. In the hydrogen atom, the electron interacts with the proton. Does it create the "form" of the electron?julcab12 said:Somewhat frozen image/depiction/description/detection of things that is always formless dynamic in nature --unless it interacts. That is exactly the view of Rovelli.
It doesn't say that. Well according to him. locality of quantum mechanics is by postulating relativity to the observer for events and facts, instead of an absolute “view from nowhere”. The main ontology of “observers”, measurement interactions and relative events. And, it doesn't say any form or becomes meaningless otherwise. Besides the only way to detect/picture a electron(seen as local) is through electron interacting.Demystifier said:I think it doesn't make sense. To see why, suppose that the universe contains only a hydrogen atom and nothing else. In the hydrogen atom, the electron interacts with the proton. Does it create the "form" of the electron?
I’m familiar with the two slit experiment etc. But to me it seems just as sensible to interpret the vave-like interference pattern seen by the detector(s) as “confirming” or “realizing” the non-locality of the quantum field, especially if new entangled states ensue - as opposed to describing it as “decoherence”. But that may be what you were getting at.Auto-Didact said:Your suspicions are of course warranted: entanglement is ubiquitous, almost all quantum states in Nature are entangled states, but decoherence of course breaks these entanglements, which of course is why building a quantum computer is such an engineering challenge.
But to make the argument even stronger, in textbook QM the description of ##\psi## is non-local whether or not entanglement is involved, i.e. even for a single particle wavefunction non-locality is already present in the following example given by Penrose about a decade ago or earlier:
Imagine a photon source and a screen some distance away and single photons are detected (or measured) as single points on the screen; in between source and screen is where the wavefunction is. Now imagine that there is a detector at each point of the screen; once the photon is detected at a single point on the screen we can call it a detection event.
Each single detection event on the screen instantaneously prohibits the photon from being seen anywhere else on the screen i.e. once a detection event takes place by a single detector, all other detectors are effectively instantaneously prohibited from detecting the photon; if the detector had to communicate this detection event to all the other detectors it would need to convey that information faster than light.
In other words, detection i.e. measurement itself breaks the non-locality of the wavefunction; this can be mathematically described in detail as measurements effectively removing the first cohomology element of single photon wavefunctions (NB: these photon wavefunctions are usually Fourier transformed wavefunctions, and together with their Fourier transforms reside in a larger abstract complex analytic mathematical space).
zonde said:There are more than one point on which your position is unscientific.
First, you believe in one true explanation. Just because you have an explanation that fits observations does not mean that there can't be other explanations.
Second, the process of gaining scientific knowledge is ... well a process, a dynamical story as you call it. What is the point of denying value of dynamical approach and then seeking justification for that from perspective of dynamical approach. It's stolen concept fallacy.
So answering your question: "Must all scientific explanations be dynamical?" - yes, all scientific explanations must be dynamical because only testable explanations are scientific and the process of testing is dynamical, you have initial conditions and then you observe what happens and if your observations agree with predictions.
Interesting.zonde said:It's stolen concept fallacy.
vanhees71 said:Causality is not vague
vanhees71 said:Locality is another case
vanhees71 said:the S-matrix provides a time ordering. You define an initial state (usually two asymptotic free particles) and then look for the transition probability rate to a given final state. This reflects how we can do experiments
vanhees71 said:Of course QFT admits entangled states. We write them down all the time discussing about photons
vanhees71 said:Measurements are just usual interactions between entities described by the fields, and due to microcausality they are local
vanhees71 said:there cannot be any causal influence of one measurment event on another measurement event that is space-like separated
vanhees71 said:a lot of confusion arises from the fact that too often people don't distinguish between causal effects and (predetermined) correlations.
They can only not be predetermined Bell-locally, by the latter's definition, as in your previous posts. But this is a tautology and means nothing.PeterDonis said:Correlations that violate the Bell inequalities can't be "predetermined" locally. That's what Bell's Theorem shows.
vanhees71 said:Hm, in my understanding, causality implies a specific time-ordering. In fact it's the only sense you can give to specific time-ordering, and thus causally connected events cannot be space-like separated. In other words event A can only be the cause of event B if it is time- or light-like separated from B and B is within or on the future light cone of A. It's not clear to me, how you define causality to begin with.
PeterDonis said:The same way you've been defining it (you sometimes use the term "microcausality", but sometimes not): that spacelike separated measurements commute. But now you seem to be shifting your ground and giving a different definition of "causality" (the one I quoted above), the basis of which in QFT I don't understand (which is why I asked about it).
Causality is generally defined as the universal law that causes must preceed effects in every frame of reference, and it entails nothing more. In contrast to locality, a notion with multiple, partially conflicting uses, one cannot tamper with the content of the concept of causality without misrepresenting much of classical and quantum physics.PeterDonis said:Not if you give it a precise definition, such as "operators at spacelike separated events commute", no. Which is why I've repeatedly suggested that we should all stop using vague ordinary language and start using precise math, or at least precise definitions that refer to precise math, as the one I just gave in quotes does. Then we can stop arguing about words and start talking about physics.
If you define "locality" as "does not violate the Bell inequalities", then QFT is not local. If you define "locality" as meaning the same thing as "causality" does above, then QFT is local, but you've also used two ordinary language words to refer to the same physical concept, plus you've thrown away the usual way of referring in ordinary language to another physical concept.
In any case, once again, can we please stop using vague ordinary language?
No, I didn't say "locally". In QT a state is given by a statistical operator. That's it. It's neither local nor non-local. It's just given by the preparation procedure. The most intuitive picture of time evolution is the Heisenberg picture, where also in the mathematical formulation the state is time-independent (or only time-dependent if there's explicit time-dependence).PeterDonis said:Correlations that violate the Bell inequalities can't be "predetermined" locally. That's what Bell's Theorem shows.
Small correction: In the Heisenberg picture, the state is never time-dependent, as any explicit time dependence is necessarily in the terms of the Hamiltonian.vanhees71 said:The most intuitive picture of time evolution is the Heisenberg picture, where also in the mathematical formulation the state is time-independent (or only time-dependent if there's explicit time-dependence).
In my field, i.e., relativistic QFT, these words have a clear meaning: Causality is implemented by the microcausality constraint, and locality means the locality of interactions, i.e., the Hamiltonian density is a local polynomial of the fields and their canonical momenta, i.e., it's depending only on one space-time argument. Also proper orthochronous Poincare transformations are realized on the field operators locally, i.e., the field operators transform under the unitary representations of the proper orthochronous Poincare group as the analogous classical fields do. Together with microcausality this makes the standard QFTs successfully used to describe real-world observations consistent with the space-time structure and thus the induced meaning of causality of special relativity.PeterDonis said:Not if you give it a precise definition, such as "operators at spacelike separated events commute", no. Which is why I've repeatedly suggested that we should all stop using vague ordinary language and start using precise math, or at least precise definitions that refer to precise math, as the one I just gave in quotes does. Then we can stop arguing about words and start talking about physics.
If you define "locality" as "does not violate the Bell inequalities", then QFT is not local. If you define "locality" as meaning the same thing as "causality" does above, then QFT is local, but you've also used two ordinary language words to refer to the same physical concept, plus you've thrown away the usual way of referring in ordinary language to another physical concept.
In any case, once again, can we please stop using vague ordinary language?
In other words, it reflects how we experience things. But QFT does not explain why we experience things that way. We don't fully understand why we experience things that way.
Sure, you can write down such states, but they include operators at different spacetime events (which can be spacelike separated events). So they're not "local" in the ordinary sense of the term.
With your preferred definition of "local", yes. But they violate the Bell inequalities, which means they are not "local" in that sense of the term "local". Which, again, is why I keep saying we should stop using vague ordinary language.
With your preferred definition of "causal influence", yes. But not everybody shares your preferences for definitions of ordinary language terms. Which is why we should stop using them.
In physics you always have to be ready that your model will be falsified by observation in some domain where your model has not yet been tested.RUTA said:There may be other explanations, but as a physicist I have to stake my approach on just one. It took my math colleague and I three months to modify and apply Regge calculus to the SCP Union2 data and it took us four months to modify and program a fit to the Planck 2015 CMB power spectrum data. These are just two examples of the many papers I have written based on my one approach. Maybe a philosopher can write one paper on a particular approach this month and turn around and write another paper on another approach next month, but we don't have that luxury in physics.
Any scientific explanation has to give predictions that are testable within dynamical process. So even if you believe that adynamical view can explain observation better you still have to be able to translate your adynamical view into dynamical story and point out unique features that show up in dynamical story.RUTA said:It is true that physics is done dynamically, but that doesn't mean an explanation of what we find has to be ultimately dynamical.
Almost all observations are still geocentric. So non geocentric model still have to express it's predictions for geocentric observer.RUTA said:It is also true that we do astrophysics and cosmology from Earth, seeing the sky rotate about us, but we long ago abandoned geocentricism.
There is big difference between facts A and B and components of the model A and B. It seems you are mixing them together.RUTA said:Changing from dynamical to adynamical explanation is revolutionary. As Skow said in his review, "It really is necessary to understand how radical this idea is. ... You can't explain A because B and B because A." But, in adynamical explanation (such as Einstein's equations of GR), it is precisely the case that "A (the spacetime metric) because B (the stress-energy tensor) and B because A." You can't input the SET to solve EE's for the metric unless you already know how to make spatiotemporal measurements, i.e., you already have the metric. And vice-versa of course. Solutions to EE's are self-consistent sets of the spacetime metric, energy, momentum, force, etc. on on the spacetime manifold, where "self-consistent" means "satisfies the constraint, i.e., EE's." That's why our proposed approach constitutes a Kuhnian revolution. When I started in foundations 25 years ago, I too was convinced that GR and/or QM were flat out wrong. Now, I believe (base my research approach on the fact that) they are in fact both right and beautifully self-consistent.
Every scientist has to operate within common generally accepted framework. Within that framework you have a lot of freedom with your explanations, but there is one condition - your explanation has to produce predictions that are testable even for those who do not believe in your explanation. So your condition "as long as you're willing to give up your anthropocentric dynamical bias" takes you out of that framework.RUTA said:Every physicist has to stake their research on a particular model of "the real external world." I'm very happy now with mine because it shows modern physics is in fact complete (minus QG) and consistent, i.e., it is amazingly comprehensive and coherent ... as long as you're willing to give up your anthropocentric dynamical bias.
No. It changes only the Hamiltonian by a time-dependent term.vanhees71 said:An example is that sometimes you like to describe a QFT system with some time-dependent "classical background field" present. This background field brings in explicit time-dependence.
No. The local equilibrium density operator is not in the Heisenberg picture, which would result in a covariant formula. The formula you give is covariant but in correct since the right hand side depends on ##x##, not on ##t##. You need to integrate over a Cauchy surface to get a valid exponent to which to apply the standard cumulant expansion. This shows that the expression is frame-dependent, hence constitutes a Schrödinger picture.vanhees71 said:Another important example for an explicitly time-dependent state is local thermal equilibrium. In the grand-canonical description it reads
$$\hat{\rho}=\frac{1}{Z} \exp[-(\hat{p} \cdot u(x)-\mu(x))/T(x)], \quad Z=\mathrm{Tr} \exp[-(\hat{p} \cdot u(x)-\mu(x))/T(x)].$$
I admitted that your right hand side is covariant, but it hasn't the correct form, hence is nonsense.vanhees71 said:The right-hand side depends on ##t## and ##x##, and it's manifestly covariant, ##u## is a four-vector field, ##\hat{p}## is a four-vector, ##T## and ##\mu## are four-vector fields.
How else would you write this standard statistical operator?
I corrected my formula, which was also nonsense. The new formula describes local equilibrium since if you discretize the integral into a sum over a number of mesoscopic cells, you get the formula that you would get from regarding the cells as independent and in equilibrium by taking a tensor product.vanhees71 said:Ok, I have to think about this, though I don't understand why your ##\hat{\rho}## describes local thermal equilibrium.
Sure, you are right. But if I write the statistical operator for relativistic quantum fields in the Heisenberg picture, why should it then be the statistical operator in the Schrödinger picture all of a sudden? I'd say one can just take your formula an write it down using the relativistic (canonical) energy-momentum-tensor ##\hat{\mathcal{T}}^{\mu \nu}(x)##. ThenA. Neumaier said:I corrected my formula, which was also nonsense. The new formula describes local equilibrium since if you discretize the integral into a sum over a number of mesoscopic cells, you get the formula that you would get from regarding the cells as independent and in equilibrium by taking a tensor product.
You can also get this formula from Jaynes' maximum entropy principle, assuming the local densities at fixed time to be the set of relevant variables.
No. Apply your recipe to the Schrödinger state of a free relativistic scalar particle instead of a quantum field, and you'll see that one cannot transform from the Schrödinger to the Heisenberg picture by a relabeling of the kind you do. It still remains the Schrödinger state. You need to apply the usual unitary transformation to mediate between the pictures.vanhees71 said:With the operators in the Heisenberg picture this should be the stat. op. in the Heisenberg picture too, right?
Well, you'd never claim something you had never seen...vanhees71 said:I've never seen this idea used in non-equilibrium QFT.
This is needed in the covariant case since due to renormalization, there are no sensible dynamical equations in interacting QFTs, so one needs to find the hydrodynamic equations from the functional integral rather than via a projection operator formalism.vanhees71 said:As you well know, there usually one works with a general ansatz, derives the Kadanoff-Baym equations und does further approximations from there.
Except possibly for ##H##. I was lazy and wrote everywhere a dependence on ##t##.vanhees71 said:In the Schrödinger picture the field operators would be time-independent,
OK, I see now what you mean. Need to think about this...vanhees71 said:The non-relativistic case is a bit simpler, but if I use Heisenberg fields, why is then the Stat. Op. all of a sudden in another picture of time evolution?
What is ##\cal G##?vanhees71 said:In the non-relativistic case, I'd write it in the form
$$\hat{S}=\int \mathrm{d}^3 x \left [\hat{\mathcal{H}}(t,\vec{x}) - \vec{\beta}(t,\vec{x}) \cdot \vec{\mathcal{G}}(t,\vec{x})-\mu(t,\vec{x}) \hat{\rho}(t,\vec{x}) \right]/T(t,\vec{x}).$$
Sorry; corrected. ##u,\mu,T## are coefficient fields but only the quotients are well-determined. Thus the redundancy. To fix this, there should be no denominator ##T##, and ##T## should be computed from your ##u## as its time component.vanhees71 said:I didn't understand your remark about redundancy.
vanhees71 said:I don't understand, why you think, we don't understand something.
Well, how you choose your thermodynamical parameters is a matter of convention. I also usually prefer ##\alpha=\mu/T## (I don't even know a name for it, but calculational-wise it's often more convenient if it comes to certain quantities like susceptibilities of (conserved) charges and things like that).A. Neumaier said:Except possibly for ##H##. I was lazy and wrote everywhere a dependence on ##t##.
OK, I see now what you mean. Need to think about this...
What is ##\cal G##?
Sorry; corrected. ##u,\mu,T## are coefficient fields but only the quotients are well-determined. Thus the redundancy. To fix this, there should be no denominator ##T##, and ##T## should be computed from your ##u## as its time component.
But your covariant formula also does not have enough intensive fields since the energy-momentum tensor has more coordinates than the momentum vector in my formula. There must be a multiplier field for every field operator component.
Well, as already said above, natural sciences are one (on purpose limited!) aspect of human knowledge. They restrict themselves to describe what can be accurately observed. For the most simple systems (which are usually described by physics) there's a surprising discovery that we can describe our observations by mathematical theories and understand a lot of phenomena from a very few fundamental principles, which finally cannot be derived from even more fundamental principles and which are an abstraction from our experience. Finally physics, as all of natural sciences, is an empirical science (on purpose). To find descriptions of ever more complex systems (many-body systems) from the fundamental theories, is a creative act. Though there's a big hype about AI, machine learning, and all that, I don't think there's a automatic way to find such descriptions, and thus that will stay a human art for a long time to come.PeterDonis said:We don't understand why we experience things a certain way. More precisely, we don't understand how our experiences are produced by our brains (which are in turn connected to the rest of the universe through our senses). But that's not a question of physics; it's a question of neuroscience, cognitive science, etc.
We also don't understand why we experience time to have a particular direction even though the underlying physical laws are time-symmetric (with the minor exception of weak interactions that don't play a part in the operation of our brains and bodies anyway). To some extent that is a question of physics, in that if physics can give an explanation for how time asymmetry can be produced from underlying laws that are time symmetric, we might not need to understand all the details of neuroscience, cognitive science, etc. to understand why we experience time to have a particular direction.
I am aware of only one hypothesis from physics to explain time asymmetry, namely asymmetry of initial conditions: time has an arrow in our universe because our universe started in a state with a very high degree of symmetry and uniformity. But we don't really have any way of testing this hypothesis since we can't run controlled experiments on universes.