"Single-world interpretations.... cannot be self-consistent"

In summary: This might be of interest to participants in this subforum. Have anyone read this? What do you think?This certainly sounds like a very big claim so I've been trying to read the preprint to find out about all the fine prints. Below is my attempt to summarize their basic argument based on my first pass at the preprint. I simplify it a bit which may leave some room for ambiguity.There are 4 players. Wigner (W), his assistant (A), his friend 1 (F1) and friend 2 (F2). I can think of them all as robots that do quantum experiments, record the outcomes in some physical states, and process that information to make predictions. No consciousness is required, and
  • #1
Truecrimson
263
86
A new preprint by Daniela Frauchiger and Renato Renner argues that any interpretation of quantum theory that posits only a single world gives contradictory predictions provided that an observer (which makes predictions) can be observed (Wigner's friend scenarios). This might be of interest to participants in this subforum. Have anyone read this? What do you think?

This certainly sounds like a very big claim so I've been trying to read the preprint to find out about all the fine prints. Below is my attempt to summarize their basic argument based on my first pass at the preprint. I simplify it a bit which may leave some room for ambiguity.

There are 4 players. Wigner (W), his assistant (A), his friend 1 (F1) and friend 2 (F2). I can think of them all as robots that do quantum experiments, record the outcomes in some physical states, and process that information to make predictions. No consciousness is required, and in particular, I don't have to assume that macroscopic conscious human beings can be put into a superposition.

Step 1 F1 observes one of two possible outcomes from measuring the state $$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} |H\rangle + \sqrt{\frac{2}{3}} |T\rangle $$ in the "Head" ## |H\rangle ## or "Tail" ## |T\rangle ## basis. F1 then coherently prepares a spin down state ## |\downarrow \rangle ## if she observes Head or ## |\rightarrow \rangle = \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} = |\uparrow \rangle + |\downarrow \rangle ## if she observes Tail, resulting in the entangled state $$ | \psi \rangle = \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} ( | H \rangle | \downarrow \rangle + | T \rangle | \downarrow \rangle + | T \rangle | \uparrow \rangle ). $$ She sends the spin state to F2.

Step 2 F2 measures the spin in the Z basis (up or down).

Step 3 A projectively measures F1 (the whole laboratory) and declares success if he gets the outcome $$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} (| H \rangle - | T \rangle ) $$ or failure if he gets the orthogonal outcome.

Step 4 W projectively measures F2 and declares success if he gets the outcome $$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} (| \downarrow \rangle - | \uparrow \rangle ) $$ or failure if he gets the orthogonal outcome.

The preprint analyzes the situation where both A and W succeed. This is possible because of the nonzero overlap of the projection operator $$ \frac{1}{2} (| H \rangle - | T \rangle ) \otimes (| \downarrow \rangle - | \uparrow \rangle ) $$ and the state $$ |\psi \rangle = \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} [ ( | H \rangle + | T \rangle ) | \downarrow \rangle + | T \rangle | \uparrow \rangle ] . $$ It is the rightmost term that contributes to the nonzero overlap. Given that both A and W succeed, A infers that the spin must be in the up state, which means that F1 observed the outcome Tail. But if the result comes out tail then Wigner must fail! because projecting the state ## |\psi \rangle ## onto $$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} |T \rangle ( | \uparrow \rangle + | \downarrow \rangle ) $$ means that Wigner will never succeed. Q.E.D.

The step that seems problematic to me is the retrodiction that the spin has a definite (up) value. This seems to be reminiscent of Aharonov and Vaidman's Three-Box Paradox.
 
  • Like
Likes mfb
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Thanks for sharing! I've had correspondence in the past with Renato Renner, regarding other papers he has published.
 
  • #3
Another interesting paper might be

http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9712044
Quantum and classical descriptions of a measuring apparatus
Ori Hay, Asher Peres
"This article examines whether these two different descriptions are mutually consistent. It is shown that if the dynamical variable used in the first apparatus is represented by an operator of the Weyl-Wigner type (for example, if it is a linear coordinate), then the conversion from quantum to classical terminology does not affect the final result. However, if the first apparatus encodes the measurement in a different type of operator (e.g., the phase operator), the two methods of calculation may give different results."


But Hay's and Peres's result was not considered to overturn Copenhagen or de Broglie Bohm - it just means that the folklore that the classical quantum cut can be placed anywhere is not absolutely true - and makes sense from both Copenhagen and dBB viewpoints where some "common sense" is needed to say that FAPP we do know what a "macroscopic measurement apparatus" is.

I believe that even von Neumann was aware of this, so the cut at an arbitrary place along the von Neumann chain is not always a classical/quantum cut, but in some cases has to be a quantum/quantum cut. Wiseman and Milburn's textbook also mentions that placing the classical/quantum cut in the wrong place gives experimentally incorrect results.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier and Truecrimson
  • #4
Truecrimson said:
A new preprint by Daniela Frauchiger and Renato Renner argues that any interpretation of quantum theory that posits only a single world gives contradictory predictions provided that an observer (which makes predictions) can be observed (Wigner's friend scenarios). This might be of interest to participants in this subforum. Have anyone read this? What do you think?

Without looking at the detail it looks highly dubious to me.

In QM you need a framework of system being observed and something doing the observing. Its not a contradiction that different frameworks may give different results. Its one of the weird things about QM, although this is the first paper I have seen that describes such a situation. That said I personally doubt such an experiment can actually be performed, but I will leave that up to experimental types to comment. The difficulty in doing it would seem to explain why in the world around us we never notice such a possibility of different frameworks giving different outcomes.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #5
atyy said:
it just means that the folklore that the classical quantum cut can be placed anywhere is not absolutely true

Well Von Neumann proved it rigorously so it's not exactly folklore.

But like you I suspect there are some caveats involved to do with differing frameworks of observer and observed. That would certainly be the decoherent histories viewpoint which requires non mutually contradictory frameworks. That is usually enforced by decoherence, but its possible to perhaps come up with a way around it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #6
bhobba said:
Well Von Neumann proved it rigorously so it's not exactly folklore.

But like you I suspect there are some caveats involved to do with differing frameworks of observer and observed. That would certainly be the decoherent histories viewpoint which requires non mutually contradictory frameworks. That is usually enforced by decoherence, but its possible to perhaps come up with a way around it.

But actually even if one thinks of it from say Schlosshauer's discussion of decoherence, his point is that decoherence plus some additional criteria gives us objective ways to say where we can place the cut (usually must be far out enough), then we can see that decoherence itself suggests the cut cannot be too early.
 
  • #7
I agree that where the cut is can't be arbitrary. With decoherence, one can't place the cut too early before decoherence has occurred. The Wigner's friends scenario though doesn't explicitly has decoherence. Then one probably has to have a rule for co-existing viewpoints as bhobba pointed out. (I don't know what the axioms of decoherent histories are.) In particular, the conclusion of Frauchiger and Renner probably comes about by combining viewpoints that you shouldn't combine.

I need to read the paper atyy brought up. Thank you.
 
  • #8
Truecrimson said:
A new preprint by Daniela Frauchiger and Renato Renner argues that any interpretation of quantum theory that posits only a single world gives contradictory predictions provided that an observer (which makes predictions) can be observed (Wigner's friend scenarios). This might be of interest to participants in this subforum. Have anyone read this? What do you think?
I had an extensive discussion about that paper with one of the authors, so I think I can tell what is the main problem with their idea. One of their assumptions is that new measurements delete information about the outcomes of previous measurements, and in my opinion this assumption is unjustified.
 
  • Like
Likes secur, Truecrimson, atyy and 1 other person
  • #9
Demystifier said:
One of their assumptions is that new measurements delete information about the outcomes of previous measurements...
It's 1 am over here so I need to go to bed. I will think about the paper and this statement some more when I have time. Thank you.
 
  • #10
Truecrimson said:
I agree that where the cut is can't be arbitrary.

As I said Von Neumann did prove it rigorously and he is no mean mathematician. But of course not infallible as his supposed proof of no hidden variables showed. I only suspect there is an out.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #11
atyy said:
But actually even if one thinks of it from say Schlosshauer's discussion of decoherence, his point is that decoherence plus some additional criteria gives us objective ways to say where we can place the cut (usually must be far out enough), then we can see that decoherence itself suggests the cut cannot be too early.
Another important thing about decoherence is that it is FAPP irreversible. Therefore information about outcomes of previous measurements is not deleted by new measurements, in contradiction with the crucial assumption used in the paper under discussion.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114 and atyy
  • #12
Demystifier said:
Another important thing about decoherence is that it is FAPP irreversible.

Hmmmm. The delayed choice experiment?

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #13
bhobba said:
Hmmmm. The delayed choice experiment?
The delayed choice is reversible precisely because it does not involve decoherence.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #14
Demystifier said:
The delayed choice is reversible precisely because it does not involve decoherence.

Got it.

It ties in with a discussion about entanglement and decoherence. Its easy to get the two confused.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #15
bhobba said:
Got it.

It ties in with a discussion about entanglement and decoherence. Its easy to get the two confused.
Yes. Decoherence always involves entanglement, but not the vice versa.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #16
Truecrimson said:
Step 3 A projectively measures F1 (the whole laboratory) and declares success if he gets the outcome $$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} (| H \rangle - | T \rangle ) $$ or failure if he gets the orthogonal outcome.
The problem with the paper is that they do not explain what does it mean to measure the whole laboratory. Certainly the whole laboratory cannot be in the state
$$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} (| H \rangle - | T \rangle ) $$
Instead, it should involve something like
$$ \sqrt{\frac{1}{2}} (| H \rangle - | T \rangle ) \otimes | {\rm detector \;\; shows\;\;} H-T \rangle$$
where the second factor is a macroscopic state that cannot be easily destroyed by a new measurement.
 
  • Like
Likes atyy
  • #17
My main issue with the paper is that I don't understand how it's justified to have the value of z be an element of the story of A, before A has carried out any measurement. To A, and hence (to my understanding), in any story about A's experiment, before they perform a measurement on the system F2, the total system F1 + F2 should be in a superposition, with components having both $$|z=+\frac{1}{2}\rangle$$ and $$|z=-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$$ elements; that is, a state to which one could not assign any definite value of z, at least if one wants to keep the eigenvalue-eigenstate link.

Yet, they consider $$(n:20,*,z,*)$$ to be a 'plot point' of A's story (in their notation, this roughly means that at time n:20, there exist some values for the asterisks such that the completed element is part of the set of events that characterize A's experiment). I don't see how that is justified; in particular, A could, instead of the measurement they perform in the paper, perform an interference experiment, which would tell them that indeed a superposed state is present (even after the measurement of F2). So it seems to me more natural to add some rule to the effect that 'quantities only have a definite value in X's story if the system is in an eigenstate of the relevant operator as described by X', which, it seems, would rule out the definiteness of $z$, and block the proof in the paper; thus, with such a rule in place, one could indeed find a consistent single-world interpretation. Or am I way off base here?
 
  • #18
Very interesting!

The authors provide a simple summary:

Main result (informal version)
There cannot exist a physical theory T that has all of the following properties
:
(QT) Compliance with quantum theory: T forbids all measurement results that are forbidden by standard quantum theory (and this condition holds even if the measured system is large enough to contain itself an experimenter).
(SW) Single-world: T rules out the occurrence of more than one single outcome if an experimenter measures a system once.
(SC) Self-consistency: T's statements about measurement outcomes are logically consistent (even if they are obtained by considering the perspectives of different experimenters).
 
  • Like
Likes entropy1
  • #19
Let's see if I understood this correctly.

Recall the state before any measurement by F2, A, and W: $$ |\psi \rangle = \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} (|H\rangle |\downarrow \rangle + |T\rangle |\downarrow \rangle + |T\rangle |\uparrow \rangle) $$ After the measurements, there are associated memory states which record the value of the spin and whether both A and W succeeded. For example, ## |\uparrow ,\checkmark \rangle ## means that the spin was measured to be up and A and W succeeded. Hence the total state will have 3 terms: $$ (|H\rangle +|T\rangle ) |\downarrow \rangle |\downarrow , \times \rangle, $$ $$ |T\rangle |\uparrow \rangle |\uparrow ,\checkmark \rangle ,$$ $$ |T\rangle |\uparrow \rangle |\uparrow ,\times \rangle $$ Given that A and W succeeded, putting the Heisenberg cut after F2's spin measurement or after A and W's measurements makes no difference. (You just collapse to the state to ## |T\rangle |\uparrow \rangle |\uparrow ,\checkmark \rangle ##.)

However A and F2 can't infer that because the spin is up, the outcome Tail must had happened because this entails a different set of memory states, one of which may look like this: $$ |T\rangle |\rightarrow \rangle |\rightarrow ,\times \rangle . $$ (F2 can make a measurement with 3 POVM elements: ## |\uparrow \rangle ##, ## |\leftarrow \rangle ## and another one to complete the resolution of the identity. This way, she will never confuse the states ## |\downarrow \rangle ## and ## |\rightarrow \rangle ## but the price to pay is that the third POVM element gives an inconclusive result.) The point is that they have to undo the measurement and

Demystifier said:
the [last] factor is a macroscopic state that cannot be easily destroyed by a new measurement.

Or even if they can undo the measurement, that memory A and W succeeded will no longer be there. So no one will predict that A and W succeed, and the contradiction cannot be reached.

Does this look remotely right?
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #20
S.Daedalus said:
My main issue with the paper is that I don't understand how it's justified to have the value of z be an element of the story of A, before A has carried out any measurement. To A, and hence (to my understanding), in any story about A's experiment, before they perform a measurement on the system F2, the total system F1 + F2 should be in a superposition, with components having both $$|z=+\frac{1}{2}\rangle$$ and $$|z=-\frac{1}{2}\rangle$$ elements; that is, a state to which one could not assign any definite value of z, at least if one wants to keep the eigenvalue-eigenstate link.

That was the point that I was suspicious of too. But now I wonder if it matters in this case? Sure, it is wrong to place the Heisenberg cut (and infer a definite value of an observable) too early, but conditional upon the success of A and W, this doesn't seem to affect the argument (as I mentioned in #19 above).
 
  • #21
Truecrimson said:
Recall the state before any measurement by F2, A, and W: $$ |\psi \rangle = \sqrt{\frac{1}{3}} (|H\rangle |\downarrow \rangle + |T\rangle |\downarrow \rangle + |T\rangle |\uparrow \rangle) $$
Now I noticed that this is nothing but the Hardy state, which is well known to lead to paradoxes if interpreted naively. See e.g.
http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/0609163
the discussion around Eq. (43) and references therein. See also
https://www.physicsforums.com/threa...d-joint-weak-measurement.298924/#post-2712422
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Truecrimson, entropy1 and bhobba
  • #22
I think this is an exercise for finding the conceptual error, nothing more. Because we have a counterexample to the claim with dBB theory. Define the configuration space as containing all observers with all their possible outcomes in all possible combinations. Then, define whatever wave function you like on this configuration space. Then look how it evolves. In dBB, we have a wave function on the universe, so measuring some Schrödinger сat state is possible and not a problem, because the state of the observer itself and the state of the wave function are different, independent things. I have to admit that I was unable to get the idea how they try to construct a contradiction.

I would guess they think in many worlds terms and confuse, therefore, wave functions or some parts of them with observers. But the observers in dBB are configurations, not wave functions.
 
  • #23
The measurement process is an inherently thermodynamic one ( think signal amplification if you need a paradigm) and so fundamentally you cannot (sharply) observe the observer.
 
  • #24
Ilja said:
I think this is an exercise for finding the conceptual error, nothing more. Because we have a counterexample to the claim with dBB theory. Define the configuration space as containing all observers with all their possible outcomes in all possible combinations. Then, define whatever wave function you like on this configuration space. Then look how it evolves. In dBB, we have a wave function on the universe, so measuring some Schrödinger сat state is possible and not a problem, because the state of the observer itself and the state of the wave function are different, independent things. I have to admit that I was unable to get the idea how they try to construct a contradiction.

I would guess they think in many worlds terms and confuse, therefore, wave functions or some parts of them with observers. But the observers in dBB are configurations, not wave functions.
The problem is that many people (including the authors) accept the claim that BM makes the same predictions as standard QM, but do not understand why exactly it makes the same predictions. To understand that, it is necessary to understand some elements of the quantum theory of measurement (e.g. von Neumann scheme, decoherence, and related stuff) which most physicists don't understand. Not because they are not smart enough (they usually understand many other, more difficult aspects of QM), but because most QM textbooks say nothing about it.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #25
Ilja said:
In dBB, we have a wave function on the universe, so measuring some Schrödinger сat state is possible and not a problem, because the state of the observer itself and the state of the wave function are different, independent things. I have to admit that I was unable to get the idea how they try to construct a contradiction.

I don't think they mean dBB is inconsistent in the normal sense of the word. I think they mean "inconsistent" in some rather strange technical sense, so it's not clear to me that dBB is a counterexample.

But it's not so clear why the strange sense is that interesting, so perhaps even though the paper could be correct, it's not very interesting.
 
  • #26
atyy said:
I don't think they mean dBB is inconsistent in the normal sense of the word. I think they mean "inconsistent" in some rather strange technical sense, so it's not clear to me that dBB is a counterexample.

But it's not so clear why the strange sense is that interesting, so perhaps even though the paper could be correct, it's not very interesting.
Here is the crucial quote from their paper, Sec. 6.3:
"It is certainly unsatisfactory if a theory is not self-consistent. One may therefore ask
whether there is an easy fix. One possibility could be to restrict the range of applicability
of the theory and add the rule that its predictions are only valid if an experimenter who
makes the predictions keeps all relevant information stored. While we do not normally
impose such a rule when using theories to make predictions, this would, at least in the
case of Bohmian mechanics, remove the inconsistency."

So they say that predictions of Bohmian mechanics are consistent, provided that one keeps all information that is relevant for making predictions. And I agree with this, but I consider it trivial. That can be said even for classical mechanics (CM). You can easily make inconsistent predictions with CM if you don't keep some relevant information. It seems that the authors think that QM is somehow different from CM because information is somehow naturally deleted by quantum measurements, and not by classical measurements. But this is wrong. The results of QM measurements are recorded by mechanisms which are essentially classical (e.g. by ink on the paper), so information is typically not deleted by new measurements. There is no need to impose such a rule as something additional, because that rule is already there.
 
  • #27
But there would be also no inconsistency if you forget information. The configuration space defines a set of consistent descriptions of what is possible at a particular moment. And this description is a global, observer-independent and consistent one. And dBB defines, at any moment, a consistent element of it, q(t). It also defines a wave function. And this wave function has to assign some non-zero probability to q(t). Which is all one needs. If the observer had memories about some past measurement result, this information would be part of the complete description q(t) now. If it is not, he now has no such information.
 
  • Like
Likes Truecrimson
  • #28
atyy said:
I don't think they mean dBB is inconsistent in the normal sense of the word. I think they mean "inconsistent" in some rather strange technical sense, so it's not clear to me that dBB is a counterexample.

But it's not so clear why the strange sense is that interesting, so perhaps even though the paper could be correct, it's not very interesting.
Demystifier said:
Here is the crucial quote from their paper, Sec. 6.3:
"It is certainly unsatisfactory if a theory is not self-consistent. One may therefore ask
whether there is an easy fix. One possibility could be to restrict the range of applicability
of the theory and add the rule that its predictions are only valid if an experimenter who
makes the predictions keeps all relevant information stored. While we do not normally
impose such a rule when using theories to make predictions, this would, at least in the
case of Bohmian mechanics, remove the inconsistency."

So they say that predictions of Bohmian mechanics are consistent, provided that one keeps all information that is relevant for making predictions. And I agree with this, but I consider it trivial. That can be said even for classical mechanics (CM). You can easily make inconsistent predictions with CM if you don't keep some relevant information. It seems that the authors think that QM is somehow different from CM because information is somehow naturally deleted by quantum measurements, and not by classical measurements. But this is wrong. The results of QM measurements are recorded by mechanisms which are essentially classical (e.g. by ink on the paper), so information is typically not deleted by new measurements. There is no need to impose such a rule as something additional, because that rule is already there.

I'm not sure I understand at all what they mean by "keep all relevant information stored". Are they saying that it is important that the information be in the form of a persistent record (which is sometimes considered important for something to count as an observation in QM)?
 
  • #29
stevendaryl said:
Are they saying that it is important that the information be in the form of a persistent record (which is sometimes considered important for something to count as an observation in QM)?
Yes, I think that this is what they are saying.
 
  • #30
Ilja said:
But there would be also no inconsistency if you forget information. The configuration space defines a set of consistent descriptions of what is possible at a particular moment. And this description is a global, observer-independent and consistent one. And dBB defines, at any moment, a consistent element of it, q(t). It also defines a wave function. And this wave function has to assign some non-zero probability to q(t). Which is all one needs. If the observer had memories about some past measurement result, this information would be part of the complete description q(t) now. If it is not, he now has no such information.
Nature is, of course, consistent if a person forgets information. But the predictions by such a person may not be. For instance, a meteorologist can make some weather predictions based on results of performed measurements, then he can forget the results of these measurements, and consequently make new predictions which differ from the initial ones. In such a case, the meteorologist makes two mutually contradictory predictions, so he is inconsistent. This, of course, is trivial, but it seems to me that the results in the paper are not much more different than that.
 
  • Like
Likes Truecrimson
  • #31
Demystifier said:
Yes, I think that this is what they are saying.

Well, in that case, I would say that this is different from similar considerations in classical mechanics. In classical mechanics, nothing physically important follows from the fact that information was not recorded. But in quantum mechanics, persistent records have a physical effect: there can be no interference between alternatives that have different persistent records. Of course, having a persistent record is not necessary for destroying interference, as decoherence and other kinds of entanglement show, but it is certainly sufficient.
 
  • Like
Likes maline, Truecrimson and Demystifier
  • #32
bhobba said:
Without looking at the detail it looks highly dubious to me.

In QM you need a framework of system being observed and something doing the observing.

I am not too sure of this. As we are on the subject of many worlds, Hughe Everett's work (many worlds theorem) describes definite outcomes (wave function collapse) in terms of corrolation of states and as such no oberver is needed, and different observations would just be different corrolations of states. Of course in his formulation it would be impossible for two observers to obtain contradictory results from the SAME experiment, as this would mean the observers themselves were in different uncorrolated states and thus could not communicate these results with each other.

Brage
 
  • #33
Brage said:
corrolation of states and as such no oberver is needed,

Every interpretation contains the standard formalism which has observables and that includes MW. Observers in QM are something much more general than observers used in general language and this leads to a lot of semantic difficulties. In modern times an observation is anything that leads to decoherence.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #34
bhobba said:
Every interpretation contains the standard formalism which has observables and that includes MW.

Thanks
Bill
Yes but the theory predicting observables does not mean observers are central to the theory, although I suppose you could argue in Everetts case any particle will itself be an observer.

Cheers
 
  • #35
Brage said:
observers are central to the theory

Observers in QM is something much more general than in normal usage - I added that refinement a bit later in my post.

Thanks
Bill
 
<h2>What is a single-world interpretation?</h2><p>A single-world interpretation is a theory in physics that suggests there is only one reality or universe. This means that everything that exists, including all events and objects, are contained within this single world.</p><h2>Why can single-world interpretations not be self-consistent?</h2><p>Single-world interpretations cannot be self-consistent because they do not account for the possibility of multiple realities or universes. This means that there is no way to explain or reconcile conflicting observations or theories within a single-world interpretation.</p><h2>What are some examples of single-world interpretations?</h2><p>One example of a single-world interpretation is the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, which states that particles exist in multiple states at once until they are observed. Another example is the Many-Worlds interpretation, which suggests that every possible outcome of an event exists in a separate universe.</p><h2>Are there any alternative interpretations to single-world interpretations?</h2><p>Yes, there are alternative interpretations to single-world interpretations, such as the Many-Worlds interpretation, which suggests the existence of multiple universes, or the Pilot Wave theory, which proposes that particles are guided by a hidden wave function.</p><h2>What are the implications of single-world interpretations in the scientific community?</h2><p>Single-world interpretations have been a topic of debate and controversy in the scientific community, as they challenge our understanding of reality and the laws of physics. They also raise questions about the role of observation and consciousness in shaping our understanding of the universe.</p>

What is a single-world interpretation?

A single-world interpretation is a theory in physics that suggests there is only one reality or universe. This means that everything that exists, including all events and objects, are contained within this single world.

Why can single-world interpretations not be self-consistent?

Single-world interpretations cannot be self-consistent because they do not account for the possibility of multiple realities or universes. This means that there is no way to explain or reconcile conflicting observations or theories within a single-world interpretation.

What are some examples of single-world interpretations?

One example of a single-world interpretation is the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, which states that particles exist in multiple states at once until they are observed. Another example is the Many-Worlds interpretation, which suggests that every possible outcome of an event exists in a separate universe.

Are there any alternative interpretations to single-world interpretations?

Yes, there are alternative interpretations to single-world interpretations, such as the Many-Worlds interpretation, which suggests the existence of multiple universes, or the Pilot Wave theory, which proposes that particles are guided by a hidden wave function.

What are the implications of single-world interpretations in the scientific community?

Single-world interpretations have been a topic of debate and controversy in the scientific community, as they challenge our understanding of reality and the laws of physics. They also raise questions about the role of observation and consciousness in shaping our understanding of the universe.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
47
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
15
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
59
Views
6K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
24
Views
543
Replies
2
Views
934
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
44
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
72
Views
6K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
59
Views
10K
Replies
9
Views
904
Replies
2
Views
522
Back
Top