Uncountable Set with this property

In summary: I wrote that... that... the set... is a countable union... of countable sets. That's what I said. This set... of... of... what did I say? Points? No, no... real numbers. Yes, real numbers. So... so... we've got this set... S... and it's a countable union... of countable sets. And... and... countable means... means... what was it again? Countable means... ah, I don't know, but it's a countable union... of countable... countable things. And that's... that's... that's... that's what we want. We want
  • #1
Dragonfall
1,030
4
Does there exist an uncountable set of positive reals such that every countable decreasing sequence from that set sums to a finite number?
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I don't know how to prove it rigorously, but I'd think it reduces to a problem in measure theory.

If your uncountable set contains any non-empty interval [a, b], it fails to have the countable-sums property.

All non-empty intervals have a nonzero measure. I wouldn't be surprised if the converse was true for the real numbers. Let's assume it is for now. This means that if our uncountable set has a nonzero measure, it contains an interval, and fails to have our desired property. So, we conclude our set has zero measure.

Sets of zero measure are countable. This is our contradiction.Again, this is just my intuition. I don't know much about measure theory, but if I did, this is what I would expect the proof to look like ;-)EDIT: Or maybe the Cantor set is a counter example to the last assumption I made. It is uncountable with zero measure. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Measure_zero)
 
Last edited:
  • #3
Tac-Tics said:
EDIT: Or maybe the Cantor set is a counter example to the last assumption I made. It is uncountable with zero measure. (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Measure_zero)
Beat me to it.
 
  • #4
I'm thinking that any uncountable set has at least one accumulation point away from zero. The problem is that if the accumulation point is from a sequence of increasing numbers instead of decreasing. Then it wouldn't work.
 
  • #5
Pretty sure this proof works:

Obviously, if a set [tex] S [/tex] is to have the desired property, then [tex] S \cap [a,b] [/tex] is finite for all positive [tex] a [/tex] and [tex] b [/tex]. (Indeed, if [tex] S \cap [a,b] [/tex] has infinitely many elements, we can choose a countably infinite, decreasing sequence, which necessarily diverges, since all terms are [tex] \geq a [/tex].) Furthermore, if [tex] S [/tex] has this property, then any uncountable subset of [tex] S [/tex] also does; thus, WLOG, [tex] S \subseteq (0, \infty) [/tex] (if [tex] S \cap (0, \infty) [/tex] is countable, then [tex] S \cap (-\infty, 0) [/tex] is uncountable, and we may proceed in essentially the same way). Define [tex]\displaystyle U_i = \left[ \frac{1}{i + 1}, \frac{1}{i} \right] [/tex] for [tex] i \geq 1 [/tex], and [tex] U_0 = [1, \infty] [/tex]. By above, [tex] \displaystyle \bigcup_{i = 0}^{\infty} (S \cap U_i) = S [/tex] (since [tex] S \subseteq (0, \infty) [/tex]); however, recall that each term [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] has finite order. Thus, [tex] S [/tex] is a countable union of finite sets, and is therefore countable. This is a contradiction; hence, no such set can exist.
 
  • #6
VKint said:
(Indeed, if [tex] S \cap [a,b] [/tex] has infinitely many elements, we can choose a countably infinite, decreasing sequence, which necessarily diverges, since all terms are [tex] \geq a [/tex].)
Actually, that's not guaranteed. For example, consider the infinite set containing
1, 1.9, 1.99, 1.999, 1.9999, 1.99999, ...​
Every decreasing sequence whose elements in this set is necessarily finite.

The thing we can prove with this argument is that [itex]S \cap [a, \infty)[/itex] is well-ordered by <.
 
  • #7
Excellent point, Hurkyl; I guess that's what I get for trying to write up a post while on Vicodin. Wisdom teeth... :(

I think my proof can still be repaired, though. All I really need to show is that [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] is countable for all [tex] i [/tex] (a countable union of countable sets is countable). We prove the following lemma:

Lemma: Let [tex] V [/tex] be a bounded set of real numbers. If, for all [tex] x \in V [/tex], the set [tex] \{ y \in V \; | \; y < x \} [/tex] is countable, then [tex] V [/tex] is countable.
Proof: Let [tex] q = \sup(V) [/tex]. Clearly, if [tex] q \in V [/tex], we're done. Thus, WLOG, [tex] q \notin V [/tex]. Let [tex] p [/tex] be a lower bound for [tex] V [/tex], and let [tex] d = q - p [/tex]. Define [tex]\displaystyle T_i = \left[ q - \frac{d}{2^i}, q \right] [/tex]. Since [tex] q [/tex] is the supremum of [tex] V [/tex], it is also an accumulation point, so [tex] V \cap T_i \neq \emptyset [/tex] for all [tex] i [/tex]. Thus, using the axiom of choice if necessary, we can choose some non-decreasing sequence of points [tex] x_i \in V \cap T_i [/tex]. Finally, define [tex] Q_i = \{ z \in V \; | \; z < x_i \} [/tex] (running out of letters...) and observe that [tex]\displaystyle V = \bigcup_{i = 0}^{\infty} Q_i [/tex], i.e., a countable union of countable sets (by hypothesis). This concludes the proof.

Now that we have this result, we can prove that [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] is countable by contradiction. As before, the contradiction comes from assuming that [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] is uncountable, and constructing a countable decreasing sequence of points in [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex]. Indeed, if [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] is uncountable, we can choose some [tex] x_0 \in S \cap U_i [/tex] such that [tex] \{ y \in S \cap U_i \; | \; y<x \} [/tex] is uncountable by the lemma. It should be easy to see now that we can construct a strictly decreasing sequence of points in [tex] S \cap U_i [/tex] inductively, which gives the same contradiction as before.
 
  • #8
Every well ordered (by <) set is countable. Then [itex]S=\cup_a (S\cap [a,\infty))[/itex] for a that are inverse powers of 2. S is therefore a countable union of countable sets, which is countable. Contradiction.

EDIT: I think you went overboard there with your lemma.
 
  • #9
Every well ordered (by <) set is countable.

Not if you allow the axiom of choice...I think.
 
  • #10
VKint said:
Not if you allow the axiom of choice...I think.

But then an uncountable well-ordered set would be a counterexample to your contradiction, it would have the property we're looking for!
 
  • #11
But then an uncountable well-ordered set would be a counterexample to your contradiction.

Not at all. You'll notice that in the statement of my lemma, I specifically noted that the result only applied to set of real numbers, implying the the usual ordering on the reals must be used for the result to remain valid. In other words, the lemma proved that no uncountable set is well-ordered under the usual ordering of [tex] \mathbb{R} [/tex], which does not preclude the existence of some other well-ordering.

EDIT: I just realize that this was what you were getting at all along when you said "well ordered (by <)," in which case you were correct. My lemma was essentially just a proof of your statement that "every well ordered (by <) set is countable." Apologies for the misunderstanding.
 
Last edited:
  • #12
Incidentally, where did this problem come from?
 
  • #13
I thought it up when I was playing around with the idea of uncountable sums (a previous post).
 
  • #14
If one permits the Axiom of Choice, the reals can be well ordered.

(In fact the Well Ordering Theorem, the Axiom of Choice, and Zorn's Lemma (among others) are all equivalent.)

--Elucidus
 
  • #15
So trying to rewrite what you've written in a more generally useful form, I think you've shown the following.

Define an uncountable accumulation point of a set X to be a point such that every neighborhood of that point contains uncountably many points of X.
(I doubt this is a standard term)

Every uncountable subset of R has an uncountable accumulation point​

and a slight modification will allow

Every uncountable subset of R has at least countably infinitely many uncountable accumulation points​


I haven't worked out whether or not it must have uncountably many uncountably accumulation points...
 
  • #16
Every uncountable subset of R has an uncountable accumulation point

I don't see how this follows directly from what I proved. However, it's fairly easy to prove this by using the second-countability of [tex] \mathbb{R} [/tex]. Indeed, if [tex] S \subseteq \mathbb{R} [/tex] is uncountable but has no uncountable accumulation point, then for all [tex] x \in S [/tex] there exists an open set [tex] U_x [/tex] with [tex] x \in U_x [/tex] and [tex] S \cap U_x [/tex] countable. Open sets are closed even under uncountable unions, so the set [tex]\displaystyle T = \bigcup_{x \in S} U_x [/tex] is open. However, since [tex] \mathbb{R} [/tex] is second-countable, each [tex] U_x [/tex] may be written as a union of base open sets [tex] B_{x,i} [/tex] for [tex] i \in I_x [/tex] (i.e., some countable index set), each of which has [tex] S \cap B_{x,i} [/tex] countable. We then have [tex]\displaystyle T = \bigcup_{x \in S, \; i \in I_x} B_{x,i} [/tex]. However, since the base is countable, this is at most a countable union. The set [tex] S [/tex] is then a countable union of countable sets, so it is countable.

Your next proposition follows fairly trivially from the first (by simply removing successive uncountable accumulation points). I also think I have a proof that any uncountable [tex] S \in \mathbb{R} [/tex] must have uncountably many uncountable accumulation points. Indeed, suppose not. Let [tex] X \subseteq S [/tex] be the set of all uncountable accumulation points. Then, since [tex] X [/tex] is countable, [tex] S \setminus X [/tex] is uncountable. Thus, [tex] S \setminus X [/tex] must contain an uncountable accumulation point, contradicting assumption.

Thoughts?
 
  • #17
VKint said:
I don't see how this follows directly from what I proved.
I don't remember precisely what I was thinking -- but I had convinced myself my first proposition was either an easy consequence of what you had proved, or that your proof of your lemma contained most/all of the bits needed to prove my proposition.


The proof you give of my second and third propositions is flawed -- accumulation points of S don't actually have to be elements of S, so you don't get the contradiction you were relying on.
 
  • #18
Hurkyl said:
Define an uncountable accumulation point of a set X to be a point such that every neighborhood of that point contains uncountably many points of X. (I doubt this is a standard term)

"condensation point"
 
  • #19
The proof you give of my second and third propositions is flawed -- accumulation points of S don't actually have to be elements of S, so you don't get the contradiction you were relying on.

I must have misunderstood what you intended. The proof I gave in #16 assumed that uncountable accumulation points ("condensation points") must lie in the uncountable set itself, and proved that every uncountable subset of [tex] \mathbb{R} [/tex] must have at least one such point. If you wanted to prove the existence of a condensation point not necessarily in the target set, you could do it by an inductive method similar to that used to prove the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem--dividing a bounded region containing an uncountable set into finitely many pieces at each step, and picking one point from a piece with uncountably many points. In the end, you get a convergent sequence of points in the set, which must converge to a condensation point.
 
  • #20
How about simply this:

For any a>0, there must be a right neighbourhood of a containing no members of S (otherwise we could create a decreasing sequence approaching a), i.e. a number b>a such that there are only countably many members of S on the interval [itex]\langle a; b\rangle[/itex]. Assuming that there are uncountably many members of S on the interval [itex]\langle a;+\infty)[/itex] yields a contradiction: just take the supremum* of all c>a s.t. there are only countably many members of S on the interval [itex]\langle a; c \rangle[/itex] and extend the interval a little. Therefore, for any a>0, there is only a countable number of members of S greater than a. But this proves the proposition, as S is the countable union of sets of the form [itex]S \cap \langle \frac{1}{n} ; \infty)[/itex].

edit: * if no such number exists, then [itex]S \cap \langle a; \infty)[/itex] is countable, being a countable union of countable sets.
 
  • #21
Preno said:
How about simply this...

Yup, that's pretty much what we did back there.

Elucidus said:
If one permits the Axiom of Choice, the reals can be well ordered.

Yes, but < is not a well-ordering of the reals.
 

1. What is an uncountable set with this property?

An uncountable set with this property refers to a set that contains an infinite number of elements that cannot be counted or enumerated. This means that the elements in the set are not able to be put in a one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers.

2. How do you know if a set is uncountable?

A set is considered uncountable if it contains an infinite number of elements that cannot be counted or enumerated. This can be determined by using the Cantor's diagonalization argument or by showing that there is no bijective function from the set to the natural numbers.

3. What is the significance of this property in mathematics?

The property of being an uncountable set is important in mathematics because it helps distinguish between sets that can be counted and those that cannot. It also has implications in areas such as set theory, measure theory, and topology.

4. Can an uncountable set have a countable subset?

Yes, an uncountable set can have a countable subset. This is because a subset of a set is a set that contains only elements of the original set. Therefore, if the original set is uncountable, it can still have subsets that are countable.

5. Are there different types of uncountable sets with this property?

Yes, there are different types of uncountable sets with this property. Some examples include the set of real numbers, the set of all subsets of natural numbers, and the set of all functions from natural numbers to real numbers. Each of these sets has different properties and characteristics, but they are all considered uncountable.

Similar threads

Replies
15
Views
1K
  • General Math
Replies
34
Views
2K
Replies
8
Views
911
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
6
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
22
Views
2K
Replies
5
Views
1K
Replies
31
Views
5K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
5
Views
2K
Back
Top