gentzen said:
Most mathematical theories can be interpreted both "literal" and "in their original context". For QT, MWI would be an attempt at a "literal" interpretation, and Copenhagen the practice of interpretation close to "the original context" of QT.
I'm still not seeing any observable contradictions. You are explaining what an interpretation is. I'm explaining what a physics theory
isn't.
gentzen said:
My reaction to any "literal" interpretation is fear of the dangers of stupid mistakes. I have no illusions about my chances to convince proponents of "literal" interpretations of the existence of such dangers.
And why should you try? What keeps you from making "stupid mistakes" is personal, like all philosophy. It would be valid science to test a thousand people of equal experience and aptitude who are trying to use QT to make predictions within the various interpretations, and score the number of stupid mistakes they make using each interpretation, but you can see how that is not the way debates over interpretations usually go.
gentzen said:
So let me instead go with the existence of scalable quantum computers that are exponentially faster than classical computers for certain problems (like factoring) as a falsifiable predictions of MWI (because of David Deutsch). Notice that quantum computers are outside of "the original context" of QT.
The issue is not the "context" of QT, but the
predictions of it. If what you are saying is outside the predictions of QT, then it's simply not QT. That's the point, a physics theory makes predictions, and if the predictions are different, it's a different theory, not a different interpretation. I realize that different interpretations of one theory can suggest different ways to alter that theory to create a new one, just as different interpretations of Newtonian physics led to general relativity. But that's because general relativity is a
different theory, not because it's a different interpretation of Newton's theory. It is perfectly valid to debate how different interpretations of QT could lead to new different theories, indeed that's precisely what interpretations are for. But you see the pointlessness of
arguing the interpretations themselves.
gentzen said:
Additionally, for Copenhagen, quantum computers are related to limits like zero temperature or perfect isolation, and it remains unclear whether those limits stand in the way of scalability or not.
It sounds like you are saying the Copenhagen interpretation predicts something about quantum computers that other interpretations do not predict. That would be impossible, because then the CT would not be an interpretation of a theory, it would be different theory that makes different predictions using different equations. It could not use all the same equations, because how can you use all the same equations and make a different prediction? I think you are not talking about interpretations of QT, you are guessing at whatever the next theory might be. To be clear, I don't say that interpretations have no value, they have value in understanding a given theory, and a value in inspiring new theories that are different from the given theory. That's exactly what interpretations are supposed to do, but the interpretations don't make different predictions because only a theory can make a prediction.
gentzen said:
In fact, I believe Bohmian mechanics provides the clearest mathematical examples to see how it contradicts both MWI and Copenhagen.
If there is such a contradiction, it must not come from "mathematical examples," it must come from different predictions. Experiment A must come out X for one and not X for the other, where X is a quantitative prediction. Theories produce such things, interpretations do not.
gentzen said:
Euclidean geometry is (proto-)typical example of a mathematical theory.
You are now talking about mathematical theories. I would have thought it would be very clear in that context that interpretations of a mathematical theory are not a different theory, or they would be called a different theory with different axioms and postulates, not a different interpretation of the same axioms and postulates.
gentzen said:
Where Euclidean geometry is quite untypical is that after the addition of THE missing axiom, it was indeed a complete theory from a purely mathematical point of view.
Any mathematical theory is
defined by its axioms, so it is logically impossible for an axiom to be missing from one. I believe what you mean is that a better version of the theory that Euclid was trying to create can be made by adding an additional axiom that he did not think to add. That would make it a different mathematical theory. Whether a mathematical theory is "better" by using a different set of axioms is a question completely outside mathematics, but it does relate to the philosophical reasons we do mathematics. That is also like interpretations that are outside of science, but relate to the personal and philosophical reasons we do science.
gentzen said:
Still, its applicability to the world around us and its range of validity remains open to interpretation.
A new meaning for "interpretation." Now you are not talking about interpretations of a mathematical theory, you are talking about interpretations of real world applicability. That sounds like philosophy for sure, and certainly not mathematics.
gentzen said:
This again is quite typical for mathematical theories, as discussed again and again by Werner Heisenberg in his book Physics and Philosophy:
Thank you for quoting the insights of Heisenberg, but they just sound to me like a careful distinction between physics and philosophy, very much along the same lines as what I am saying. Heisenberg is saying that the physics is the theory that makes predictions, but how well those predictions correspond to the real world is something outside the physics theory. It is in the realm of testing the theory, and deciding if it meets whatever needs were set out for it. The interpretations of a theory are among the latter of those two, and can be very personal, like all philosophy. Paul Davies quote seems to agree with this as well, it's just what I'm saying. All I'm adding is that I find it curious people think QT is somehow different from all other physics theories, when in fact they all possess these exact same properties. You could take the quotes by Heisenberg and Davies and replace all references to QT with references to Newtonian mechanics and it's all just the same.
gentzen said:
The examples would have been Bell type experiments where the decision by the experimenter can be modeled by a time dependent Hamiltonian in Bohmian mechanics, but not in MWI.
But this is exactly the point, at issue is not "how it can be modeled", but rather, the testable predictions it makes. From the perspective of a scientific theory, everything else is counting angels on a pin. From the perspective of personal philosophy, and inspirations for the next theory, that's where we have interpretations. But just as Heisenberg implied, the interpretations don't tell you anything, you still need to interview reality to obtain knowledge.
gentzen said:
To see that this is incompatible with Bohmian mechanics, note that what is described here would be a backaction of the trajectories on the wavefunction, which is not possible (or at least not included) in Bohmian mechanics.
Again that all sounds, at best, like confusing an interpretation with a theory, and at worst, a category error about what an interpretation of a theory is. It is not the purpose of a theory to say what is really happening, the purpose is to make testable predictions, period. Some hold that the job of an interpretation is to say what is really happening, but that just sounds like kidding oneself to me. If one stays within the realm of science, the job of an interpretation is to create a personal sense of understanding of a theory, not to make sense of reality (as the latter can be done by no other means than experimentation). It is pure personal philosophy to use interpretations for the latter purpose, which is fine as a personal philosophy, but its only projection onto the scientific process appears in how it can be used to inspire new theories. Whether or not it is ever "what is actually happening" is entirely unscientific, because it is not testable beyond simply testing the theory itself, which never requires any interpretation or philosophy.