Constructing Infinite Sequence in R: Well-Ordering of Reals Explained

  • Thread starter Ookke
  • Start date
In summary: Submit.In summary, the conversation discussed the possibility of constructing an infinite sequence with a limit point in a total order on the set of real numbers. The axiom of choice was mentioned as a means to prove the existence of such a sequence, but its acceptance was debated. The idea of well-ordering the reals was also mentioned, and it was argued that it is equivalent to the axiom of choice. The possibility of splitting uncountable intervals into two uncountable parts was explored, and a counterexample using the smallest uncountable ordinal, \omega_1, was presented. The conversation then shifted to discussing the use of uncountable ordinals in mathematics, particularly in proving the non
  • #1
Ookke
172
0
If < is any total order in R, isn't it always possible to construct an infinite sequence
x1 > x2 > x3 > ... > y for some limit point y in R.

It seems to me that {x1, x2, x3, ...} is then a subset of R that does not have
least element in this ordering. No total order in R can be well-order?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
The axiom of choice says that such a sequence exists. You may or may not accept that axiom.
 
  • #3
Ookke said:
If < is any total order in R, isn't it always possible to construct an infinite sequence
x1 > x2 > x3 > ... > y for some limit point y in R.
Why would it?

Do keep in mind that a total order on R does not have to bear much resemblance to the usual order.
 
  • #4
Hurkyl said:
Why would it?

Do keep in mind that a total order on R does not have to bear much resemblance to the usual order.

It's just an intuition of that uncountable set is necessarily kind of dense for any order, not just the common order.

I had in mind two assumptions which seem quite natural:
1. Uncountable set of reals must have uncountable interval (a,b) for any order <.
2. It's always possible to split uncountable interval into two parts, both uncountable.

Then what follows, we can split (a,b) into two parts, select x1 from the upper part. Then split lower part again into two parts, select x2 from the new upper part, and so on. This way should be formed a sequence {x1, x2, ...} where x1 > x2 > ... for the order <, and the sequence does not have a least element.

I'm just developing the idea, but if this is already flawed, I would appreciate any point.
 
  • #5
Ookke said:
2. It's always possible to split uncountable interval into two parts, both uncountable.
This is demonstratably false, by a rather slick argument. It depends on two facts:

(1) The class of all ordinal numbers is well-ordered
(2) There exists an uncountable ordinal

Therefore, there exists a smallest uncountable ordinal number; let's call it [itex]\omega_1[/itex].

Now, consider the (uncountable) half-open [itex][0, \omega_1)[/itex] of ordinal numbers. If you choose any ordinal [itex]\alpha[/itex] in this interval, we have:
* [itex][0, \alpha][/itex] is countable,
* [itex][\alpha, \omega_1)[/itex] is uncountable.​
In particular, every Dedekind cut of [itex][0, \omega_1)[/itex] has a countable lower part.
 
  • #6
Ok, thanks. Had fun trying, now I need to learn some ordinals.
 
  • #7
Since you're researching it anyways -- it might interest you to look at another counterexample you can create using [itex]\omega_1[/itex]: the long ray.
 
  • #8
Hurkyl said:
Therefore, there exists a smallest uncountable ordinal number; let's call it [itex]\omega_1[/itex].

I found an interesting article about smallest uncountable set:
http://www.math.fsu.edu/~bellenot/class/su08/found/other/omega-one.pdf

From there, I understood that it's possible to have uncountable set X for which every [itex]seg(y) = \{x\in X | x < y\}[/itex] is countable. This is exactly against an idea I had for proving my second assumption (yes it hurts, but I don't care).

But why is it impossible to have a sequence [itex]\{x_n\}[/itex] in X that takes up the whole X, i.e. for any x, [itex]x < x_n[/itex] for large enough n?

Existence of such a sequence seems almost obvious to me, and this would be enough to prove X as union of [itex]seg(x_n)[/itex] countable. Or is it just that because of initial assumptions, we must deny this kind of sequences. Do you happen to know any "real-world" example where any sequence cannot take the whole set?
 
  • #9
Ookke said:
But why is it impossible to have a sequence [itex]\{x_n\}[/itex] in X that takes up the whole X, i.e. for any x, [itex]x < x_n[/itex] for large enough n?
...
Existence of such a sequence seems almost obvious to me, and this would be enough to prove X as union of [itex]seg(x_n)[/itex] countable.
And since we know [itex]\omega_1[/itex] isn't countable, that tells you why it's impossible.

If this seems obvious to you, that just means your intuition isn't equipped to deal with orders of uncountable cofinality. ("cofinality" measures this quality of orders)


Do you happen to know any "real-world" example where any sequence cannot take the whole set?
"Real world" is very much in the eye of the beholder. As I mentioned in my previous post, [itex]\omega_1[/itex] can be used to construct counterexamples, such as the long ray -- which tells geometers if they want to study more "normal"-looking spaces, they need to require that manifolds aren't merely Hausdorff and locally Euclidean... one must also insist on second countability.

I've personally explicitly used uncountable ordinals in proofs because my preferred method of applying the axiom of choice is to use the well-ordering theorem along with transfinite iteration1.

I've also explicitly used them to help understand nonstandard analysis. (In particular, to understand just how ugly the hyperreals look when studied externally)

1: This refers to a form of transfinite induction that I find particularly natural, but I don't think it's a standard term.
 
  • #10
discountbrain said:
This is the most messed up forum I've ever seen. It kept going round and round saying I wasn't logged in and then it said I was. I wrote my proof that the reals can't be well ordered and went to post it and then it said I wasn't logged in and erased it.

Whenever I write a long post for ANY online forum, I always Select All and Copy it before I hit Submit. That's because every website has occasional hiccups and sometimes your browser loses your text. It happens often enough that if I write something long or complicated enough, I'll make sure to save it in my Copy buffer just in case.

I actually picked up this good habit on the Craigslist forums, which used to have a fairly high frequency of these types of errors.

In any event, you should first convince yourself that you can prove that the existence of a well-ordering of the reals is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. If you can then prove that no well-order exists, then a) If you assumed the negation of AC you have re-proven a known result; or b) If you assumed AC, you have discovered an inconsistency in mathematics and you will become famous.

So if you really have a proof, it's worth cleaning it up and posting it again. Not so much because I believe you've discovered an inconsistency in set theory; but because the effort to re-write and think through the math will help you learn more about the subject.

Over the years I always find that whenever I write something and the computer eats it, it comes out much better when I rewrite it.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • Like
Likes berkeman
  • #11
Ookke said:
If < is any total order in R, isn't it always possible to construct an infinite sequence
x1 > x2 > x3 > ... > y for some limit point y in R.

For an arbitrary total ordering there is no notion of distance.

It seems to me that {x1, x2, x3, ...} is then a subset of R that does not have
least element in this ordering. No total order in R can be well-order?

The Axiom of Choice guarantees that any set can be well ordered.
 
  • #12
I'll have to retract what I said. If <* well orders R then each subset of R has a least element with respect to <*. I was thinking of a nonempty set {x: a<*x<*b} or {x:a<*x} with respect to <*. This should be a valid subset of R with no least element. But such a set by assumption should contain a least element, L ≠ to a, but there appears to be no way to prove there are numbers in this set between a and L with respect to <*. The fact that I can write such a set suggests that it exists and has no least element with respect to <*. The conclusion is If W.O. is correct there does exists an ordering <* such that there is no S subset of R such that
{x: xεS, a<*x<*b} or interval (a,b) with respect to <* exists.

I was going to add more, but this thing keeps telling me I'm not logged in.
 
  • #13
discountbrain said:
I'll have to retract what I said. If <* well orders R then each subset of R has a least element with respect to <*. I was thinking of a nonempty set {x: a<*x<*b} or {x:a<*x} with respect to <*. This should be a valid subset of R with no least element. But such a set by assumption should contain a least element, L ≠ to a, but there appears to be no way to prove there are numbers in this set between a and L with respect to <*. The fact that I can write such a set suggests that it exists and has no least element with respect to <*. The conclusion is If W.O. is correct there does exists an ordering <* such that there is no S subset of R such that
{x: xεS, a<*x<*b} or interval (a,b) with respect to <* exists.

I was going to add more, but this thing keeps telling me I'm not logged in.

Try clearing your cookies and starting over. I've never had trouble with this site. I think they had some login issues a couple of weeks ago.
 

1. What is the well-ordering principle for real numbers?

The well-ordering principle for real numbers states that any non-empty set of real numbers has a least element, meaning that there is always a smallest number in the set.

2. How is the well-ordering principle different from the completeness property?

The completeness property states that any non-empty set of real numbers that is bounded above has a least upper bound, while the well-ordering principle applies to all non-empty sets of real numbers, regardless of whether they are bounded or not.

3. How is the well-ordering principle used in mathematics?

The well-ordering principle is used in various areas of mathematics, including set theory, topology, and analysis. It is particularly useful in proving the existence of certain mathematical objects, such as least elements, minimal/maximal elements, and well-ordered sets.

4. Can the well-ordering principle be generalized to other sets?

Yes, the well-ordering principle can be generalized to other sets, such as the set of natural numbers or the set of integers. However, it does not hold for all sets, as there are some sets that cannot be well-ordered.

5. Is the well-ordering principle a fundamental property of real numbers?

Yes, the well-ordering principle is considered a fundamental property of real numbers, as it is closely related to other important concepts in mathematics, such as induction and the axiom of choice. It also plays a crucial role in establishing the uniqueness and completeness of the real number system.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
9
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
14
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • Introductory Physics Homework Help
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
15
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • Topology and Analysis
Replies
11
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
3K
Back
Top