What is peano postulates: Definition and 4 Discussions

In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (, [peˈaːno]), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly unchanged in a number of metamathematical investigations, including research into fundamental questions of whether number theory is consistent and complete.
The need to formalize arithmetic was not well appreciated until the work of Hermann Grassmann, who showed in the 1860s that many facts in arithmetic could be derived from more basic facts about the successor operation and induction. In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided an axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic. In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a simplified version of them as a collection of axioms in his book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method (Latin: Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita).
The nine Peano axioms contain three types of statements. The first axiom asserts the existence of at least one member of the set of natural numbers. The next four are general statements about equality; in modern treatments these are often not taken as part of the Peano axioms, but rather as axioms of the "underlying logic". The next three axioms are first-order statements about natural numbers expressing the fundamental properties of the successor operation. The ninth, final axiom is a second-order statement of the principle of mathematical induction over the natural numbers, which makes this formulation close to second-order arithmetic. A weaker first-order system called Peano arithmetic is obtained by explicitly adding the addition and multiplication operation symbols and replacing the second-order induction axiom with a first-order axiom schema.

View More On Wikipedia.org
  1. I

    Prove if ##a\cdot c = b \cdot c## then ##a = b## using Peano postulates

    with this background, we proceed to the proof. Let us define a set $$ G = \{ x \in \mathbb{N} | \; y, z \in \mathbb{N}\; \text{ if } (x \cdot z) = (y \cdot z) \text{ then } x = y \} $$ We want to prove that ##G = \mathbb{N} ##. For this purpose, we will use part 3) of Peano postulates...
  2. I

    Prove ##(a\cdot b)\cdot c =a\cdot (b \cdot c)## using Peano postulates

    with this background, we proceed to the proof. Let us define a set $$ G = \{ z \in \mathbb{N} | \; x, y \in \mathbb{N}\; (x \cdot y) \cdot z = x \cdot (y \cdot z) \} $$ We want to prove that ##G = \mathbb{N} ##. For this purpose, we will use part 3) of Peano postulates given above...
  3. I

    Prove ##a\cdot b = b \cdot a ##using Peano postulates

    with this background, we proceed to the proof. Let us define a set $$ G = \{ z \in \mathbb{N} | \mbox{ if } y \in \mathbb{N}, y\cdot z = z \cdot y \} $$ We want to prove that ##G = \mathbb{N} ##. For this purpose, we will use part 3) of Peano postulates given above. Obviously, ## G...
  4. I

    Prove ##1 + a=s(a)=a+1## for ##a \in \mathbb{N}##

    I have to prove that ##1 + a = s(a) = a + 1## using Peano postulates if ##a \in \mathbb{N}##. The book I am using ("The real numbers and real analysis" by Ethan Bloch) defines Peano postulates little differently. Following is a set of Peano postulates I am using. (Axiom 1.2.1 in Bloch's book)...
Back
Top