Can Everett Branches Break Quantum Laws?

In summary, the "branches" or "worlds" referred to in discussions of the Many Worlds Interpretation (MWI) of quantum mechanics have mathematical counterparts in the form of subspaces in the Hilbert space. These subspaces represent the possible outcomes or results of measurements in a given experiment, with each subspace corresponding to a particular outcome. In particular, this can be seen in the example of a Stern-Gerlach experiment, where the two output "slots" correspond to the two subspaces of the Hilbert space. However, to fully understand the math behind MWI, more background in quantum mechanics is necessary.
  • #1
bluecap
396
13
Are Everett branches (or relative states) the eigenstates or the Hilbert subspaces (or others?)?

Once in a branch (or world), what law of QM would be broken if you can cut off the branch you are sitting on and revert back to the global state vector (isn't the quantum eraser, etc. about upcollapsing wave function or recoherence of the branches?)?

Your help greatly appreciated!
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
bluecap said:
Are Everett branches (or relative states) the eigenstates or the Hilbert subspaces (or others?)?

When you brought this topic up in a previous thread I asked you to point at some actual math, since you were bringing it up at an "I" level. The same applies here. Please show some actual math behind what you describe as "Everett branches", "eigenstates", "Hilbert subspaces", etc. This topic cannot be discussed productively if all we have is vague ordinary language.
 
  • #3
bluecap said:
Once in a branch (or world), what law of QM would be broken if you can cut off the branch you are sitting on and revert back to the global state vector

This is easy: the law of unitary evolution.

bluecap said:
(isn't the quantum eraser, etc. about upcollapsing wave function or recoherence of the branches?)?

No. Once again, if you were looking at the actual math, it would be a lot easier for you to understand what is going on. Your ordinary language descriptions are misleading you.
 
  • #4
PeterDonis said:
When you brought this topic up in a previous thread I asked you to point at some actual math, since you were bringing it up at an "I" level. The same applies here. Please show some actual math behind what you describe as "Everett branches", "eigenstates", "Hilbert subspaces", etc. This topic cannot be discussed productively if all we have is vague ordinary language.

Sorry I changed the level from "I" to "B" because I am just learning the math and concepts laymen way. You wrote elsewhere:

"In the double slit experiment, if we are sloppy and talk about "position eigenstates" as if they were actual states, then after the particle hits the detector and is detected, it is in a position eigenstate. If we are not sloppy, then we have to say that after the particle hits the detector and is detected, it is in a state with a very narrow spread of amplitude as a function of position--heuristically, a state in which the particle's position is somewhere within a very small "box" (the size of the "box" corresponds to the spatial resolution of the detector). But these are states of a single-particle system, not a multi-particle system."

Many accounts of Many Worlds always refer to the detector hits in the double slits as Worlds or Branches. But these are for simply systems like single-particle system and double slit experiment. In our macroscopic world we are living in one branch of the so called universal wave function. So you can't model it as Eigenstates anymore like you explained before. So for macroscopic world.. the subspace is the so called World or Branch in MWI? I just need a conceptual understanding so just want advisors to confirm yes or no or exactly what is the mathematical equivalents of the famous Worlds or Branches in simple layman terms. About Subspace, you explained thus:

It appears that you don't understand what a "subspace" is. Let me illustrate with a particular example. Suppose we have measured the center of mass position of a two-particle system to be ##X = 0##; i.e., we have measured the center of mass of the two-particle system to be at the spatial origin. The full Hilbert space of the two-particle system is the set of all wave functions ##\Psi(x_1, x_2)## of two positions. Our measurement of the center of mass position restricts the state of the two-particle system to the subset ##\Psi_0(x_1, x_2)## for which ##x_2 = - x_1## (because the average position must be ##0##), i.e., to the set of functions ##\Psi(x_1, x_2)## which only have nonzero values when ##x_2 = - x_1##. This set of functions is a subspace of the full Hilbert space. But a "pure state" is a single function ##\Psi(x_1, x_2)##, not a whole set of them. (Strictly speaking, this is only true if we have defined the wave functions appropriately, so that each one corresponds to a distinct ray in the Hilbert space; but we'll ignore that complication here.)

Is it a known thing that the subspace is the MW branches?

You have a point that it's better to just think of the maths and forgets about interpretations. No problem. But I just want to know what is the QM math counterparts for MW branches or worlds.. That's all. Thank you.
 
  • #5
bluecap said:
I changed the level from "I" to "B"

I'm not sure this topic can be productively discussed at the "B" level, but I'll try.

bluecap said:
So you can't model it as Eigenstates anymore like you explained before.

That is not what I said before, but it's not worth trying to disentangle that here. For this discussion I suggest that you forget whatever you think you know about eigenstates. I won't use that term at all in what follows.

bluecap said:
So for macroscopic world.. the subspace is the so called World or Branch in MWI?

Sort of. See below.

bluecap said:
I just want to know what is the QM math counterparts for MW branches or worlds.

If I give you an answer to this, it won't be at the "B" level. To even understand the math at all, you need more background than that. But here is the best answer I can give.

Let's take an even simpler experiment than the double slit: a Stern-Gerlach device, that measures the spin of a single quantum particle. For concreteness, let's say it's an electron. We orient the device in a certain direction, which we'll call the ##z## direction, and we send the electron through the device. The device has two output "slots", which we'll call "up" and "down", and the electron comes out through one or the other of these slots, corresponding to whether its spin in the ##z## direction is up or down. Those are the only two possible results.

Mathematically, we can write the state of the electron as a vector ##\vert \psi \rangle## in a Hilbert space. (I'll use the state vector formalism rather than the wave function formalism since it's easier to understand.) For the case of a single electron when all we're interested in is its spin, the Hilbert space is the simplest possible one that is not trivial. The two states that the electron can be in when it comes out of the Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction are two particular state vectors in this Hilbert space, which we can call ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle##. Note that these two states are orthogonal and linearly independent, so they can be thought of as basis states for the Hilbert space we are using--any state vector in that Hilbert space can be written as a linear combination of these two states.

But suppose that the electron enters the Stern-Gerlach device in some state ##\vert \psi \rangle## that is not ##\vert +z \rangle## or ##\vert -z \rangle##. What happens then? To figure that out, we use the fact I referred to above, that any state ##\vert \psi \rangle## can be written as a linear combination of ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle##, i.e., ##\vert \psi \rangle = a \vert +z \rangle + b \vert -z \rangle##, where ##a## and ##b## can be any two complex numbers that satisfy the condition ##|a|^2 + |b|^2 = 1##. (This condition ensures that the probabilities of all possible measurement results add up to 1.) The two terms in this linear combination, ##a \vert +z \rangle## and ##b \vert -z \rangle##, are what the MWI refers to as "worlds" or "branches". Note that there is one world/branch for each possible measurement result.
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #6
PeterDonis said:
I'm not sure this topic can be productively discussed at the "B" level, but I'll try.
That is not what I said before, but it's not worth trying to disentangle that here. For this discussion I suggest that you forget whatever you think you know about eigenstates. I won't use that term at all in what follows.
Sort of. See below.
If I give you an answer to this, it won't be at the "B" level. To even understand the math at all, you need more background than that. But here is the best answer I can give.

Let's take an even simpler experiment than the double slit: a Stern-Gerlach device, that measures the spin of a single quantum particle. For concreteness, let's say it's an electron. We orient the device in a certain direction, which we'll call the ##z## direction, and we send the electron through the device. The device has two output "slots", which we'll call "up" and "down", and the electron comes out through one or the other of these slots, corresponding to whether its spin in the ##z## direction is up or down. Those are the only two possible results.

Mathematically, we can write the state of the electron as a vector ##\vert \psi \rangle## in a Hilbert space. (I'll use the state vector formalism rather than the wave function formalism since it's easier to understand.) For the case of a single electron when all we're interested in is its spin, the Hilbert space is the simplest possible one that is not trivial. The two states that the electron can be in when it comes out of the Stern-Gerlach device oriented in the ##z## direction are two particular state vectors in this Hilbert space, which we can call ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle##. Note that these two states are orthogonal and linearly independent, so they can be thought of as basis states for the Hilbert space we are using--any state vector in that Hilbert space can be written as a linear combination of these two states.

But suppose that the electron enters the Stern-Gerlach device in some state ##\vert \psi \rangle## that is not ##\vert +z \rangle## or ##\vert -z \rangle##. What happens then? To figure that out, we use the fact I referred to above, that any state ##\vert \psi \rangle## can be written as a linear combination of ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle##, i.e., ##\vert \psi \rangle = a \vert +z \rangle + b \vert -z \rangle##, where ##a## and ##b## can be any two complex numbers that satisfy the condition ##|a|^2 + |b|^2 = 1##. (This condition ensures that the probabilities of all possible measurement results add up to 1.) The two terms in this linear combination, ##a \vert +z \rangle## and ##b \vert -z \rangle##, are what the MWI refers to as "worlds" or "branches". Note that there is one world/branch for each possible measurement result.

Ok that's clear. Thanks. For the double slit experiment.. there are multiple possible measurement results in terms of the hits in the detectors. So the worlds or branches are each detector hit or are there only 2 worlds or branches in the double slits in terms of the left or right slit? But then replacing the word world/branch with "possible measurement result", it doesn't seem to make sense that the double slit experiment has only 2 possible measurement result (left and right slit).

For your example of the Stern-Gerlach experiment above. It's great time to introduce the Eigenstate. So for the observable spin, it is in up and down spin Eigenstate? This is to distinguish how is Eigenstate math related to "each possible measurement result". The term ##a \vert +z \rangle## and ##b \vert -z \rangle## can never be called Eigenstate?
 
  • #7
bluecap said:
So for the observable spin, it is in up and down spin Eigenstate? This is to distinguish how is Eigenstate math related to "each possible measurement result". The term a|+z⟩a|+z⟩a \vert +z \rangle and b|−z⟩b|−z⟩b \vert -z \rangle can never be called Eigenstate?

For this particular measurement |+z> and |-z> would be the eigenstates, which can also be called eigenspinors. See https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Eigenspinor.
 
  • #8
secur said:
For this particular measurement |+z> and |-z> would be the eigenstates, which can also be called eigenspinors. See https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Eigenspinor.

What cases or measurement results when branches (worlds) are not Eigenstates? And what cases or measurement results branches (worlds) are Eigenstates?
 
  • #9
@bluecap please do not quote an entire post when you respond. Only quote the particular things you are responding to.
 
  • #10
bluecap said:
For the double slit experiment.. there are multiple possible measurement results in terms of the hits in the detectors. So the worlds or branches are each detector hit

Yes, there is one world or branch for each possible measurement result.

bluecap said:
it doesn't seem to make sense that the double slit experiment has only 2 possible measurement result (left and right slit).

That's because the double slit experiment does not have those two measurement results; in that experiment you don't measure which slit the particle goes through, you only measure where it hits on the detector. So the possible measurement results are all the possible places it could hit on the detector.

If you are talking about a variant of the double slit experiment where we do measure which slit the particle goes through, then the measurement result is more complicated, because for each possible place the particle could hit on the detector--call such a place point P--you have two possible measurement results, not one. Instead of just "particle hit detector at point P", you have "particle went through slit #1 and hit detector at point P", and "particle went through slit #2 and hit detector at point P". And you have such a pair of results for each possible point P, so there are twice as many possible measurement results as for the ordinary double slit (where you don't measure which slit the particle went through). And, of course, in this variant the pattern of hits on the detector that you get when you record the results for a large number of particles is different from the ordinary version, because the latter shows an interference pattern and the former does not.
 
  • #11
bluecap said:
What cases or measurement results when branches (worlds) are not Eigenstates? And what cases or measurement results branches (worlds) are Eigenstates?

I'm still not understanding why you think this is such an important question. But I'll try to answer it.

Go back to the case of a spin measurement in the ##z## direction, and remember we are talking about the MWI. As secur says, the eigenstates of this observable are ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle##. A general state ##\vert \psi \rangle## is not an eigenstate of this observable. And under the MWI, there is no collapse, so the system starts in the state ##\vert \psi \rangle## and stays in the state ##\vert \psi \rangle##. What changes is the state of the detector, so let's add that to the model.

In the Stern-Gerlach device, the "detector" is actually just the direction of the particle's motion when it comes out--i.e., which slot it comes out of. So let's assume that the particle goes in moving to the right, and comes out moving either up (for ##\vert +z \rangle##) or down (for ##\vert -z \rangle##). That means the particle's complete state going in is not just ##\vert \psi \rangle##, but ##\vert R, \psi \rangle##, because it has spin state ##\psi## and is moving to the right. Then the effect of the device can be written as follows:

$$
\vert R, \psi \rangle = \vert R, a \left( +z \right) + b \left( -z \right) \rangle
$$

turns into

$$
a \vert U, +z \rangle + b \vert D, -z \rangle
$$

where ##U## and ##D## denote the particle moving up or down. In other words, what the Stern-Gerlach device does is to entangle the momentum of the particle with its spin.

Now, the fact that ##\vert +z \rangle## and ##\vert -z \rangle## are eigenstates of spin in the ##z## direction isn't really relevant any more, because the particle's state is not just its spin. If we want to talk about eigenstates, we have to ask whether ##\vert U, +z \rangle## and ##\vert D, -z \rangle## are eigenstates of any measurement operator, and if so, which one? It turns out that, in this particular case, they are: ##\vert U \rangle## and ##\vert D \rangle## are eigenstates of ##z## momentum, and the operators for ##z## momentum and ##z## spin commute, so they can be jointly measured (basically, after each particle comes out of the Stern-Gerlach device, we detect which slot it came out of, and we can do that without changing its spin). But that is not always true.

For example, let's try to model the double slit experiment (the original version, where we don't detect which slit the particle goes through) along the same lines. The particle comes out of the source in some state ##\vert \psi \rangle##, which we don't need to write down explicitly, we just stipulate that the source emits every particle in this same state. Mathematically, to predict the probability of the particle hitting at a particular spot on the detector, we compute an amplitude for it coming through slit 1 and an amplitude for it coming through slit 2, and add the amplitudes, then take the squared norm of the resulting complex number. So, heuristically, if we pick a point P on the detector, we compute a state for the particle at P that looks like this:

$$
\vert \Psi \left( P \right) \rangle = \left( H_{1P} H_{S1} + H_{2P} H_{S2} \right) \vert \psi \rangle
$$

where the ##H## operators are the Hamiltonians describing the time evolution from the source to slits 1 and 2, and from slits 1 and 2 to the point P on the detector. The squared norm of ##\vert \Psi \left( P \right) \rangle## then gives the probability of the particle hitting at point P.

If we really want to write down the full state of the particle, including all possible points P on the detector, then that would look something like this:

$$
\vert \Psi \rangle = \Sigma_P \vert \Psi \left( P \right) \rangle = \left[ \Sigma_P \left( H_{1P} H_{S1} + H_{2P} H_{S2} \right) \right] \vert \psi \rangle
$$

i.e., a linear combination of the states for all possible points P. (I have left out normalization here, i.e., the exact computation of the coefficients of each ##\vert \Psi \left( P \right) \rangle## in the above, which is why I say this is only heuristic.)

If we now compare this to the Stern-Gerlach measurement discussed above, the key difference is that in this case, there is no obvious measurement operator that ##\vert \Psi \rangle##, the states ##\vert \Psi \left( P \right) \rangle##, or any of their components, are eigenstates of. Of course once a particle is detected at a particular point P, we can say it is in a position eigenstate corresponding to point P; but the state we wrote down above is not such a state, or a linear combination of such states. In other words, knowing which states are and are not eigenstates doesn't really tell us what we want to know, namely, what are the probabilities of the different possible measurement results?
 
  • Like
Likes bluecap
  • #12
PeterDonis said:
Yes, there is one world or branch for each possible measurement result.
That's because the double slit experiment does not have those two measurement results; in that experiment you don't measure which slit the particle goes through, you only measure where it hits on the detector. So the possible measurement results are all the possible places it could hit on the detector.

If you are talking about a variant of the double slit experiment where we do measure which slit the particle goes through, then the measurement result is more complicated, because for each possible place the particle could hit on the detector--call such a place point P--you have two possible measurement results, not one. Instead of just "particle hit detector at point P", you have "particle went through slit #1 and hit detector at point P", and "particle went through slit #2 and hit detector at point P". And you have such a pair of results for each possible point P, so there are twice as many possible measurement results as for the ordinary double slit (where you don't measure which slit the particle went through). And, of course, in this variant the pattern of hits on the detector that you get when you record the results for a large number of particles is different from the ordinary version, because the latter shows an interference pattern and the former does not.

Let's say a radioactive material was tracked by a scanner at exactly 1 AM and 2 1/10000+ seconds owned by Comey. If it decays and the scanner clicks. Then he wakes up and unable to sleep and not in mood the next day and he sent the letter to congress reminding Congress of email stuff. If it doesn't decay and the scanner doesn't click. Then he continues to sleep and in good mood and didn't send the letter. In the former case, let's say Trump wins because of that. In the latter case, let's say Clinton wins because of that. We have two branches. Are they still modellable by subspace? But subspace is still in superposition being part of Hilbert space. So in principle can't one cut off the Trump branch you are sitting and get back to the global superposition where you can see the other branch where Clinton won. Earlier you wrote about Unitary Evolution. What is unitary evolution violated when you jump off from the Trump Branch? What is the equivalent in wave function evolution when subspace is not the same as collapse and not in Eigenstates at all.

(edit I send this a minute after you sent the last message)
 
  • #13
bluecap said:
We have two branches. Are they still modellable by subspace? But subspace is still in superposition being part of Hilbert space. So in principle can't one cut off the Trump branch you are sitting and get back to the global superposition where you can see the other branch where Clinton won. Earlier you wrote about Unitary Evolution. What is unitary evolution violated when you jump off from the Trump Branch? What is the equivalent in wave function evolution when subspace is not the same as collapse and not in Eigenstates at all.

This is too involved for a B level thread, and contains too many misconceptions for me to try to disentangle them. You will need to spend some time actually working through the math of QM, and then come back and start an "I" level thread.

The quick B-level answer to "why is unitary evolution violated" is that unitary evolution conserves information, and "cutting off" any branch destroys information, so such an operation manifestly can't be unitary. Similarly, trying to "rejoin" branches while still preserving the unique information in each branch (as opposed to a "quantum eraser" experiment that erases the information that distinguished the branches) creates information, so it manifestly can't be unitary. If you want more than that, then you'll have to do as I just said and get to the point where you can have an "I" level discussion.
 
  • #14
PeterDonis said:
This is too involved for a B level thread, and contains too many misconceptions for me to try to disentangle them. You will need to spend some time actually working through the math of QM, and then come back and start an "I" level thread.

The quick B-level answer to "why is unitary evolution violated" is that unitary evolution conserves information, and "cutting off" any branch destroys information, so such an operation manifestly can't be unitary. Similarly, trying to "rejoin" branches while still preserving the unique information in each branch (as opposed to a "quantum eraser" experiment that erases the information that distinguished the branches) creates information, so it manifestly can't be unitary. If you want more than that, then you'll have to do as I just said and get to the point where you can have an "I" level discussion.

I have thought of this by googling "unitary evolution conserves information". But here is a counter argument. Supposed you are watching the double slit experiment and even though the detector hit occurs in certain spots.. you could say communicate to one spot/hit (or branch) and inform it that the next hits were so and so location.. that particular spot/hit (or branch) would know the location of others. How do you describe this effect using the language of "unitary evolution". How could it still conserve information when you inform the hits or branches of the others location (that it couldn't know on its own)?
 
  • #15
bluecap said:
I have thought of this by googling "unitary evolution conserves information". But here is a counter argument. Supposed you are watching the double slit experiment and even though the detector hit occurs in certain spots.. you could say communicate to one spot/hit (or branch) and inform it that the next hits were so and so location.. that particular spot/hit (or branch) would know the location of others. How do you describe this effect using the language of "unitary evolution". How could it still conserve information when you inform the hits or branches of the others location (that it couldn't know on its own)?

PeterDonis said:
... contains too many misconceptions for me to try to disentangle them. You will need to spend some time actually working through the math of QM, and then come back and start an "I" level thread.
 
  • #16

That's why we are called laymen because we are not expert in math. I've been reflecting on the words "Unitary Evolution" for quite some hours. It is defined as:

"In quantum physics, unitarity is a restriction on the allowed evolution of quantum systems that ensures the sum of probabilities of all possible outcomes of any event is always 1. [Wiki]"

As the wave function evolves.. what is the context probabilities of all possible outcomes of any event is always 1. Any simple math for this? And what's it connection to the born rule that would probabilities to be less or more than one? But if you have another wave piggybacking on the wave function and can track where the particle collapses.. and it can communicate back to the wave function.. won't this mean unitary evolution is conserved so branch can communicate back to the state vector?
 
  • #17
bluecap said:
you could say communicate to one spot/hit (or branch) and inform it that the next hits were so and so location..

No, you can't. The fact that this sounds meaningful in ordinary language does not mean it actually is meaningful when you do the math. But the reason why goes beyond a "B" level thread.

bluecap said:
How do you describe this effect using the language of "unitary evolution".

I don't have to because it violates unitary evolution and hence is inconsistent with QM. The reason why goes beyond a "B" level thread.

bluecap said:
I've been reflecting on the words "Unitary Evolution" for quite some hours.

You don't need to "reflect on the words", and you shouldn't try to understand this topic by reading Wikipedia. You need to actually look at a QM textbook and work through the math. Ballentine is a good one to start with.

bluecap said:
if you have another wave piggybacking on the wave function and can track where the particle collapses..

This is not consistent with QM; there is no such "other wave" in QM. Go look at the math.
 
  • #18
This topic cannot be productively discussed further at the "B" level. Thread closed.
 

1. Can Everett Branches Break Quantum Laws?

According to the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics proposed by Hugh Everett III, the branching of multiple parallel universes does not violate any laws of quantum physics. It is simply a different way of understanding the behavior of particles and their wave functions.

2. How does the Many-Worlds Interpretation explain the branching of Everett branches?

The Many-Worlds Interpretation suggests that every possible outcome of a quantum event exists in a separate parallel universe. The branching of Everett branches occurs when the wave function of a particle collapses and creates multiple parallel universes, each with a different outcome.

3. Are there any experiments that support the Many-Worlds Interpretation?

While there is no direct experimental evidence for the Many-Worlds Interpretation, it is a valid interpretation of quantum mechanics that does not contradict any experimental observations. However, there are ongoing experiments, such as quantum teleportation, that could potentially provide evidence for the existence of parallel universes.

4. Can the Many-Worlds Interpretation be proven or disproven?

As with any interpretation of quantum mechanics, the Many-Worlds Interpretation cannot be proven or disproven. It is a theoretical framework that provides a different perspective on the behavior of particles and their wave functions. However, it is a valid interpretation that does not contradict any experimental evidence.

5. Is the Many-Worlds Interpretation widely accepted by the scientific community?

The Many-Worlds Interpretation is one of several interpretations of quantum mechanics and is still a topic of debate among scientists. While it has gained some support and recognition, it is not yet widely accepted by the entire scientific community. However, it remains a valid and intriguing perspective on the nature of reality.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
10
Views
2K
Replies
17
Views
4K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
89
Views
6K
  • STEM Academic Advising
Replies
3
Views
452
  • Quantum Physics
9
Replies
286
Views
20K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
27
Views
7K
Back
Top