Gaps In The System of Rational Numbers

In summary, the conversation discusses the discovery and significance of irrational numbers, specifically in regards to the equation ##p^2 = 2##. The question is raised about why we want this equation to have solutions and whether the existence of irrational numbers is simply a pragmatic choice. The conversation also touches on the concept of gaps in the rational and real number systems, and the role of extensions such as complex and hyperreal numbers.
  • #1
Bashyboy
1,421
5
I have a question which comes from Rudin's Principles of Mathematical Analysis; specifically, from the introduction.

In example 1.1, the author clearly shows that no rational numbers satisfy the equation ##p^2 = 2##.
So, I am trying to imagine myself in a scenario in which I am in a time before the discovery of irrational numbers, which provide us with solutions to equations as ##p^2 = 2##. Furthermore, I am one of these pre-irrational-number mathematician who does a proof to demonstrate that ##p^2= 2## has no rational solutions.

Here is my question: What would make me think that there existed any solutions; and why would we think
that one of the irrational numbers—namely, ##\sqrt{2}##—would be one such solution to ##p^2=2##? In other words, does ##p^2 = 2## "get" solutions because we want it to have solutions?

Also, below this example the author attempts to demonstrate that the rational number system has gaps. But would this only be true if we wanted ##p^2 = 2## to have solutions, right? Two questions: (1) why does it matter if the rational numbers are incomplete, and why would we fill in the gaps with numbers and then refer to them as irrational numbers (Note: I am not questioning the name given to these sorts of numbers, but the numbers themselves); (2) by augmenting our number system by including these numbers which fill the gaps, we form the real number system, how do we know that ##\mathbb{R}## does not have any gaps?

In short, why should we want ##p^2 = 2## to have solutions?
 
Last edited:
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Here is my question: What would make me think that there existed any solutions

Maybe because we can draw a triangle and, by Pythagoras's theorem, deduce that one side must have that length?

In other words, does p2=2 "get" solutions because we want it to have solutions?

I suppose it's a matter of taste. We could debate whether irrational numbers exist "out there" in the real world, but inventing (or discovering?) irrational numbers allows us to do more trigonometry etc. which might turn out to be useful.
 
  • #3
So, we constrain them to exist for pragmatic purposes? I suppose that that is reasonable!
 
  • #5
One answer is appealing to geometry, as madness mentioned. In a square with side length 1, the length of diagonal cannot be expressed as a rational number. But the diagonal is clearly a line segment, so it should have a length.

We can also appeal to algebra. Mathematicians don't like unsolvable equations. If an equation, say ##x^2=2##, has no solution within a certain number system, we invent an extension of the number system such that that the equation has a solution in the extended system. One can view negative numbers, fractions, and imaginary (and complex) numbers in this way.

As for the question about gaps in the real number system, there are no such gaps. The real number system is defined in such way that no such gaps can occur. There are some alternative definitions of the real numbers, but they give rise to isomorphic structures, and they all satisfy the following axiom, given by Dedekind:

If A and B are nonempty disjoint sets of real numbers, such that A ∪ B = ℝ, and such that for all x ∈ A and y ∈ B, it must hold that x < y, then there is a an r ∈ R which is either the greatest number in A or the smallest number in B.

This is not true with ℚ instead of ℝ, since ℚ has gaps, for example the gap produced by the irrational number ##\sqrt 2##.

Rudin mentions this, if I remember correctly.
 
  • #6
Erland said:
As for the question about gaps in the real number system, there are no such gaps.

That seems strange. So, it is not possible to come across another "equation" and find that the real numbers are insufficient, as we did with ##p^2 = 2## and the rational numbers? Didn't the pre-irrational-number people think that ##\mathbb{Q}## was complete?
 
  • #7
Bashyboy said:
That seems strange. So, it is not possible to come across another "equation" and find that the real numbers are insufficient, as we did with ##p^2 = 2## and the rational numbers?
The real numbers are not sufficient for this equation: x2 + 1 = 0. For this one you need the complex numbers.
Bashyboy said:
Didn't the pre-irrational-number people think that ##\mathbb{Q}## was complete?
 
  • #8
Oh, yes, complex numbers. Well, I suppose I could ask the very same question with complex numbers.
 
  • #9
Oh, yes, complex numbers. Well, I suppose I could ask the very same question with complex numbers.

Note that the extension to complex numbers wasn't exactly filling a "gap" like irrational numbers do, it was extending them in a different way. I could always add an extra element to the real number line if I like, but it wouldn't fill a "gap". A gap implies something about the ordering of numbers, i.e. if there is a gap between a and b then there should be some other (non-real) number that has a value in between any two real numbers.

At a push, you might consider the hyperreal numbers (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hyperreal_number) as filling a gap (at infinity), but to me it's more like sticking another one on the end.

There are also lots of extensions of complex numbers (http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hypercomplex_number), but as far as I know they don't fill gaps in the usual complex numbers.
 
  • #10
Starting with a compass and a straight edge, one can construct many lengths among them all of the rational numbers. One can also construct the diagonal of a square. It is natural if you believe that all numbers are rational to ask which rational number the length of this diagonal is. Using an elementary proof, the ancient Greeks discovered that it is not a rational.

If not all numbers are rational, one might ask whether all numbers are constructible with a ruler and straight edge. In the 18'th century Gauss classified all possible constructible numbers and was able to show elementary examples such as the length of a side of a regular septagon that are not constructible. This meant that not only are all numbers not rational but not all of them are constructible either.

If one thinks of ruler and compass constructions as constructing points in the plane, then one may think of these points as complex numbers. As such they all lie in iterated quadratic extensions of the rationals since ruler and compass constructions can only create square roots of known lengths.
This of course is nowhere near all of the real or complex numbers and if one thinks about it the number of constructible numbers must be countably infinite since they are constructed iteratively starting with two points.

One might try to generalize construction to taking roots of arbitrary polynomials (not just quadratic) starting with rational coefficients and iteratively including coefficients from the extension fields. Even though many new numbers arise, there are still only countably infinitely many of them. Numbers like pi are not obtained in this way. I do not know when it was first discovered that pi is transcendental but I imagine it would have stunned mathematicians much the way the discovery of the irrationality of the square root of 2 stunned the Pythagoreans. After all one can construct pi simply with only a compass.
 
Last edited:
  • #11
Okay, so I have another question.

Below this example the author endeavors to show that there are gaps in the rational number system, which appears that it can only be done if you accept that ##p^2 = 2## must have some solution.

To do this, the author considers all of the rational number solutions ##p^2 < 2##, and let ##A## contain all of these solutions; he also considers solutions to ##p^2 > 2##, and let's ##B## contain these solutions. Evidently, by showing that ##A## does not have a largest element, and that ##B## does not have a smallest element, we will have shown that there is a gap.

He proceeds by supposing ##A## has a largest element, which he calls ##q##, so that ##p < q## ##\forall p \in A##. He then says that we can associate with each rational number ##p > 0## the number

##q = p - \frac{p^2 - 2}{p+2}##.

Why would you do such a thing?

##q = p - \frac{(p+2)(p-2)}{p+2} = p - (p-2) = 2##

Why would you define ##q## to be ##2##?

Another more pressing question I have is, why would showing ##A## has no greatest element, and ##B## no smallest, show that there is a gap?
 
  • #12
Bashyboy said:
That seems strange. So, it is not possible to come across another "equation" and find that the real numbers are insufficient, as we did with ##p^2 = 2## and the rational numbers? Didn't the pre-irrational-number people think that ##\mathbb{Q}## was complete?
I don't know the history but it seems like ruler and compass constructions may be thought of as a program for constructing all of space, a failed program of course.
 
Last edited:
  • #13
Bashyboy said:
Okay, so I have another question.

Below this example the author endeavors to show that there are gaps in the rational number system, which appears that it can only be done if you accept that ##p^2 = 2## must have some solution.

To do this, the author considers all of the rational number solutions ##p^2 < 2##, and let ##A## contain all of these solutions; he also considers solutions to ##p^2 > 2##, and let's ##B## contain these solutions. Evidently, by showing that ##A## does not have a largest element, and that ##B## does not have a smallest element, we will have shown that there is a gap.

He proceeds by supposing ##A## has a largest element, which he calls ##q##, so that ##p < q## ##\forall p \in A##. He then says that we can associate with each rational number ##p > 0## the number

##q = p - \frac{p^2 - 2}{p+2}##.

Why would you do such a thing?

##q = p - \frac{(p+2)(p-2)}{p+2} = p - (p-2) = 2##
Where did the equation above come from? ##\frac{p^2 - 2}{p+2} \neq \frac{(p+2)(p-2)}{p+2}##
Bashyboy said:
Why would you define ##q## to be ##2##?

Another more pressing question I have is, why would showing ##A## has no greatest element, and ##B## no smallest, show that there is a gap?
 
  • #14
Bashyboy said:
why would showing ##A## has no greatest element, and ##B## no smallest, show that there is a gap?
If you mark the sets A and B on the number line, and if A has no greatest element and B no smallest, isn't it then geometrically obvious that there is a "hole" between the two sets, corresponding to a point on the number line?

As for complex numbers, the field ℂ is algebraically complete: Every algebraic equation ##a_n z^n + a_{n-1} z^{n-1} + \dots + a_1 z + a_0=0##, with complex coefficients and ##a_n≠0##, has a complex root. This is the content of the Fundamental Theorem of Algebra.
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Fundamental_theorem_of_algebra
 
Last edited:
  • #15
Oh, whoops...Thank you for showing me my error Mark44. However, I am still confused as to why we would define ##q## as ##p - \frac{p^2 -2}{p+2}##. Certainly it it plausible to relate ##q## and ##p##, because we already have some relationship between them, that ##p < q##. But if we define ##q## in such a manner, as ##p## minus some quantity involving ##p##, won't this make ##q## less than ##p##?
 
  • #16
Bashyboy said:
Oh, whoops...Thank you for showing me my error Mark44. However, I am still confused as to why we would define ##q## as ##p - \frac{p^2 -2}{p+2}##. Certainly it it plausible to relate ##q## and ##p##, because we already have some relationship between them, that ##p < q##. But if we define ##q## in such a manner, as ##p## minus some quantity involving ##p##, won't this make ##q## less than ##p##?

Is it ##p## or ##q## which is the supposed largest element in ##A##?

Anyway, ##p - \frac{p^2 -2}{p+2}=p + \frac{2-p^2}{p+2}>p##, since ##p^2<2##.
 
  • #17
Bashyboy said:
Okay, so I have another question.

Below this example the author endeavors to show that there are gaps in the rational number system, which appears that it can only be done if you accept that ##p^2 = 2## must have some solution.

To do this, the author considers all of the rational number solutions ##p^2 < 2##, and let ##A## contain all of these solutions; he also considers solutions to ##p^2 > 2##, and let's ##B## contain these solutions. Evidently, by showing that ##A## does not have a largest element, and that ##B## does not have a smallest element, we will have shown that there is a gap.

He proceeds by supposing ##A## has a largest element, which he calls ##q##, so that ##p < q## ##\forall p \in A##. He then says that we can associate with each rational number ##p > 0## the number

## q = p - \frac{p^2 - 2}{p+2}##.

Why would you do such a thing?

##q = p - \frac{(p+2)(p-2)}{p+2} = p - (p-2) = 2##

Why would you define ##q## to be ##2##?

Another more pressing question I have is, why would showing ##A## has no greatest element, and ##B## no smallest, show that there is a gap?

- The idea of the proof is to show that there is no largest rational number less than the square root of 2. So given such a rational, one must find another that is bigger but still less than the square root of 2. Check that if ##p^2 < 2## then

## (p - \frac{p^2-2}{p+2} )^2 < 2##

as well.

- "Gap" just mans that there are numbers that are not rational. If you think of the number line then intuitively there must be holes and these holes separate the rationals into disjoint sets.

As it turns out, there is no possible procedure for constructing all of the real numbers. One must define them in another way. All equivalence classes of Cauchy sequences of rationals is one way. Another is all Dedekind cuts. But there is no way to construct all of these cuts or equivalence classes. This is because the number of real numbers is a larger infinity than the infinity of the integers.
 
Last edited:
  • #18
As others have said, the geometric line preceded the real numbers. It was the desire to represent points on the line by numbers that led to the discovery of irrational numbers, and real numbers in general. This becomes clear if you start your mathematical education at the beginning, namely with Euclid. The need to define the ratio of two lengths, and to prove the principle of similarity for all triangles with the same angles, leads to the approximation of arbitrary lengths by rational lengths, in Book V or VI I believe in Euclid. See especially Book VI, Propositions 1 and 2.
 
  • #19
There are three kinds of gaps that I'm aware of. One of them is the gaps created by ruler and compass constructions, needed for the geometry of the ancient Greeks. You fill those in by throwing in square roots (including nested square roots). Another gap kind of gap is holes where there should be a solution to some algebraic equation. But what's most relevant for the real numbers is the gaps created by sequences that want to converge. Any sequence whose terms get arbitrarily close together ought to be converging to something (Cauchy sequences). What the real numbers really do is fill in those holes, so that any Cauchy sequence does converge to something. This is needed to get "obvious" facts like the intermediate value theorem to work. The intermediate value theorem is equivalent to completeness.

The precursor to the real numbers was Eudoxus' theory of proportions, which is the subject of Book 5 of Euclid's Elements. Dedekind's Dedekind cuts construction of the real numbers was inspired by this ancient Greek theory. It was only later in the 19th century that the need for filling all these gaps to get calculus to work was really appreciated.

The real numbers "exist", not in the real world, but mathematically, because we can construct them from the ground up, starting with things like the empty set and the ability to stick whatever sets we have together into another set, and the existence of an infinite set, and all that stuff. So, we don't just postulate the existence of the real numbers. We can construct them from simpler things, which we do have to postulate the existence of, but it's somewhat more satisfying to postulate something simple like some basic things about sets than to start with the real numbers.
 
  • #20
Bashyboy said:
So, we constrain them to exist for pragmatic purposes? I suppose that that is reasonable!
Not really. The way irrational numbers can be defined in modern math as limits of real numbers, there is no logic that allows anyone to deny they exist. It wouldn't be hard to define a series of rational numbers that come arbitrarily close to the solution of p2=2. The limit of that sequence would define the solution. Then you can prove that the solution is irrational.

In the time of Pythagoras, they didn't believe in irrational numbers, but that was a different. Zero and negative numbers had not been invented and numbers were thought of as having mystical, religious properties. Geometry was all they really believed in. So the existence of an isosceles right triangle with a hypotenuse of sqrt(2) was a given. Pythagoras religiously believed that there was a rational number for that length. His religious beliefs did not allow irrational numbers. Some believe that his followers killed the man who proved that the square root of 2 was irrational. Here is an amusing (I think) account of it:
 
Last edited:
  • #21
FactChecker said:
The way irrational numbers can be defined in modern math as limits of real numbers

I find this statement slightly perplexing. Aren't irrational numbers considered real?
 
  • #24
Bashyboy said:
I have a question which comes from Rudin's Principles of Mathematical Analysis; specifically, from the introduction.

In example 1.1, the author clearly shows that no rational numbers satisfy the equation ##p^2 = 2##.
So, I am trying to imagine myself in a scenario in which I am in a time before the discovery of irrational numbers, which provide us with solutions to equations as ##p^2 = 2##. Furthermore, I am one of these pre-irrational-number mathematician who does a proof to demonstrate that ##p^2= 2## has no rational solutions.

Here is my question: What would make me think that there existed any solutions; and why would we think
that one of the irrational numbers—namely, ##\sqrt{2}##—would be one such solution to ##p^2=2##? In other words, does ##p^2 = 2## "get" solutions because we want it to have solutions?

Also, below this example the author attempts to demonstrate that the rational number system has gaps. But would this only be true if we wanted ##p^2 = 2## to have solutions, right? Two questions: (1) why does it matter if the rational numbers are incomplete, and why would we fill in the gaps with numbers and then refer to them as irrational numbers (Note: I am not questioning the name given to these sorts of numbers, but the numbers themselves); (2) by augmenting our number system by including these numbers which fill the gaps, we form the real number system, how do we know that ##\mathbb{R}## does not have any gaps?

In short, why should we want ##p^2 = 2## to have solutions?
Are you saying you don't recognize egzistance of irrational numbers?
Ok, I respect that opinion, but I have mine too.
 
  • #25
Mark44 said:
Are you quoting something that someone said in this thread?

Yes, he was quoting post #20.

zoki85 said:
Are you saying you don't recognize egzistance of irrational numbers?

No, I was not doubting their existence. I was just curious as to why the equation ##p^2 = 2## would warrant creating/discovering new numbers.

zoki85 said:
Ok, I respect that opinion, but I have mine too.

I am curious to know what your opinion is. Please, do tell.
 
  • #26
Bashyboy said:
I am curious to know what your opinion is. Please, do tell.
For me they exist. They exist in my world of ideas. But who am I to make you believe my world of ideas is better than yours?
 
  • #27
Bashyboy said:
I find this statement slightly perplexing. Aren't irrational numbers considered real?
Sorry. I should have said irrationals can be defined as limits of rational numbers. (Of course, there are also series of rational numbers that converge on rational numbers too, and that does not make them irrational.)
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Bashyboy
  • #28
  • #29
there is no logic that allows anyone to deny they exist
madness said:
This is a strange statement. Exist in what sense? There is plenty of logic that allows people to deny that they exist physically...
@madness, when you quote someone, you should identify who said it (FactChecker in this case). Also, the quoted text above lacks some important context, such is who are what "they" refers to. I interpreted the statement above as logic that allows someone to deny their own existence. In FactChecker's full statement, it was clear that the antecedent of "they" was real numbers.
 
  • Like
Likes madness
  • #30
If you choose to only consider rational numbers, then obviously ##p^2=2## has no solution in ℚ. Similarly, ##p^2=-1## has no solution in ℝ, the real numbers. Perhaps you are wondering about the concept of field extensions. http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Field_extension It was troubling to have equations with no solution, so mathematicians constructed a larger field which allowed for solutions. One motivator to make us think there are such solutions to ##p^2=2## is when we draw a square of unit side length, and try to find the length of the diagonal.
 
Last edited:

1. What are gaps in the system of rational numbers?

Gaps in the system of rational numbers refer to numbers that cannot be expressed as a fraction of two integers. These numbers are often referred to as irrational numbers and include numbers such as pi and the square root of 2.

2. Why do gaps exist in the system of rational numbers?

Gaps exist in the system of rational numbers because there are infinitely many real numbers that cannot be expressed as a fraction of two integers. This means that there will always be numbers that cannot be represented in the rational number system.

3. How do gaps in the system of rational numbers affect mathematical operations?

Gaps in the system of rational numbers can complicate mathematical operations, especially when dealing with infinite decimals. For example, adding or subtracting irrational numbers can result in an infinite decimal that cannot be accurately represented.

4. Can gaps in the system of rational numbers be filled?

No, gaps in the system of rational numbers cannot be filled. This is because there will always be infinitely many real numbers that cannot be expressed as a fraction of two integers, making it impossible to fully represent the entire set of real numbers.

5. How do gaps in the system of rational numbers impact the real world?

Gaps in the system of rational numbers have a significant impact on the real world, especially in fields such as science and engineering. Many physical quantities, such as the circumference of a circle, cannot be expressed as a rational number and require the use of irrational numbers to be accurately measured and calculated.

Similar threads

Replies
4
Views
630
Replies
13
Views
1K
Replies
6
Views
1K
  • General Math
Replies
11
Views
1K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • General Math
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
3
Views
281
Replies
2
Views
262
Back
Top