Need (or not) for invoking axiom of choice in a certain case

In summary, the conversation discusses the question of whether the proof of a theorem about differentiable manifolds requires the axiom of choice. It is determined that while the axiom of choice may be needed in some cases, it is not necessary for this particular proof. The concept of points in geometry and the limitations of the axiom of choice are also discussed.
  • #1
RockyMarciano
588
43
I was wondering about the following scenario, we have a certain differentiable manifold with the standard topology not induced by any previous metric structure on the manifold. There is no natural way to identify a vector with its dual(no canonical isomorphism between them),

If we had to define the length of a curve and we were not allowed to use an induced metric from a prespecified metric structure, would it be necessary to make a choice of inner product for each of the uncountable points in the curve and therefore would we have to appeal to the axiom of choice?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
I meant "induced topology" instead of "induced metric" in the second paragraph. Sorry about that.
 
  • #3
A differentiable manifold is a Hausdorff space with countable basis (definition) and every differentiable manifold admits a Riemannian metric (theorem). Therefore your question can be translated to: Does the proof of this theorem require the axiom of choice? As far as I have seen on a quick glimpse this is not the case as the main tool is the countable basis. However, AC is sometimes well hidden somewhere in a result which is used by propositions which themselves are used to prove the theorem. Personally I do not think that AC is needed somewhere, as all required properties are already contained in the definition of a differentiable manifold. So neither an embedding nor the AC itself should be required at some stage of the proof. Differential geometry is about neighborhoods, not about points.
 
  • Like
Likes Carrock and RockyMarciano
  • #4
fresh_42 said:
A differentiable manifold is a Hausdorff space with countable basis (definition) and every differentiable manifold admits a Riemannian metric (theorem). Therefore your question can be translated to: Does the proof of this theorem require the axiom of choice? As far as I have seen on a quick glimpse this is not the case as the main tool is the countable basis. However, AC is sometimes well hidden somewhere in a result which is used by propositions which themselves are used to prove the theorem. Personally I do not think that AC is needed somewhere, as all required properties are already contained in the definition of a differentiable manifold. So neither an embedding nor the AC itself should be required at some stage of the proof. Differential geometry is about neighborhoods, not about points.
Thanks for replying.
I completely agree with everything you wrote. My question is trying to complicate a bit the picture by imposing some constraint that might seem to be artificial but that has some important examples in mathermatical physics. So the requirement is that even though our differential manifold admits a Riemannian metric, let's say that it has a pseudoriemannian metric and therefore the topology in the manifold is not the one that the pseudo-Riemannian metric tensor would induce, but the standard topology instead. And we want to determine the length( of a timelike curve in this manifold(let's say for concreteness that it is Minkowski 4-space).

Now in the usual case in Riemannian geometry with a differentiable manifold that has a defined riemannian metric that induces the standard topology I can easily see how integrating infinitesimal lengths at each point to obtain a length doesn't require the AC as the metric tensor is naturally built up on the differentiable and topologic structuures, but when the metric tensor doesn't agree with the manifold topology I don't know if this could require choice at each poit of the curve even if just to decide the signature convention for timelike vectors at each point given that it being purely conventional there is no canonical choice but still at each tangent space it is needed in order to integrate them to a curve length(or proper time).
 
  • #5
The difficulty with the axiom of choice is, that you cannot control the way individual points are picked. Thus you don't have any control of their behavior. Esp. you can neither make any assumptions on their neighborhood nor on any equations like linearity, or inequalities like the triangle inequality, which doesn't make it helpful in the context of geometries. Things might change in the infinite dimensional case, where you need it to guarantee the existence of a basis of the tangent space. However, a metric on a finite dimensional manifold is an equation (bilinear form) about tangent vectors, or connections to compare different ones. All of which are given by an equation, i.e. a closed set. These are algebraic, resp. topological properties and the axiom of choice doesn't really apply on them. Or put it another way: the axiom of choice is about well-orderings. So either this well-order has something to do with the metric, in which case you don't need it anymore, or it has not, in which case it isn't helpful.

I once listened to a talk about the proof of the Banach-Tarski paradoxon and I remember, that the closing statement was: "This shows less the absurdity of the axiom of choice than it demonstrates our difficulties with what a point is." I think there is much truth to it. And translated to the case you mentioned, it means, that manifolds are at least continuous objects, and all their properties are of topological nature where AC has no role in it, i.e. open sets, not points.
 
  • Like
Likes RockyMarciano
  • #6
fresh_42 said:
The difficulty with the axiom of choice is, that you cannot control the way individual points are picked. Thus you don't have any control of their behavior. Esp. you can neither make any assumptions on their neighborhood nor on any equations like linearity, or inequalities like the triangle inequality, which doesn't make it helpful in the context of geometries. Things might change in the infinite dimensional case, where you need it to guarantee the existence of a basis of the tangent space. However, a metric on a finite dimensional manifold is an equation (bilinear form) about tangent vectors, or connections to compare different ones. All of which are given by an equation, i.e. a closed set. These are algebraic, resp. topological properties and the axiom of choice doesn't really apply on them. Or put it another way: the axiom of choice is about well-orderings. So either this well-order has something to do with the metric, in which case you don't need it anymore, or it has not, in which case it isn't helpful.

I once listened to a talk about the proof of the Banach-Tarski paradoxon and I remember, that the closing statement was: "This shows less the absurdity of the axiom of choice than it demonstrates our difficulties with what a point is." I think there is much truth to it. And translated to the case you mentioned, it means, that manifolds are at least continuous objects, and all their properties are of topological nature where AC has no role in it, i.e. open sets, not points.
Thanks, I see. So I would have to go for something weaker than the full AC, right? For instance the axiom of countable dependent choice(DC).

I'm not completely sure if DC is assumed either in the differentiable manifold definition(here I tend to think that countable choice(CC), which is weaker than DC, would be enough) or in the (pseudo)Riemannian manifold definition(here I'm pretty sure non-compact metric spaces need DC).
 
  • #7
fresh_42 said:
A differentiable manifold is a Hausdorff space with countable basis (definition) and every differentiable manifold admits a Riemannian metric (theorem). Therefore your question can be translated to: Does the proof of this theorem require the axiom of choice? As far as I have seen on a quick glimpse this is not the case as the main tool is the countable basis. However, AC is sometimes well hidden somewhere in a result which is used by propositions which themselves are used to prove the theorem. Personally I do not think that AC is needed somewhere, as all required properties are already contained in the definition of a differentiable manifold. So neither an embedding nor the AC itself should be required at some stage of the proof. Differential geometry is about neighborhoods, not about points.

The proof I remember to show the existence of a globally-defined metric does not require any infinite construction. Essentially, the local diffeomorphisms allow us to pullback ( pushforward) the needed properties of ##\mathbb R^n ## onto the manifold locally. Then, using paracompactness ( 2nd Countable+ something else) we can show the existence of partitions of unity subordinate to the cover by open sets, so that we can glue the locally-defined inner-products into a single globally-defined inner-product.
 
  • #8
WWGD said:
The proof I remember to show the existence of a globally-defined metric does not require any infinite construction. Essentially, the local diffeomorphisms allow us to pullback ( pushforward) the needed properties of ##\mathbb R^n ## onto the manifold locally. Then, using paracompactness ( 2nd Countable+ something else) we can show the existence of partitions of unity subordinate to the cover by open sets, so that we can glue the locally-defined inner-products into a single globally-defined inner-product.
That's the proof I've found, too. I didn't read the details, but I thought for the partition of unity the countable basis would have been needed to avoid unpleasant sums.
 
  • #9
fresh_42 said:
That's the proof I've found, too. I didn't read the details, but I thought for the partition of unity the countable basis would have been needed to avoid unpleasant sums.
Precisely, no need to deal with convergence. Differential Geometers are somewhat-spoiled in dealing with manifolds, which are overall very well-behaved. It seems like Algebraic Geometry or Geometric Measure Theory would be nastier -- no wonder it is called "Ze-Risky" topology in Alg Geo. ;). Good point on the " points v open sets" , though.
 
  • #10
WWGD said:
The proof I remember to show the existence of a globally-defined metric does not require any infinite construction. Essentially, the local diffeomorphisms allow us to pullback ( pushforward) the needed properties of ##\mathbb R^n ## onto the manifold locally. Then, using paracompactness ( 2nd Countable+ something else) we can show the existence of partitions of unity subordinate to the cover by open sets, so that we can glue the locally-defined inner-products into a single globally-defined inner-product.
The example of determining a length in the OP doesn't just require existence, wouldn't it be needed to attain an infimum? Isn't some countable choice needed for this?

Edit:(Actually to be precise I should be referring to the distance between two points in the manifold, rather than just the length of a curve)
 
Last edited:
  • #11
RockyMarciano said:
The example of determining a length in the OP doesn't just require existence, wouldn't it be needed to attain an infimum? Isn't some countable choice needed for this?
Good point, let me think it through.
 
  • #12
I love the risky topology. Maybe because the pun doesn't work here but more likely because the Zariski topology offers such a pretty short imagination: equations ergo closed, inequality ergo open. And everything is dense!##^*)##

There is another pun possible: May I introduce the honorable Prof. Dr.
latest?cb=20111024180557.png
Zariski!
---------
##^*)## Not intended to be rigorous.
 
  • #13
fresh_42 said:
I love the risky topology. Maybe because the pun doesn't work here but more likely because the Zariski topology offers such a pretty short imagination: equations ergo closed, inequality ergo open. And everything is dense!##^*)##

There is another pun possible: May I introduce the honorable Prof. Dr. View attachment 211282Zariski!
---------
##^*)## Not intended to be rigorous.
But it is "anti-Haudorff", aka strongly-connected in most cases; no two points can be separated. Open sets are just way too big
 
  • #14
A quick PF search of "countable choice" got this http://dml.cz/dmlcz/118951 showing several uses of various degrees of choice. The sentence it ends with: "Let us sum things up: Topology with “choice” may be as unreal as a soap-bubble dream, but topology without “choice” is as horrible as nightmare", seems to be in contrast with the previous comments about the null role of choice in topology.

Anyway, specifically for what concerns the OP it says that: the assertion "in a (pseudo)metric space X, a point x is an accumulation point of a subset A iff there exists a sequence in A \ {x} that converges to x" is equivalent to the axiom of countable choice. This appears to me a condition for an infimum length, no?
 
  • #15
RockyMarciano said:
This appears to me a condition for an infimum length, no?
Doesn't the infimum of length simply mean, that ##\mathbb{R}## is complete? I don't see the connection. Of course we could debate the justification of complete scalar fields, but this is a different topic and again independent of AC. We don't chose the limits in existence, we require they're already there.
 
  • #16
Why do you ask?
 
  • #17
fresh_42 said:
Doesn't the infimum of length simply mean, that ##\mathbb{R}## is complete?
I don't see how defining distance in an arbitrary (pseudo)metric space with the infimum of a sequence of lengths o the curves that connect two points, which seems to require the assertion equivalent to countable choice in my previous post, could be equivalent to every cauchy sequence converges in the space, I don't think defining a distance requires completeness.

I'm not even sure if you are making any distinction between full AC and weaker forms in this thread.
 
  • #18
RockyMarciano said:
I'm not even sure if you are making any distinction between full AC and weaker forms in this thread.
No, since I don't understand all of your words, e.g. "countable choice" or here "weaker form". Never heard of them before.
RockyMarciano said:
I don't see how defining distance in an arbitrary (pseudo)metric space with the infimum of a sequence of lengths o the curves that connect two points, which seems to require the assertion equivalent to countable choice in my previous post, could be equivalent to every cauchy sequence converges in the space ...
Me neither, since for the infimum to exist you need the limit to exist, which is completeness in my understanding and has nothing to do with any kind of choice.
 
  • #19
I am a bit lost. Infimum of what, taken over what?
 
  • #20
fresh_42 said:
No, since I don't understand all of your words, e.g. "countable choice" or here "weaker form". Never heard of them before.
Some weaker forms of choice:
Axiom of countable dependent choice
Axiom of countable choice
Ultrafilter lemma

All can be consulted in wikipedia

Me neither, since for the infimum to exist you need the limit to exist, which is completeness in my understanding and has nothing to do with any kind of choice.
Ok, hopefully somebody might step in and clarify.
Added: You're probably right that it requires completeness but I don't think it is the same as completeness.
 
Last edited:
  • #21
martinbn said:
I am a bit lost. Infimum of what, taken over what?
Distance between 2 points in (pseudo)Riemannian manifolds is defined from the concept of curve arc length as the infimum of the arc lengths of the possible curves uniting the points. I would like to know if attaining this infimum requires some weak form of choice like countable choice.
 
  • #22
Perhaps an example might help, would you say the following requires some form of choice or is enpugh with completeness? : "Given a sequence (##A_n##) of non-empty sets, choose ##x_n ∈ A_n## for each ##n∈N##".
.
 
  • #23
RockyMarciano said:
Distance between 2 points in (pseudo)Riemannian manifolds is defined from the concept of curve arc length as the infimum of the arc lengths of the possible curves uniting the points. I would like to know if attaining this infimum requires some weak form of choice like countable choice.
In the beginning it seemed that you were asking about the existence of a metric. Now you say that you have a Riemannian manifold, which comes with the metric, and you want to define distance between two points as the infimum of lengths of curves that join them (in the pseudo-Riemannian case some things are different). But then this has nothing to do with manifolds, topologies and what not. What you are asking, seems to be, whether the result that a bounded from below set of real numbers has an infimum requires the axiom of choice.
 
  • #24
RockyMarciano said:
Perhaps an example might help, would you say the following requires some form of choice or is enpugh with completeness? : "Given a sequence (##A_n##) of non-empty sets, choose ##x_n ∈ A_n## for each ##n∈N##".
.
How is that related to any of the above, for example the completeness of the real numbers or metrics on manifolds?
 
  • #25
martinbn said:
In the beginning it seemed that you were asking about the existence of a metric. Now you say that you have a Riemannian manifold, which comes with the metric, and you want to define distance between two points as the infimum of lengths of curves that join them (in the pseudo-Riemannian case some things are different). But then this has nothing to do with manifolds, topologies and what not.
I realize that I have had problems making my question precise, I did mention lengths in manifolds in the OP.
What you are asking, seems to be, whether the result that a bounded from below set of real numbers has an infimum requires the axiom of choice.
No, that is not what I'm asking exactly, I am referring to the infimum in relation with the definition of distance in Riemannian geometry.
martinbn said:
How is that related to any of the above, for example the completeness of the real numbers or metrics on manifolds?
It is related to my question in this way, I identify the sequence ##A_n## with the sequence of curves(as sets of reals) between the points, and ##x_n## with the arc length in each curve, one of them being the infimum. I think this could be a good way to make it precise what I'm asking.
 
  • #26
RockyMarciano said:
It is related to my question in this way, I identify the sequence ##A_n## with the sequence of curves(as sets of reals) between the points, and ##x_n## with the arc length in each curve, one of them being the infimum. I think this could be a good way to make it precise what I'm asking.
But you don't make any choice, you build a limit which defines your choice, not an axiom.
 
  • #27
fresh_42 said:
But you don't make any choice, you build a limit which defines your choice, not an axiom.
Right, the choice is of an arc length for each n curve. Sorry if I confused you earlier. So the question is just whether choosing ##x_n## in #22 involves just ZF(and induction) or also some amount of the axiom of choice, what's your opinion?
 
  • #28
What do you mean by the choice of an arc length for each curve? If you have a Riemannian manifold and a curve between two points, there is no choice for its length.
 
  • #29
Sure for the arc length of a curve there is no choice involved, but this is not what I'm talking about here, I'm talking about the function defined on the collection of curves(as sets of real numbers) between two points that assigns to each of these countably infinite curves simultaneously some element of the set of real numbers of each curve to construct a sequence of which the infimum is defined to be the distance between the points. I'm asking if this choice function requires the axiom of countable choice.
 
  • #30
It is still very unclear. What choice is there for the function? Given any curve from the family you compute its length. So the function is the map from those curves to real numbers assigning the each curve its length, no choice involved here. May be you can make it clearer on an example. Take the Euclidean plane and two point, consider all curves (let's say smooth) with those two points as end points. Each of them has a length and you have the function that maps each curve to its length i.e. the domain is the set of these curves the range is positive real numbers. What you have is a set of positive real numbers, does it have an infimum? Where in all this is the choice you are asking about?
 
  • #31
martinbn said:
It is still very unclear. What choice is there for the function? Given any curve from the family you compute its length. So the function is the map from those curves to real numbers assigning the each curve its length, no choice involved here. May be you can make it clearer on an example. Take the Euclidean plane and two point, consider all curves (let's say smooth) with those two points as end points. Each of them has a length and you have the function that maps each curve to its length i.e. the domain is the set of these curves the range is positive real numbers. What you have is a set of positive real numbers, does it have an infimum? Where in all this is the choice you are asking about?
I'm considering the set X of all curves between the 2 given points, and these curves as sets S of points, and the choice function f(S) as the one that assigns a positive real number to each S in X. I'm using this definition of choice function from Wikipedia:"A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function f that is defined on some collection X of nonempty sets and assigns to each set S in that collection some element f(S) of S".
 
  • #32
RockyMarciano said:
I'm considering the set X of all curves between the 2 given points, and these curves as sets S of points, and the choice function f(S) as the one that assigns a positive real number to each S in X. I'm using this definition of choice function from Wikipedia:"A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function f that is defined on some collection X of nonempty sets and assigns to each set S in that collection some element f(S) of S".
But in your case ##f(S)## is not an element of ##S##, it is a real number, while ##S## consists of points of the manifold.
 
  • #33
RockyMarciano said:
Perhaps an example might help, would you say the following requires some form of choice or is enpugh with completeness? : "Given a sequence (##A_n##) of non-empty sets, choose ##x_n ∈ A_n## for each ##n∈N##".
.
Yes, this is the actual statement, at least as I know it.
 
  • #34
martinbn said:
But in your case ##f(S)## is not an element of ##S##, it is a real number, while ##S## consists of points of the manifold.
It is quite straightforward to identify the points with the real intervals(sets of reals) that the curves map to the points in the manifold, so S consists of real numbers. Or is this not licit?
 
  • #35
@martinbn, @fresh_42, @WWGD could you please address #34? I'm not sure if curves can be identified with sets of real numbers in this context.
 

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
25
Views
2K
  • Differential Geometry
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Differential Geometry
Replies
6
Views
3K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
11
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
6
Views
985
  • Poll
  • Science and Math Textbooks
Replies
4
Views
5K
  • Beyond the Standard Models
Replies
11
Views
2K
  • Math Proof Training and Practice
3
Replies
93
Views
6K
Back
Top