Understanding Division by Zero: Exploring the Concept of Undefined

  • Thread starter heshbon
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Stupid
In summary, the reason why division by zero is undefined is because it is not possible to define it in a way that would make sense mathematically. Unlike other operations, such as multiplication and addition, there is no way to define division by zero as the inverse of another operation. This is due to the fact that multiplication is not a one-to-one function, meaning that there are multiple inputs that can result in the same output. Therefore, division by zero remains undefined and cannot be given a numerical value.
  • #1
heshbon
27
0
Division by zero is undefined...but why doesn't somebody just define it?

Like they did with root (-1).
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
  • #3
heshbon said:
Division by zero is undefined...but why doesn't somebody just define it?

Like they did with root (-1).

Arithmetical operations have to result in unique numbers.
4 multiplied by 6 can result in one and only one number.
100 divided by 12 results in one and only one number.
1 divided by zero does not result in a unique number. What it results in is not numerically definable.
 
  • #4
heshbon said:
Division by zero is undefined...but why doesn't somebody just define it?

Like they did with root (-1).

[itex]\forall x\in \mathbb{R}, x \times 0 = 0[/itex]

Then

Let be [itex]a, b \in \mathbb{R}, a \neq b[/itex]

We said before that [itex]a \times 0 = 0[/tex] and also [itex]b \times 0 = 0[/itex].

So, [itex]a \times 0 = b \times 0[/tex]. If we were able to divide by 0, we will have that [itex]a = b[/itex] which is a contradition with our suppose.
 
  • #5
heshbon said:
Division by zero is undefined...but why doesn't somebody just define it?

Like they did with root (-1).

Check the archives. There are good discussions about this question.

The basic problem is there IS no way to define it in such a way that it is the full inverse of multiplication.

What does that mean? Two operators are inverses if they "undo" each other, regardless of input. Addition and subtraction are the best known example. For any x and y, x + y - y = x. You start with x, you do "+y" then you "undo" the +y with a -y.

But there is no way to do this with multiplication. You can do it for *almost* every single number. Clearly, if we have 16 * 4 / 4, that equals 16 and division has "undone" the multiplication. In fact, this works for every number except 0. Try it out.

The proof of this lies in the fact that multiplication is not one-to-one (it does not map unique inputs to unique outputs). Functions which are one-to-one all have inverse functions. Functions which are not one-to-one may only, at best, have partial inverses.

This contrasts to imaginary numbers. Square root, unlike division, IS one-to-one. No two real numbers have the same square root. However, it happens that some reals don't have square roots. The imaginary number system is a way to extend the real line to preserve the square root function's one-to-one-ness, and at the same time, upgrade square root from a partial function to a total function.
 
  • #6
Tac-Tics said:
What does that mean? Two operators are inverses if they "undo" each other, regardless of input. Addition and subtraction are the best known example. For any x and y, x + y - y = x. You start with x, you do "+y" then you "undo" the +y with a -y.
This definition is too restrictive, just say that y and it's inverse under the operation gives the identity.
Here's a counterexample. Define the binary operation on a set S = {a,b,c} as follows
[tex]
\newcommand{\mc}[3]{\multicolumn{#1}{#2}{#3}}
\begin{array}{|l|lll}\hline
\mc{1}{l}{*} & \mc{1}{l}{\bfseries a} & \bfseries b & \bfseries c \\ \hline
a & a & b & c \\
b & b & a & b \\
c & c & b & a
\end{array}
[/tex]
The operation is commutative, [itex]a[/itex] is the identity, and for each x in S, the inverse is also x. Let's do b on c, [itex]cb = a[/itex] let's undo b by it's inverse, then [itex](cb)b = ab = b[/tex] but now the original [itex]c[/itex]
This is due to the fact that your definition would work only for associative operations!

The proof of this lies in the fact that multiplication is not one-to-one (it does not map unique inputs to unique outputs). Functions which are one-to-one all have inverse functions. Functions which are not one-to-one may only, at best, have partial inverses.
Does that mean addition is one-to-one? What is the definition of a one-to-one here?
Take [itex](7,1) \neq (5,3)[/tex] but [itex]+(7,1) = +(5,3)[/itex], in other words, I can't see how given an output, one can determine the unique ones which produced it (the usual one-to-one definition!)
Actually "map unique inputs to unique outputs" doesn't suggest one-to-oneness but rather that the operation is well defined, i.e given a unique x, it gets mapped to only one f(x)!
 
Last edited:
  • #7
wsalem said:
This definition is too restrictive,

I wasn't giving a full definition. Just the flavor of it.

You shouldn't really speak of an operator's inverse. You speak about sections of that operator, where only one argument is applied, such as (*2), the doubling function. The inverse function would be (/2), the halving function.

The argument is that the section (*0), which maps all real numbers to 0, has no inverse.

When speaking about addition, what I meant was that all functions (+n) have an inverse called (-n). To contrast, for all n EXCEPT 0, (*n) has an inverse (/n). That exception cannot be removed because (*0) is not one-to-one. In fact, it is quite the opposite.
 
  • #8
You shouldn't really speak of an operator's inverse. You speak about sections of that operator, where only one argument is applied, such as (*2), the doubling function. The inverse function would be (/2), the halving function.
Let me clarify that when I said "y and it's inverse under the operation gives the identity.", I was implicitly assuming "if it exists" both for the inverse and for the identity. Obviously an operation doesn't need to have any of these!

The argument is that the section (*0), which maps all real numbers to 0, has no inverse.
Absolutely! I never argued that!

When speaking about addition, what I meant was that all functions (+n) have an inverse called (-n). To contrast, for all n EXCEPT 0, (*n) has an inverse (/n). That exception cannot be removed because (*0) is not one-to-one. In fact, it is quite the opposite.
I'm sorry but I can't follow, what "all functions (+n)" are you talking about here, do you mean to define a function for each n, why not just a single function that sends each element to it's inverse?

To contrast, for all n EXCEPT 0, (*n) has an inverse (/n). That exception cannot be removed because (*0) is not one-to-one.
Surely the exception cannot be removed, but then if we define such function, actually *0 wouldn't be "not one-to-one" but rather undefined!
This is what my argument is about, I can't understand what do you mean by one-to-one!
 
  • #9
Tac-Tics, I should have assumed the definition meant to be informal, so I hope my reply didn't offend you. I simply couldn't understand what you meant by one-to-one! But this is off the main argument. I think you already made your point which I definitely agree with. Cheers.
 
Last edited:
  • #10
wsalem said:
Tac-Tics, I should have assumed the definition meant to be informal, so I hope my reply didn't offend you.

You did not offend.

I might as well add one more idea about division. The standard accepted definition is that division isn't even defined at 0. If we're talking about the function f(x) = 1/x (or using "section" notation (1/)), 0 isn't even part of the domain. The advantage of this is that f is actually a continuous function (by the epsilon-delta definition) even though its graph clearly makes a large "jump" from negative infinity to positive infinity.
 
  • #11
I'm glad to hear that.

Surely, there's an algebraic explanation why it is undefined, as was elaborated by you and others, but here's an interesting example.
The same operations of R (+ and *) defined on a set with just one element. We can actually freely divide by 0 since we already know that the multiplicative identity equals the additive identity.

But I realize also that the original poster didn't question why it's undefined but rather why we can't find a way to come around it, which I believe was put nicely in the fourth post by MiGUi, which if such inverse exists, it would result in equating all the elements (in other words, reduces the set R to a singleton set, which is contradictory).
 
  • #12
Simple-minded thought: a number, n is a specific (although unknown, variable) number, and zero is a specific number. n divided by 0 is infinity? But infinity is NOT a number. Division by zero is impossible. Good? Not Good?
 
  • #13
I wouldn't go with that argument, infinity is a "number" in the extended reals isn't it?
 
  • #14
Is it possible to construct an algebraic system where zero is not unique, prehaps have a unique zero for every element which would than permit division by zero?

Or maybe think of the zero as an operater rather than an identity element where the inverse would represent division by zero.

sorry for the general questions but any response would be greatly appreciated.
 
  • #15
Algebraicly speaking, there's a structure called wheels, which does something similar to that. Not sure how useful it is though! See http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0960129503004110

Division by zero is still not defined in the extended real line, since you would get both [itex]+\infty[/itex] and [itex]-\infty[/itex]. However, it can be defined on the extended complex plane [itex]C \cup \{\infty\} [/itex] since there's only one infinity, and you would get [itex]\frac{1}{0} = \infty[/itex]. But the structure you get is NOT a field, like R or C. So you won't be treating it as an algebraic structure and get the usual contradictions!
 
Last edited:

Related to Understanding Division by Zero: Exploring the Concept of Undefined

1. What is considered a "possibly very stupid question" in the scientific community?

In the scientific community, there is no such thing as a "stupid" question. All inquiries and curiosity are welcomed and encouraged, as they contribute to the advancement of knowledge and understanding.

2. Why do people say "possibly a very stupid question" before asking a question?

This phrase is often used to acknowledge that the question may seem obvious or simple to some, but the person asking genuinely does not know the answer and is seeking clarification.

3. Is it better to ask a "possibly a very stupid question" or not ask at all?

It is always better to ask a question, even if it may seem "stupid" to some. Asking questions is a crucial part of the scientific process and can lead to new insights and discoveries.

4. How can I avoid feeling embarrassed when asking a "possibly a very stupid question"?

Remember that everyone has different levels of knowledge and understanding in different areas. Asking questions is a sign of curiosity and a desire to learn, which are important qualities in a scientist. It is also important to create a safe and inclusive environment where all questions are welcomed and respected.

5. Should I fact-check before asking a "possibly a very stupid question"?

It is always a good idea to do some research and fact-check before asking a question, as it may save time and lead to a more productive discussion. However, if you are unsure or cannot find the answer, do not hesitate to ask the question as it may spark a valuable conversation and lead to new knowledge.

Similar threads

  • General Math
2
Replies
47
Views
3K
  • Programming and Computer Science
Replies
32
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
Replies
13
Views
2K
  • General Math
Replies
7
Views
3K
Replies
10
Views
1K
  • General Math
2
Replies
45
Views
4K
  • General Math
Replies
2
Views
2K
  • General Math
2
Replies
36
Views
4K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Back
Top