ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation

  • MHB
  • Thread starter Math Amateur
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Axiom Zfc
In summary: So, $1 \cap a = \{0\} \cap \{1,2,3\} = \emptyset$ since $0 \not\in \{1,2,3\}$.In summary, the Axiom of Foundation establishes that every non-empty set has an element that is disjoint from it. This is important because it shows that there is no set that contains itself, preventing the existence of a "buck-stopping" set. It also distinguishes between a number and a singleton subset, as seen in the example of $\{1\}$ and $1$. This distinction is often overlooked in analysis. Additionally, the axiom helps to establish that the collection of all sets is not a set
  • #1
Math Amateur
Gold Member
MHB
3,990
48
I am reading Micheal Searcoid's book: Elements of Abstract Analysis ( Springer Undergraduate Mathematics Series) ...

I am currently focussed on Searcoid's treatment of ZFC in Chapter 1: Sets ...

I am struggling to attain a full understanding of the Axiom of Foundation which reads as shown below:https://www.physicsforums.com/attachments/5072Can someone explain this Axiom and give some simple examples ...

I am perplexed by my own example ... as follows ...

Consider the set \(\displaystyle a = \{ 1, 2, 3 \}\)

[Note that \(\displaystyle 1, 2, 3\) are sets - previous post by Deveno ... ]

Now \(\displaystyle 1 \cup a = 1 \)

and \(\displaystyle 2 \cup a = 2\)

and \(\displaystyle 3 \cup a = 3\)

... ? ... what is the member of a which is disjoint from a ...

Can someone clarify this issue and explain how the Axiom works ...

Hope someone can help ..

Peter
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Let's look at a very simple set:

$A = \{a\}$.

Since $a \in A$, the axiom applies, because $A$ is non-empty. So we have an element of $A$ which is disjoint from $A$. Well, the only element to be found is $a$. So:

$a \cap A = \emptyset$. Let's write this a bit differently:

$a \cap \{a\} = \emptyset$.

I claim this means $a \not\in a$.

For suppose we had $a \in a$. Since $a \in A$, this would mean $a$ and $A$ have a common element, $a$. But this violates:

$a \cap A = \emptyset$.

The purpose of this, is to establish that there is no such set as:

$S = \{S,\{S,\{S,\dots,\}\}\}$

in other words "the buck stops somewhere" (this principle is called "foundation" or "well-founded-ness").

It establishes that $a$ and $\{a\}$ are always *distinct* sets. This distinction is often glossed over in analysis, where the real number $x$, and the singleton subset $\{x\}$ are often conflated (by such vague language such as "consider the point $x$").

Interestingly enough, if $\phi(x)$ is the predicate; $x \not\in x$, we see that $\phi(x)$ is true for any non-empty set $x$.

So if the collection of all sets was a set, it would be a Russell set, whose very existence negates itself. This contradiction shows the collection of all sets is not a set.

As for your example, you are confusing $1$ with $\{1\}$. For example:

$\{1\} \cap a = \{1\}$, but:

$1 \cap a = \emptyset$ (since $0 \not\in a$).
 
  • #3
Deveno said:
Let's look at a very simple set:

$A = \{a\}$.

Since $a \in A$, the axiom applies, because $A$ is non-empty. So we have an element of $A$ which is disjoint from $A$. Well, the only element to be found is $a$. So:

$a \cap A = \emptyset$. Let's write this a bit differently:

$a \cap \{a\} = \emptyset$.

I claim this means $a \not\in a$.

For suppose we had $a \in a$. Since $a \in A$, this would mean $a$ and $A$ have a common element, $a$. But this violates:

$a \cap A = \emptyset$.

The purpose of this, is to establish that there is no such set as:

$S = \{S,\{S,\{S,\dots,\}\}\}$

in other words "the buck stops somewhere" (this principle is called "foundation" or "well-founded-ness").

It establishes that $a$ and $\{a\}$ are always *distinct* sets. This distinction is often glossed over in analysis, where the real number $x$, and the singleton subset $\{x\}$ are often conflated (by such vague language such as "consider the point $x$").

Interestingly enough, if $\phi(x)$ is the predicate; $x \not\in x$, we see that $\phi(x)$ is true for any non-empty set $x$.

So if the collection of all sets was a set, it would be a Russell set, whose very existence negates itself. This contradiction shows the collection of all sets is not a set.

As for your example, you are confusing $1$ with $\{1\}$. For example:

$\{1\} \cap a = \{1\}$, but:

$1 \cap a = \emptyset$ (since $0 \not\in a$).
Hi Deveno ... thanks for the help ...

Still reflecting on your post ...

But just one quick question ... ...

... you write ...

" ... As for your example, you are confusing $1$ with $\{1\}$. For example:

$\{1\} \cap a = \{1\}$, but:

$1 \cap a = \emptyset$ (since $0 \not\in a$). ..."

I do not follow your reasoning in arguing that $1 \cap a = \emptyset$ because $0 \not\in a$ ... can you explain this further ... how exactly does the fact that $0 \not\in a$ imply that $1 \cap a = \emptyset$ ...

Hope you can clarify and explain this issue ...

Peter
 
  • #4
As a set, $1 = \{0\}$.
 

1. What is ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation?

ZFC, or Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice, is a widely used mathematical system that serves as the foundation of modern set theory. The Axiom of Foundation, also known as the Axiom of Regularity, is one of the axioms of ZFC that ensures the existence of a well-founded universe of sets.

2. Why is ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation important?

ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation are important because they provide a rigorous and consistent foundation for mathematics. They allow mathematicians to define and study sets and their properties in a logical and systematic way, leading to further advancements in various branches of mathematics.

3. What is the relationship between ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation?

The Axiom of Foundation is one of the axioms of ZFC, meaning that it is a fundamental assumption used to build the entire system of ZFC. This axiom, along with the other axioms of ZFC, ensures that the resulting system is consistent and can be used to prove mathematical theorems.

4. Are ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation universally accepted?

While ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation are widely accepted and used in mathematics, there are alternative set theories that do not include the Axiom of Foundation. These alternative theories, such as non-well-founded set theory, may lead to different mathematical conclusions and are still an active area of research in mathematical logic.

5. Can ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation be proven to be consistent?

One of the main goals of set theory is to prove the consistency of ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation. However, this has not been achieved yet and remains an open question in mathematical logic. Many mathematicians believe that ZFC and the Axiom of Foundation are consistent, but a proof has not yet been discovered.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
14
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
5
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
4
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
9
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
2
Views
2K
Back
Top