Are there signs that any Quantum Interpretation can be proved or disproved?

In summary, according to the experts, decoherence has not made much progress in improving our understanding of the measurement problem.
  • #36
Sunil said:
I think the "unobservable" is misleading, given that all what we see are those positions - of macroscopic devices
Exactly: we see positions of macroscopic devices, not positions of individual particles. (Btw, the "particles" in question aren't necessarily any of the particles that appear in our fundamental theories--they're not necessarily quarks or leptons. They could be some other kind of particles at a deeper level.) The individual particle positions, which are the basic ontology of the Bohmian interpretation, are unobservable.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
The only theory that unites the quantum world with the "classical" scale is QFT. Out of it, it's known that the world is not made of classical objects but of the 18 quantum fields. The fields are the fundamental nature of reality. At least as far as science goes.
Gravity isn't expected to change the fields nature of reality either.
At least we now know how the world isn't.

To tackle the enigma of classical perception, physicists have conjured up fantastic ontologies: higher-dimensional space-time or the multiverse, in which our universe is just one instance out of an infinitude. Other physicists have resorted to mysticism. There are more ontological questions than answers, but it's better to not know than be fooled.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
  • Skeptical
Likes AlexCaledin and Motore
  • #38
This article seems to question the universal validity of the projection postulate.

If correct would this affect the interpretations of QM?

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-021-00452-x

"Specifically, quantum computing algorithms make heavy use of the projection postulate [2], the axiom that every measurement is strictly equivalent to random application of one of a set of mathematical projection operators, with probability governed by the Born rule.
...
So, is the projection postulate or any related measurement axiom fundamentally and literally true if you look closely enough? In this paper, I will attempt to analyze the internal dynamics of a specific real single-quantum detector, the cloud chamber.
...
I have formulated a mechanism for how the Hamiltonian structure of quantum decay, the physics of droplets in supersaturated vapors, and the mathematics of quantum Coulomb scattering from degenerate states can together account for the observed phenomenology of track origination in cloud chambers, without having to invoke measurement axioms."
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #39
timmdeeg said:
This article seems to question the universal validity of the projection postulate.

If correct would this affect the interpretations of QM?
Hard to say. Some physicists reject the projection postulate (as generally valid), but don't expect this to be a big deal:
vanhees71 said:
Where I strongly differ with the orthodox/minimal view (aka the 7 rules agreed on by the majority in this forum) is only in refusing the collapse/projection postulate as a fundamental generally valid postulate.
Arnold Neumaier's thermal interpretation also comes to the conclusion that Born's rule (and the projection postulate) are not universally valid, but seems to attach more importance to this:
A. Neumaier said:
Then I prove that under certain other circumstances and especially for ideal binary measurements (rather than assume that always, or at least under unstated conditions), Born's interpretation of the formal Born rule as a statistical ensemble mean is valid. Thus I recover the probabilistic interpretation in the cases where it is essential, and only there, without having assumed it anywhere.
Maybe the attached importance is more related to the Born rule itself, than to the projection postulate.

Edit: I should probably clarify that my answer just tries to point out that practical implications of the non-universality of the projection postulate will be very limited, because it is well known already that you should not interpret it too literally. So my guess is that the implications for quantum computing will be minimal. For interpretations on the other hand, stressing its non-universality might be important.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg
  • #40
For me the question whether or not the Born rule can be derived from other postulates is secondary. You can come to the same mathematical formalism via different heuristic routes. I'm not too convinced by the alternative @A. Neumaier calls "thermal interpretation".

What's for sure clear is that the projection postulate is not needed and in almost all real-world experiments not followed or not feasible. It's only a special case of a particular sort of preparation procedure where it is possible to prepare a system in a pure quantum state by measurement of a certain observable (or a set of compatible observables) to a resolution such that all but one outcome are filtered away. This is possible e.g., for the Stern-Gerlach experiment, where a beam of silver atoms is split in two entangeling the spin component chosen by the direction of the magnetic field with the position almost ideally and thus being able to prepare a pure spin-component eigenstate. Another example are polarization states of single photons just using a good polarization filter. It depends on the feasibility of such a high-resolution measurement and filtering, whether you can prepare a certain given pure quantum state, and most measurements are far from this. I don't think that such an exceptional case should be taken as one of the fundamental postulates of a general physical theory.
 
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg and gentzen
  • #41
gentzen said:
Hard to say. Some physicists reject the projection postulate (as generally valid), but don't expect this to be a big deal:
The projection postulate is not an interpretation of QM, but which importance this postulate has for a physicist perhaps depends on the interpretation he favors.
 
  • #42
vanhees71 said:
What's for sure clear is that the projection postulate is not needed and in almost all real-world experiments not followed or not feasible.
Would you say that this conclusion is interpretation independent?
 
  • #43
timmdeeg said:
Would you say that this conclusion is interpretation independent?


It's standard quantum mechanics. Some people don't like it because it leads to the measurement paradox and the issue with the cat.

I think it's the most revealing aspect of all QT.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg
  • #44
timmdeeg said:
I have formulated a mechanism for how the Hamiltonian structure of quantum decay, the physics of droplets in supersaturated vapors, and the mathematics of quantum Coulomb scattering from degenerate states can together account for the observed phenomenology of track origination in cloud chambers, without having to invoke measurement axioms."
The mechanism described appears to me to be similar to Neumaier's thermal interpretation, which was mentioned in an earlier post. Basically, the mechanism is random variation in the huge number of degrees of freedom of the detector--in this case the molecules in the chamber--which leads to one particular direction for the cloud chamber track being selected out of all the possible ones.
 
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg
  • #45
timmdeeg said:
Would you say that this conclusion is interpretation independent?
Yes, you only have to look, how in practice QT is applied to describe and predict the outcome of real-world measurements within QT.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and timmdeeg
  • #46
PeterDonis said:
The mechanism described appears to me to be similar to Neumaier's thermal interpretation, which was mentioned in an earlier post. Basically, the mechanism is random variation in the huge number of degrees of freedom of the detector--in this case the molecules in the chamber--which leads to one particular direction for the cloud chamber track being selected out of all the possible ones.
This has been discussed already in 1929 by Mott in a famous article about, why one sees "straight trajectories" of ##\alpha## particles emitted from a radioactive probe within a cloud chamber. The probability for emission of any individual ##\alpha## particle is random in its direction (in good approximation it's isotropic) and the magnitude of the momentum is determined from the energy of the emitted ##\alpha## particle which is determined at an accuracy which can be estimated by the lifetime-energy uncertainty relation. Mott shows that once the direction of the ##\alpha## particle is given after being emitted by the ionization of the first few droplets of the vapor in the cloud chamber, the probability for ionizing the next droplet in the cloud chamber is sharply peaked around the straight line. It's of course clear that the "trajectory" is never as accurately determined as it would violate the Heisenberg uncertainty relation. This follows without any fancy interpretations from the application of the minimal interpretation as given in the Insights article (you don't even need the projection postulate, which however in this case holds to a pretty good approximation).
 
  • Like
Likes AlexCaledin
  • #47
vanhees71 said:
What's for sure clear is that the projection postulate is not needed and in almost all real-world experiments not followed or not feasible.
Yes. What is universally true (and therefore should replace the projection postulate and Born's rule associated with it) is the more general POVM view. Simple, elementary foundations for it are given in my paper 'Born's rule and measurement' (arXiv:1912.09906).
vanhees71 said:
I'm not too convinced by the alternative @A. Neumaier calls "thermal interpretation".
But as shown in the above paper, the thermal interpretation matches perfectly with the POVM view.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and vanhees71
  • #48
Well, as you well know, I've no objections of your formalism, but more when it comes to interpretational issues. What I don't like is that it is not clear, which meaning what you call "expectation values" have. As you want to derive the Born rule, I cannot read it in its usual meaning, namely a probabilistic expectation value. On the other hand the idea that this is actually the "observable" is also not convincing, because that may be true in a "thermal sense", i.e., when you consider macroscopic observables, where the fluctuations are "negligibly small" because you "coarse grain" over large enough space-time volumes, and in this sense your interpretation is indeed really "thermal", but it doesn't apply to microscopic objects, for which we want to use and interpret quantum theory.

That's why I still think from a physicist's point of view the "orthodox minimal interpretation" (no collapse, no quantum-classical cuts on a fundamental level but probabilities and only probabilities a la Born with Born's rule itself a fundamental postulate) is the most "economic approach" to state the scientific part of quantum theory (the only part which in my opinion belongs to physics and not metaphysics).

I'll have a look at your paper as soon as I find the time :-(.
 
  • #49
vanhees71 said:
That's why I still think from a physicist's point of view the "orthodox minimal interpretation" (no collapse, no quantum-classical cuts on a fundamental level but probabilities and only probabilities a la Born with Born's rule itself a fundamental postulate) is the most "economic approach" to state the scientific part of quantum theory (the only part which in my opinion belongs to physics and not metaphysics).
In his book "Einstein's Schleier" Zeilinger says analogously (? sinngemäß) it is sufficient to understand the wave function just as a mental construct so that its collapse doesn't happen in real space. I was never sure if that is his personal view. It seems to fit though to that what you call "orthodox minimal interpretation", right?
 
  • Like
Likes AlexCaledin and vanhees71
  • #50
I think so. I've also read this book, and it's always good to have the view of an experimentalist. I've always talked briefly with Zeilinger after a colloquium some years ago, and there also he told me he's pretty much a "Bohrian Copenhagenian". AFAIK also in his scientific papers, he's pretty much an "orthodox minimal interpreter".
 
  • Like
Likes AlexCaledin and timmdeeg
  • #51
vanhees71 said:
the idea that this is actually the "observable" is also not convincing, because that may be true in a "thermal sense", i.e., when you consider macroscopic observables, where the fluctuations are "negligibly small" because you "coarse grain" over large enough space-time volumes, and in this sense your interpretation is indeed really "thermal",
Thus it applies to the measurement results, which are read off from macroscopic thermal objects...
vanhees71 said:
but it doesn't apply to microscopic objects, for which we want to use and interpret quantum theory.
... even when what is measured is a microscopic degree of freedom, by design of the detector strongly correlated with some macroscopic detector property. This is precisely the condition that allows us to speak of a measurement.
 
  • #52
@A. Neumaier: If we measure properties of macroscopic bodies, things like expectation values are usually not thought to be beables but epistemic quantities. In principle, such measurement processes should also admit a quantum description where your thermal interpretation treats expectation values as beables. How is this reconciled?
 
  • #53
timmdeeg said:
In his book "Einstein's Schleier" Zeilinger says analogously (? sinngemäß) it is sufficient to understand the wave function just as a mental construct so that its collapse doesn't happen in real space. I was never sure if that is his personal view. It seems to fit though to that what you call "orthodox minimal interpretation", right?
The detected positions correspond as if the collapse happened in real space. 1:1

That's as good as a model can get.

You can't just brush aside the evidence.
 
  • #54
kith said:
@A. Neumaier: If we measure properties of macroscopic bodies, things like expectation values are usually not thought to be beables but epistemic quantities. In principle, such measurement processes should also admit a quantum description where your thermal interpretation treats expectation values as beables. How is this reconciled?
Nothing in the abstract formalism forces us to interpret the trace of ##\rho A## as an expectation values. A historically unbiased name for this number is 'value of ##A## in the state ##\rho##' - this is the literal mathematical meaning when treating the state ##\rho## as a linear functional on an algebra of observables -, leaving the additional qualification 'expectation' to statistical interpretations.

In the thermal interpretation, the traditional name 'expectation value' is therefore just a historical leftover from the old days when the statistical interpretation was thought to be the only reasonable one. I often use 'q-expectation value' to emphasize that quantum expectation values have the name but not the meaning in common with statistical expectation values.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #55
I'm not sure if I understand this correctly. Does the thermal interpretation say that all quantum mechanical quantities which are traditionally thought of as statistical are beables and that statistics is relevant only in the classical description of measurement devices?
 
  • #56
EPR said:
The detected positions correspond as if the collapse happened in real space. 1:1
But this notion (in contradiction to special relativity) means that energy spread out in real space would collapse to a point instantaneously. That exactly is Zeilinger's argument. QM doesn't claim the "real space" issue.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #57
kith said:
I'm not sure if I understand this correctly. Does the thermal interpretation say that all quantum mechanical quantities which are traditionally thought of as statistical are beables and that statistics is relevant only in the classical description of measurement devices?
Not quite.

Whatever is traditionally a statistical expectation value is in the thermal interpretation a q-expectation value and hence a beable. But one can do statistics even on quantum beables, not only on classical ones. In this way one recovers in the thermal interpretation the statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics in those situations where it applies - namely when one has a large supply of instances in identically prepared states.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and kith
  • #58
@A. Neumaier: Would you say that the "thermal interpretation" is independent of whether or not the projection postulate holds?
 
  • #59
timmdeeg said:
But this notion (in contradiction to special relativity) means that energy spread out in real space would collapse to a point instantaneously. That exactly is Zeilinger's argument. QM doesn't claim the "real space" issue.
Yes. If you supposed the system had those properties(e.g. energy) before measurement, you'd get some nonlocality.
 
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg
  • #60
A. Neumaier said:
Thus it applies to the measurement results, which are read off from macroscopic thermal objects...

... even when what is measured is a microscopic degree of freedom, by design of the detector strongly correlated with some macroscopic detector property. This is precisely the condition that allows us to speak of a measurement.
My problem with the approach you call "thermal interpretation" still is that it is not clear what the operational meaning of your expectation values is, because you stress several times it's not considered to have the usual probabilistic meaning, but what then is the operational meaning?

What I like about the approach principally is that it makes the attempt to describe the meausurement process on a quantum theoretical basis. If this could worked out to a convincing physical picture, I think it would be real progress.

The advantage of the orthodox minimal interpretation is that it starts from clear operational concepts, i.e., the expectation values have a clear probabilistic meaning, and a measurement device is a real-world physical object not some abstract mathematical construction like a POVM. The latter is needed for the cases that you are qualitatively describing but it's never worked out how to construct the POVM for a given real-world (say quantum optical) apparatus like a beam splitter, mirrors, lenses, a photodector, etc. In the standard approach (see e.g., the textbooks by Scully and Zubairy or Garrison and Chiao), where all these elements are pragmatically described by effective quantized classical models. To some extent you can also derive it from quantum many-body theory from first principles though that is of course pretty tough.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby
  • #61
WernerQH said:
No, I am not an instrumentalist.
I'm an instrumentalist and a Bohmian. Looks contradictory, but it isn't. :smile:
(See the link in my signature.)
 
  • #62
If you are an instrumentalist you cannot be a Bohmian at the same time, or how are you measuring Bohm's trajectories for a single particle (sic!) in the real-world lab?
 
  • #63
Could you please clarify the difference between "instrumentalist" and "orthodox minimal interpretation" in a short way?
 
  • #64
timmdeeg said:
Could you please clarify the difference between "instrumentalist" and "orthodox minimal interpretation" in a short way?
You probably have to distinguish between the pejorative use of the term "instrumentalist", and between the positive aspects actual instrumentalists see in it. I was not always an instrumentalist. I only became one after studying and expensively using M. Born and E. Wolf. Principles of Optics. My guess is that Max Born was an instrumentalist, and Arnold Sommerfeld too. They were excellent in their mastery of mathematics (Sommerfeld's rigorous solution of light scattering on the perfectly conducting half plane is incredible), and cared about what they could compute and do with their mathematics.

Let me take incoherent light as an example. There is no such thing as perfectly incoherent light, at least not in theory. Yet there are many scenarios in practice that are most appropriately modeled by using the incoherent limit. So an instrumentalist like me might draw a picture of two isolated wave packets that miss each other, and write a reassuring text like "If each wave train is alone, it cannot interfere with another wave train" (see last slide of attached pdf). But I knew that it was a lie, it was not how I thought about it myself. For me, it was not important whether the wave trains missed each other or not. It was only important that their frequencies were not exactly identical, so that the interference effects would average out in the end. But will they really exactly average out? Of course not, but I don't care.
 

Attachments

  • CoherentVsIncoherent.pdf
    118.4 KB · Views: 86
  • Like
Likes dextercioby, vanhees71 and timmdeeg
  • #65
timmdeeg said:
This article seems to question the universal validity of the projection postulate.

If correct would this affect the interpretations of QM?

https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-021-00452-x
A wave function is not a "thing". Neither is it a complete description of reality. Schonfeld seems to think otherwise and feels compelled to derive something inherently non-deterministic from Schrödinger´s equation. What strikes me as particularly unphysical is the idea that an MeV alpha-particle, setting out as a spherical wave, can be "lured" into a particular direction by processes at the eV-scale in a metastable medium.

Something that is rarely discussed is the difference between the time-dependent and the time-independent Schrödinger equation. The stationary solutions of the time-independent Schrödinger equation are completely uncontroversial, and almost everybody agrees that those wave functions represent a time average. (The only time-dependence is an irrelevant phase factor, and of course this does not imply that the electrons are at rest.) Such a wave function describes a statistical ensemble.

Many people instantly forget this when they turn to the time-dependent Schrödinger equation. The wave function then seems to acquire a new meaning: describing an individual electron. The time-dependent Schrödinger equation describes the continuous and deterministic evolution of "something", which is completely at odds with the abruptness and randomness of processes in the real world. Quantum theory is more than Schrödinger´s equation: it is a stochastic theory giving us averages and expectation values. "Measurement" and the resulting collapse of the wave function were introduced only to uphold the fiction that the wave function represents an individual system; they are superfluous adornments of the formalism.A wave function is the best description we have of a beam of completely polarized particles; it is "complete" in the sense that there is no more comprehensive description. But it represents only a statistical ensemble. I think that the discussion of the time-dependence of wave functions is misleading. (In the Heisenberg picture the time-dependence disappears altogether.) It´s also worth pointing out that the Born rule arose from the consideration of stationary solutions of the scattering problem (solutions of the time-independent Schrödinger equation).
 
  • Like
Likes timmdeeg
  • #66
timmdeeg said:
@A. Neumaier: Would you say that the "thermal interpretation" is independent of whether or not the projection postulate holds?
The thermal interpretation implies that the projection postulate holds only under special circumstances, called von Neumann measurements. It is well-known that many measurements are not of this kind; any of these disproves the general validity of the projection postulate.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71, timmdeeg and gentzen
  • #67
A. Neumaier said:
The thermal interpretation implies that the projection postulate holds only under special circumstances, called von Neumann measurements. It is well-known that many measurements are not of this kind; any of these disproves the general validity of the projection postulate.
Didn't the Eraser experiment specifically disprove the existence of these 'other kind of measurements'?
 
  • #68
I don't know which "eraser experiment" you mean, but what should it have disproven? To the contrary the examples I know are all in very good accordance with the quantum theoretical predictions, and for sure here the projection postulate doesn't hold (as for nearly any experiment involving photons), because the photons are not in an eigenstate of the measured observable after the measurement but absorbed by the detector ;-)).
 
  • #69
I worded it wrong, I guess. I meant that the quantum eraser experiment suggests that measurements do not rely on classical apparatus for collapse. And those types of measurements(von Neumann measurements), which are purely quantum measurements between two strictly quantum systems(not classical) likely do not constitute measurements. As they depend on the presence of which-way inormation and not on the presence of classical apparati.
Von Neumann at some point concluded that this setup was unsatisfactory and posited the somewhat controversial bring up of consciousness into the scheme.

Sorry, if this is an incomplete account. I am trying to better understand von Neumann's reasoning. If I have grasped it correctly.
 
  • #70
vanhees71 said:
If you are an instrumentalist you cannot be a Bohmian at the same time, or how are you measuring Bohm's trajectories for a single particle (sic!) in the real-world lab?
You can play an instrument like the violin and be a Bohmian. :p
 
  • Haha
Likes Delta2 and vanhees71

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
1
Views
309
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
29
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
11
Replies
371
Views
10K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
979
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
736
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
15
Views
172
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
653
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
49
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
14
Views
2K
Back
Top