I Cantor's Controversies: Resolving Divisive Theories in Mathematics

  • I
  • Thread starter Thread starter greswd
  • Start date Start date
AI Thread Summary
Cantor faced significant criticism from prominent mathematicians like Kronecker, who rejected the concept of infinity and found Cantor's ideas divisive. The clarity of Cantor's expressions was often questioned, leading to misunderstandings of his theories, which were later articulated more clearly by others. The intuitionist movement, which emerged partly in response to Cantor's work, denied certain logical principles, complicating acceptance of his theories. Despite initial resistance, Cantor's contributions were eventually embraced by many in the mathematical community, particularly in the 20th century. The controversies surrounding Cantor's work highlight the evolving nature of mathematical understanding and the importance of clear communication in the field.
greswd
Messages
764
Reaction score
20
Cantor was severely criticised by many brilliant mathematicians of his time, many of whom we still regard as brilliant today.

What was so divisive about his theories? How did we resolve it? How could the best minds not do so back then?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Primarily because Cantor did not express his ideas very well or very clearly. What we have now are his ideas expressed by other people in clearer and more logical terms.
 
greswd said:
Cantor was severely criticised by many brilliant mathematicians of his time, many of whom we still regard as brilliant today.

What was so divisive about his theories? How did we resolve it? How could the best minds not do so back then?

His main enemy was Kronecker. K thought that infinity was a bogus concept, so naturally he didn't like what Cantor was up to. At the time even proof by contradiction was controversial.
 
Hornbein said:
At the time even proof by contradiction was controversial.

Was it? Even Euclid uses proof by contradiction many times in his Elements, and nobody had an objection to that! It is true that nonconstructive methods were controversial, but that is not the same as proof by contradiction being controversial!
 
micromass said:
Was it? Even Euclid uses proof by contradiction many times in his Elements, and nobody had an objection to that! It is true that nonconstructive methods were controversial, but that is not the same as proof by contradiction being controversial!

The intuitionist movement was in full swing, which denies proof by contradiction.

But I have to admit that what I had in mind was existence proofs, which are often proofs by contradiction. Hilbert was criticized for them.
 
Hornbein said:
The intuitionist movement was in full swing, which denies proof by contradiction.

Intuitionism does not deny proof by contradiction, it denies the law of excluded middle. There is a subtle difference.
And intuitionism as we know it today was started by Brouwer as a reaction to Cantor. So it cannot be true that the intuitionist movement was in full swing. There is pre-intuitionism too, which included Borel, Poincare, Lebesgue and perhaps Kronecker. You might be referring to this. But they had no problem with the law of excluded middle.
 
micromass said:
Intuitionism does not deny proof by contradiction, it denies the law of excluded middle. There is a subtle difference.

It seems to me that proof by contradiction relies on the law of excluded middle. NOT(NOT(A)) => A. The distinction is too subtle for me.
 
How would you prove that ##\sqrt{2}## is not rational in constructivism?
 
micromass said:
How would you prove that ##\sqrt{2}## is not rational in constructivism?
Beats me. Not that I care.
 
  • #10
HallsofIvy said:
Primarily because Cantor did not express his ideas very well or very clearly. What we have now are his ideas expressed by other people in clearer and more logical terms.
Did prominent critics like Poincare, Weyl and Wittgenstein eventually turn around?
 
  • #11
micromass said:
How would you prove that ##\sqrt{2}## is not rational in constructivism?
Sorry, this thread is not about proving but about why brilliant men couldn't use reason to reach a conclusion.
 
  • #12
I know this is an old thread, but I couldn't resist:
Hornbein said:
It seems to me that proof by contradiction relies on the law of excluded middle.
This doesn't have to be true. If we define proof by contradiction as ##(\neg p \rightarrow \bot ) \models p##, then we can get there without the law of the excluded middle through the conjunction expression of a conditional. Very roughly: ##(\neg p \rightarrow \bot) \leftrightarrow (\neg(\neg p \wedge \neg\bot))##. Modus ponens gives us the right side of the biconditional, which simplifies to ##\neg(\neg p \wedge \top)##. A simple truth table shows that this expression is only valid for ##p## true.

EDIT: In fact, Wikipedia is telling me that ##\neg p## is defined as ##p \rightarrow \bot## in intuitionistic logic, so it seems that proof by contradiction is baked in at the outset (or at least my model of proof by contradiction).
 
  • #13
micromass said:
How would you prove that ##\sqrt{2}## is not rational in constructivism?
The ordinary proof is perfectly constructivistic. But I suppose that was your point.

TeethWhitener said:
This doesn't have to be true. If we define proof by contradiction as ##(\neg p \rightarrow \bot ) \models p##, then we can get there without the law of the excluded middle through the conjunction expression of a conditional. Very roughly: ##(\neg p \rightarrow \bot) \leftrightarrow (\neg(\neg p \wedge \neg\bot))##. Modus ponens gives us the right side of the biconditional, which simplifies to ##\neg(\neg p \wedge \top)##. A simple truth table shows that this expression is only valid for ##p## true.

EDIT: In fact, Wikipedia is telling me that ##\neg p## is defined as ##p \rightarrow \bot## in intuitionistic logic, so it seems that proof by contradiction is baked in at the outset (or at least my model of proof by contradiction).
The last is correct. But can't follow you before that. It is not obvious that the biconditional is valid in intutionistic logic, and truth tables cannot be used there.
 
  • #14
TeethWhitener said:
I know this is an old thread, but I couldn't resist:

This doesn't have to be true. If we define proof by contradiction as ##(\neg p \rightarrow \bot ) \models p##, then we can...

I'm sorry but could you please stay on topic?
 
  • #15
Erland said:
The last is correct. But can't follow you before that. It is not obvious that the biconditional is valid in intutionistic logic, and truth tables cannot be used there.
Sorry, in the first part I was showing that you can get proof by contradiction in classical logic without relying on excluded middle. I don't know much about intuitionistic logic. As an aside, Wiki also says you can get ##\neg(\neg p \wedge \neg\bot)## from ##\neg p \rightarrow \bot## in intuitionistic logic. Again, someone more knowledgeable can speak to this.
greswd said:
I'm sorry but could you please stay on topic?
Alright, if you insist :smile:, but I warn you, this is going to get into philosophy very quickly.
greswd said:
Sorry, this thread is not about proving but about why brilliant men couldn't use reason to reach a conclusion.
The problem here is that you're assuming there's a "right" conclusion to be drawn. You're committing the same error these brilliant men did. According to logic, there's only what can be derived from the axioms. The axioms themselves are, of course, assumed to be true. The mathematicians who rejected Cantor's results were forced to look for sets of axioms that didn't allow Cantor's claims to succeed logically. But the set of axioms you choose is true by default, and the extent to which you can reach a conclusion about which axioms are best is based more on the utility of the axioms you choose than logical truth. As a really simple example, you could choose a set of axioms that gave you an inconsistent system, and within your model the axioms would be true, but an inconsistent system is practically useless. So you could say that choosing a certain set of axioms is incorrect, or wrong, but you're basing that conclusion on extra-logical considerations.

EDIT: (and here comes the philosophy...) A lot of this hinges on equivocation between "true" as "valid within a logical framework" and some metaphysical notion of truth. These distinctions were not nearly as clear in Cantor's day as they are now, and we generally just say "valid" now to make it clear that we are referring to a truth value within a particular framework.
 
  • #16
TeethWhitener said:
Sorry, in the first part I was showing that you can get proof by contradiction in classical logic without relying on excluded middle. I don't know much about intuitionistic logic. As an aside, Wiki also says you can get ##\neg(\neg p \wedge \neg\bot)## from ##\neg p \rightarrow \bot## in intuitionistic logic. Again, someone more knowledgeable can speak to this.

Alright, if you insist :smile:, but I warn you, this is going to get into philosophy very quickly.

The problem here is that you're assuming there's a "right" conclusion to be drawn. You're committing the same error these brilliant men did. According to logic, there's only what can be derived from the axioms. The axioms themselves are, of course, assumed to be true. The mathematicians who rejected Cantor's results were forced to look for sets of axioms that didn't allow Cantor's claims to succeed logically. But the set of axioms you choose is true by default, and the extent to which you can reach a conclusion about which axioms are best is based more on the utility of the axioms you choose than logical truth. As a really simple example, you could choose a set of axioms that gave you an inconsistent system, and within your model the axioms would be true, but an inconsistent system is practically useless. So you could say that choosing a certain set of axioms is incorrect, or wrong, but you're basing that conclusion on extra-logical considerations.

EDIT: (and here comes the philosophy...) A lot of this hinges on equivocation between "true" as "valid within a logical framework" and some metaphysical notion of truth. These distinctions were not nearly as clear in Cantor's day as they are now, and we generally just say "valid" now to make it clear that we are referring to a truth value within a particular framework.
So wait, Cantor introduced new axioms?
 
  • #17
greswd said:
So wait, Cantor introduced new axioms?

No, Cantor didn't think axiomatically.
 
  • #18
greswd said:
So wait, Cantor introduced new axioms?
micromass said:
No, Cantor didn't think axiomatically.
Cantor himself might not have thought axiomatically (I don't know; I'm not a historian), but his work and the controversy surrounding it is probably the major reason why people in the late 19th/early 20th century hammered on axiomatic thinking so much.
 
  • #19
Infinity is a mind-boggling concept, especially the first time you run into it. Some mathematicians of Cantor's time had a lot of trouble thinking about an infinity the way that Cantor did (and that modern mathematicians do) because they were familiar only with infinity as a "process", like for example in the definition of a sequence of points approaching a limit.

Also, because an axiomatic set theory had not yet been developed, *some* of Cantor's discoveries rested on a weak foundation. Wikipedia explains that in particular, his discovery of the cardinal numbersthe series of alephs — was flawed for this reason. I would say flawed, but still utterly brilliant in its departure from what was then conventional in mathematics.

Yet the mathematician David Hilbert — who around 1900 was widely considered the best mathematician in the world — strongly supported Cantor's work, as did most mathematicians of the 20th century. After all, it is entirely reasonable to ask whether there exists a one-to-one correspondence between two sets, such as the integers and the real numbers.
 
  • #20
Hornbein said:
His main enemy was Kronecker. K thought that infinity was a bogus concept, so naturally he didn't like what Cantor was up to. At the time even proof by contradiction was controversial.

This is from the Wikipedia article on Kronecker

"He criticized Cantor's work on set theory, and was quoted by Weber (1893) as having said, "Die ganzen Zahlen hat der liebe Gott gemacht, alles andere ist Menschenwerk" ("God made the integers, all else is the work of man.")."

This is from the Wikipedia article on Cantor

"The objections to Cantor's work were occasionally fierce: Henri Poincaré referred to his ideas as a "grave disease" infecting the discipline of mathematics,[8] and Leopold Kronecker's public opposition and personal attacks included describing Cantor as a "scientific charlatan", a "renegade" and a "corrupter of youth."[9] Kronecker objected to Cantor's proofs that the algebraic numbers are countable, and that the transcendental numbers are uncountable, results now included in a standard mathematics curriculum."

and further down in the Wikipedia article

"Mathematicians from three major schools of thought (constructivism and its two offshoots, intuitionism and finitism) opposed Cantor's theories in this matter. For constructivists such as Kronecker, this rejection of actual infinity stems from fundamental disagreement with the idea that nonconstructive proofs such as Cantor's diagonal argument are sufficient proof that something exists, holding instead that constructive proofs are required. Intuitionism also rejects the idea that actual infinity is an expression of any sort of reality, but arrive at the decision via a different route than constructivism. Firstly, Cantor's argument rests on logic to prove the existence of transfinite numbers as an actual mathematical entity, whereas intuitionists hold that mathematical entities cannot be reduced to logical propositions, originating instead in the intuitions of the mind.[8] Secondly, the notion of infinity as an expression of reality is itself disallowed in intuitionism, since the human mind cannot intuitively construct an infinite set.[59] Mathematicians such as Brouwer and especially Poincaré adopted an intuitionist stance against Cantor's work. Citing the paradoxes of set theory as an example of its fundamentally flawed nature, Poincaré held that "most of the ideas of Cantorian set theory should be banished from mathematics once and for all."[8] Finally, Wittgenstein's attacks were finitist: he believed that Cantor's diagonal argument conflated the intension of a set of cardinal or real numbers with its extension, thus conflating the concept of rules for generating a set with an actual set.[10]"
 
Last edited:
  • #21
Also from the Wikipedia article on Cantor(see post #20)

"Some Christian theologians saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God.[6] In particular, Neo-Thomist thinkers saw the existence of an actual infinity that consisted of something other than God as jeopardizing "God's exclusive claim to supreme infinity".[60] Cantor strongly believed that this view was a misinterpretation of infinity, and was convinced that set theory could help correct this mistake:"

From the Wikipedia article on "actual infinity:

"Actual infinity is the idea that numbers, or some other type of mathematical object, can form an actual, completed totality; namely, a set. Hence, in the philosophy of mathematics, the abstractionof actual infinity involves the acceptance of infinite entities, such as the set of all natural numbers or an infinite sequence of rational numbers, as given objects. This is contrasted with potential infinity, in which a non-terminating process (such as "add 1 to the previous number") produces an unending "infinite" sequence of results, but each individual result is finite and is achieved in a finite number of steps."

At core in all of the criticisms of Cantor's theory seems to be the denial that an infinity could actually exist - except perhaps God .

It would seem that these ideas must deny the existence of limits since a limit is a completed infinity - by definition. E.G. the number 1 is the completion of all Cauchy sequences that converge to 1.
 
Last edited:
  • #22
lavinia said:
Also from the Wikipedia article on Cantor(see post #20)

"Some Christian theologians saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God.[6] In particular, Neo-Thomist thinkers saw the existence of an actual infinity that consisted of something other than God as jeopardizing "God's exclusive claim to supreme infinity."

This seems to show that Cantor's theory was misunderstood since there is no largest infinite set and even if there were a supreme infinite, it may not be unique.

For instance, one might try to resurrect St. Anselm's proof of the existence of God using set theory with the following argument.

The set containing all sets of virtues is partially ordered by inclusion. Given any chain of sets of virtues, the union of the sets in the chain is also a set of virtues so every chain has a maximal element. The Hausdorff Maximal Principle now asserts that there exists a set of virtues for which there is none greater. This is Anselm's God.

Sadly, this maximal element may not be unique and also the collection of all sets of virtues may be too big to be a set.
 
Last edited:
  • #23
TeethWhitener said:
Cantor himself might not have thought axiomatically (I don't know; I'm not a historian), but his work and the controversy surrounding it is probably the major reason why people in the late 19th/early 20th century hammered on axiomatic thinking so much.

ultimately, what was the resolution to Cantor's controversy?

Did these opposing great men of mathematics eventually stop their opposition?
 
  • #24
Most mathematicians and people who use mathematics in their everyday work have accepted the existence of infinities. Yes, Cantor's set theory did give rise to axiomatic set theory, particularly in light of paradoxes like Russell's paradox. (Which is: Let X be the set of all sets not containing themselves. Then X cannot contain itself, for then it would have to not contain itself. But X also cannot not contain itself, for then it would have to contain itself.)

A number of axiom systems for set theory were proposed, and the one that is almost universally accepted these days is ZFC, which stands for Zermelo-Frankel plus Axiom of Choice: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zermelo–Fraenkel_set_theory.

Some, but not many, mathematicians are Intuitionists or Constructivists today and continue to resist the idea of infinity.
 
Last edited:
  • #25
zinq said:
Most mathematicians and people who use mathematics in their everyday work have accepted the existence of infinities. Yes, Cantor's set theory did give rise to axiomatic set theory, particularly in light of paradoxes like Russell's paradox. (Which is: Let X be the set of all sets not containing themselves. Then X cannot contain itself, for then it would have to not contain itself. But X also cannot not contain itself, for then it would have to contain itself.)

A number of axioms for set theory were proposed, and the one that is most widely accepted these days is ZFC, which stands for Zermelo-Frankel plus Axiom of Choice: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Zermelo–Fraenkel_set_theory.

Some, but not many, mathematicians are Intuitionists or Constructivists today and continue to resist the idea of infinity.
What about opposers like Wittgenstein, Weyl and Poincare?

That's so amazing. I didn't know that mathematics still had such a conundrum. I thought there was only one right answer. LOL
 
  • #26
greswd said:
What about opposers like Wittgenstein, Weyl and Poincare?

That's so amazing. I didn't know that mathematics still had such a conundrum. I thought there was only one right answer. LOL
There is only one right answer, but all don't agree what it is! :smile:
 
  • Like
Likes Samy_A
  • #27
Erland said:
There is only one right answer, but all don't agree what it is! :smile:

But how come?
 
  • #28
greswd said:
But how come?
I was actaully kidding a little :wink: but not entirely... But you deserve a more serious reply...

If you adopt the platonist viewpoint, there is only one answer to every question

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Philosophy_of_mathematics#Platonism

but we might not be able to find it or prove it. Also, not all mathematicians are platonists.

For example, take the Continuum hypothesis. This can neither be proved or disproved from the axioms of set theory (ZFC or NBG), provided that the theory is consistent. Still, a platonist would argue that it must be either true or false in an absolute sense, as a description of a true mathematical universe, just that we cannot know which it is, at least not just using the axioms of ZFC or NBG.
A non-platonist would not agree, and say that the issue of its truth or falsity is not meaningful in an absolute sense.

Who is right? Can we know that?
 
  • #29
Erland said:
a platonist would argue that it must be either true or false in an absolute sense, as a description of a true mathematical universe, just that we cannot know which it is, at least not just using the axioms of ZFC or NBG.
A non-platonist would not agree, and say that the issue of its truth or falsity is not meaningful in an absolute sense.

do you know what happened to accomplished mathematicians but prominent opposers to Cantor like Wittgenstein, Weyl and Poincare?
 
  • #30
greswd said:
do you know what happened to accomplished mathematicians but prominent opposers to Cantor like Wittgenstein, Weyl and Poincare?
I wasn't aware that anything in particular happened to them.
 
  • #31
Erland said:
I wasn't aware that anything in particular happened to them.
they opposed Cantor vehemently, I wonder if they ever changed their minds about it
 
  • #32
greswd said:
they opposed Cantor vehemently, I wonder if they ever changed their minds about it
No, sorry, I don't know anything more about that than what can be found on the net.
 
  • #33
  • #34
One speculation about why mathematicians of Cantor's era would tend to be anti-Cantor is that they had only recently gotten calculus on a reliable footing by eliminating the notion of infinity as an isolated concept. For example, if we look at rigorous definitions of the form "The limit of [something] as [something else] approaches infinity", such definitions do not contain any definition of "infinity" as an isolated concept. Nor do they contain any definition of "approaches". The phrases being defined suggest that they have some common language interpretation where individual nouns and verbs have an independent meaning, but the rigorous definitions do not define each word involved. The rigorous definitions replace any independent notion of "infinity" by using quantifiers such as "for each" and "there exists".
 
  • #35
greswd said:
they opposed Cantor vehemently, I wonder if they ever changed their minds about it

As far as I know, Wittgenstein never changed his mind regarding his finitism (if I'm not mistaken, he only accepted as legitimate a very weak form of arithmetic known as Primitive Recursive Arithmetic); similarly, I don't think Poincaré changed his mind about his "intuitionism", which, incidentally, should be sharply distinguished from Brouwer's. As for Weyl, although he came to embrace Brouwer's views for some time (much to Hilbert's chagrin), he did change his mind about it. The thing is, at the beginning of the movement, it seemed that one could get very far with the simple intuitionistic tools at one's disposal. It quickly became clear, however, that restricting analysis to what can only be accomplished by intuitionistic methods was a very restrictive move (just an example: the intermediate value theorem is not a theorem in an intuitionistic setting). In particular, it seems that Weyl's work on theoretical physics convinced him of the need to go beyond intuitionistically acceptable methods, so he ended up (more or less) accepting Hilbert's point of view.
 
  • #36
It was not so long ago (18th century) that some mathematicians frowned on negative numbers... Some thought they did not exist and should not be used (e.g., Francis Maseres, William Friend) ; others thought they could be used if they appeared during a calculation if they subsequently disappeared before the calculation was completed.
 
  • #37
Mathematicians look for consistency amongst abstraction (or variation).

In order to do this though the abstraction in its largest form has to be considered and this has happened many times.

One good example is differential geometry.

It was thought that flat geometry was the only geometry. Even those who working on it (like Gauss) kept it secret and Gauss had political clout in the community.

Cantor is no different to what many other leaps of faith in mathematics are - he basically considered something beyond what was considered to be only (or likely) consistent and eventually mathematicians came around to see that it could be (or was).

Same with complex numbers.

Same with higher dimensional algebras.

It's the same story again and again - basically what is assumed to be consistent in its entirety is found out to be wrong and a new form of abstraction is discovered.

Cantor was a victim of this mentality just like many other mathematicians who promoted abstraction beyond what was considered possible and consistent have experienced and it probably (unfortunately) won't be the last.
 
  • #38
chiro said:
Mathematicians look for consistency amongst abstraction (or variation).

In order to do this though the abstraction in its largest form has to be considered and this has happened many times.

One good example is differential geometry.

It was thought that flat geometry was the only geometry. Even those who working on it (like Gauss) kept it secret and Gauss had political clout in the community.

Cantor is no different to what many other leaps of faith in mathematics are - he basically considered something beyond what was considered to be only (or likely) consistent and eventually mathematicians came around to see that it could be (or was).

Same with complex numbers.

Same with higher dimensional algebras.

It's the same story again and again - basically what is assumed to be consistent in its entirety is found out to be wrong and a new form of abstraction is discovered.

Cantor was a victim of this mentality just like many other mathematicians who promoted abstraction beyond what was considered possible and consistent have experienced and it probably (unfortunately) won't be the last.

do you know what happened to all the mathematicians who opposed Cantor? when did his ideas get mainstream acceptance?
 
  • #39
greswd said:
do you know what happened to all the mathematicians who opposed Cantor? when did his ideas get mainstream acceptance?

About those opposed to Cantorian set theory, I gave you a (partial?) answer in post #35; do you have any further questions about that?

As for when Cantor's ideas became mainstream, I'd say probably in the 30's, when it became clear the limits of logic set theory in general (due to Gödel's theorems). One nice indication of this shift is Tarski's 1935 postscript to his 1933 paper on truth. In the 1933 paper, Tarski still worked inside the framework of (roughly Russellian) type theory, with the restrictions imposed by that (noticed that the 1933 paper was actually written during 1929-1931, so before Gödel published his results). In the postscript, however, he indicates that he now prefers to work inside a framework which accepts the transfinite hierarchy and which is thus much closer to Cantorian set-theory. This is indicative that in the early to mid 30's, Cantorian set theory, formalized as a first-order theory, became much more mainstream.

What occasioned this shift? There are a number of factors here. Certainly, one important factor was the recognition of first-order logic as an ideal framework for such theories. Today, it's common to present ZFC in a first-order theory, so that we often forget the fact that, when Zermelo proposed his axioms in 1908, his preferred framework was second-order logic----indeed, until Weyl's and Hilbert's work in the 1910's, almost nobody saw a clear distinction between first and second order logic (take a look, e.g., at Frege's Begriffsschrift from 1879, where there's no distinction between first and second order instantiation). Even Skolem's defense of first-order logic in the early 1920's was met with skepticism. So it seems that it was only after Gödel's groundbreaking work that first-order gained in prominence, which also paved the way for a more systematic investigation of Cantorian set theory.

Other important factors were the results of investigations, by Tarski, von Neumann, Zermelo, and others, into the consequences of adopting a Cantorian framework. For instance, we now take for granted the von Neumann ordinals and transfinite recursion, but before von Neumann formulated these in the 1920's, there wasn't any rigorous theory of the ordinals and their properties. Similarly, the discovery by Tarski and others of several equivalents to the Axiom of Choice certainly made it easier for others to swallow it, specially when it was discovered that many who opposed it actually employed it implicitly in their work. Relatedly, classical descriptive set theory was just being born, with the impressive results by Lebsegue, Lusin, Suslin, and others on analytic and Borel sets. Together, these developments established set theory as an important tool in the investigation of classical mathematical areas, such as analysis and topology.

Finally, I'd also add that Gödel's work on the independence of the Continuum Hypothesis and the Axiom of Choice from ZFC (and other theories such as NBG) were also crucial in establishing set theory as an important area of investigation in its own right. They showed that set theory was not only a rich tool to be used, but also a field with its own questions and research program (e.g. inner model theory). So, by 1939, when Gödel announced his results, I'd say that Cantorian set theory was firmly established as a solid and mature research program. Considering how young it was by then, that's certainly an impressive feat!

Incidentally, if you're interested in pursuing these issues in depth, I'd strongly recommend that you read José Ferreirós's Labyrinths of Thought, a very detailed and comprehensive account of the development of set theory.
 
  • #40
Thanks for the comprehensive and informative response.

Nagase said:
About those opposed to Cantorian set theory, I gave you a (partial?) answer in post #35; do you have any further questions about that?
I wanted to ask chiro what he knows about the issue.

It is sad that a very brilliant mind like Poincare never came around to Cantor's ideas.
 
  • #41
I'm not sure on specifics but usually what happens is when something reaches "political critical mass" (meaning enough people accept something to make it popular enough to be considered and then eventually verified) it gains the "main-stream" acceptance.

This happens all the time and you see it with all kinds of people from Galileo to Kepler and even people like Grassmann and Cantor (who both had ideas who were opposed for various reasons).

This is what politics does - people with political clout decide things (even if they shouldn't) because they have political clout.

Even mathematics, science, and engineering have politics and this often stops progress of many sorts from happening at the pace it should ideally happen at.

The thread has said that Cantor had supporters (like Hilbert) but in mathematics people have to reach political critical mass to take it seriously and then decide whether they want to individually verify the ideas and this is what is needed for adoption in mathematics - basically enough "votes" from people independently going through it and verifying what is being proven.
 
Back
Top