How do entanglement experiments benefit from QFT (over QM)?

In summary, the conversation discusses two important points: the first being the difference between QFT and quantum mechanics (QM) and the second being the role of QFT in analyzing entanglement experiments. QFT is a more comprehensive theory than QM, and while it is commonly used in quantum optics papers, it is not often referenced in experimental papers on entanglement. The main reason for this is that QFT is primarily used when dealing with particle-number changing processes, which are not relevant in most entanglement experiments. In addition, while QFT helps to understand how entanglement should not be explained, it does not provide a significant advantage in explaining entanglement itself, and discussions of entanglement often focus on photons due to
  • #211
Mentz114 said:
The things I'm talking about are not hidden variables. Pressure, temperature, momentum and energy are and actual stuff are dynamic variables that drive the universe, not probabilities.
Fine, but if you try to explain the dynamical evolution with them you will need nonlocality, retro/acausality or multiple worlds.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #212
DarMM said:
Fine, but if you try to explain the dynamical evolution with them you will need nonlocality, retro/acausality or multiple worlds.
A point of agreement ! I believe the non-locality required is present in all physics where spatial translational invariance is present. Unless a finite limit is placed on terms like [itex]|\mathbf{x}_1-\mathbf{x}_2|^{2}[/itex] there is manifest non-locality.
 
  • Like
Likes Auto-Didact
  • #213
DarMM said:
By "determined value" I assume you mean that there will be an observable with a completely predictable outcome, not "already has that value prior to measurement" in line with your agnosticism on the issue.
A value is determined, when an accurate measurement leads to a certain value (in the spectrum of the representing operator) with 100% probability.
In a sense yes and no.

A quantum state is a sort of a pre-ensemble (not a standard term, I'm just not sure how to phrase it), Robert Griffiths often uses the phrase "pre-probability". When provided with a context, the state together with the observables of that context will define an ensemble.
Perhaps I miss some subtlety here, but for me the state preparation defines probabilities for the outcome of measurements. As a frequentist I think probabilities describe an ensemble, and in this sense a quantum state represents an ensemble of equally prepared systems.
A basic property of an ensemble is something like the total law of probability which says that if I have two observables to measure on the ensemble ##A## and ##B## with outcomes ##A_{i}## and ##B_{i}##, the for a given ##A## outcome:
$$
P\left(A_{i}\right) = \sum_{j}P\left(A_{i} | B_{j}\right)P\left(B_{j}\right)
$$
which just reflects that ##A## and ##B## and their outcomes just partition the ensemble differently. This fails in Quantum Theory and is one of the ways in which it departs from classical probability. Thus quantum observables cannot be seen as being drawn from the same ensemble.

Thus to define an ensemble in QM you have to give the state and the context of observables, not the state alone.

Streater explains it well in Chapter 6 of his text, as does Griffith in Chapter 5 of his Consistent Quantum Theory. There are explanations in Quantum Probability texts, but I think you'd prefer those books.
I guess you talk about two incompatible observables A and B, which usually cannot be measured simultaneously in the sense of ideal (complete) von Neumann measurements. The impossibility of such measurements and corresponding preparations is indeed the main difference between classical and quantum physics.
 
  • #214
vanhees71 said:
A value is determined, when an accurate measurement leads to a certain value (in the spectrum of the representing operator) with 100% probability
Certainly, but I assume you don't think the system actually possesses such a value prior to measurement. It's just certain to produce a given outcome upon measurement.

vanhees71 said:
Perhaps I miss some subtlety here, but for me the state preparation defines probabilities for the outcome of measurements. As a frequentist I think probabilities describe an ensemble, and in this sense a quantum state represents an ensemble of equally prepared systems
The state preparations define the probabilities for future measurements, but these probabilities do not satisfy the conditions of a statistical model/ensemble unless one selects a context. A quantum state cannot be thought of as an ensemble.

vanhees71 said:
The impossibility of such measurements and corresponding preparations is indeed the main difference between classical and quantum physics.
It's not, you can have classical theories with non-commutativity and observables that are impossible to measure simultaneously.

The main difference is that in such a classical theory all observables and their outcomes can be thought of as alternate partitions of a single ensemble and thus the state can be thought of as an ensemble.
 
Last edited:
  • #215
vanhees71 said:
Perhaps I miss some subtlety here, but for me the state preparation defines probabilities for the outcome of measurements. As a frequentist I think probabilities describe an ensemble, and in this sense a quantum state represents an ensemble of equally prepared systems.
The sublety is more apparent in a simpler experimental setting:

Suppose you prepare completely unpolarized light.

It in the first experiment you pass it through polarizers polarizing it horizontally and vertically. According to Born's rule, the subsequently observed photon counting probabilities add up to 1, hence you would conclude that the original ensemble has been split into two subensembles of linearly polarized photons.

It in the second experiment you pass it through polarizers polarizing it left circularly and right circularly. According to Born's rule, the subsequently observed photon counting probabilities add up to 1, hence you would conclude that the original ensemble has been split into two subensembles of circularly polarized photons.

But the original ensemble cannot simultaneously be an ensemble consisting of linearly polarized photons and an ensemble consisting of circularly polarized photons. Thus a polarizer cannot be said to select a subensemble but must be said to create a new ensemble!

This is meant by having disjoint samle spaces, depending on the experimental setup.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and vanhees71
  • #216
Mentz114 said:
A point of agreement ! I believe the non-locality required is present in all physics where spatial translational invariance is present. Unless a finite limit is placed on terms like [itex]|\mathbf{x}_1-\mathbf{x}_2|^{2}[/itex] there is manifest non-locality.
Fully agree. To use another example from physics, the Navier-Stokes equation is manifestly nonlocal in almost exactly the same way as QT; the only proven methodology to understand the causes and effects of this type of manifest nonlocality so far is by approaching Navier-Stokes from a dynamical systems theorist perspective, i.e. not as a dynamical system per se but studying the equation using the most sophisticated technical non-perturbative tools available in the practice of applied mathematics, i.e. the tools of the modern dynamical systems theorist. This methodology, from a structuralist history of physics perspective, is the natural structural evolution of the portfolio of pure mathematical tools of the theoretical physicist. Experience has taught us that the conceptual problems of nonlocality and nonlinearity seem to be quite deeply intertwined at a pure mathematics level.
A. Neumaier said:
Your arguments are also full of assumptions solely based on your faith, none of them verifiable.
To answer you more directly, @A. Neumaier: the successfulness of applying dynamical systems methodology onto both complicated empirical phenomena and pure mathematics - even subjects which were deemed 'clearly' non-dynamical - is where my 'unfounded faith' is based upon; I am not the originator of such ideas for even Heisenberg said it himself [Heisenberg 1967]. The naive perspective of something being 'clearly non-dynamical and therefore should not be approached by dynamical methods' has more often than not in STEM and beyond turned out to be about as true as Euclid's parallel postulate is; once there is sufficient recognition that the naive perspective is actually completely contingent it gets reduced to an axiom which can and will be removed once deemed necessary, creating an entirely new form of mathematics in the process - fully analogous to the creation of non-Euclidean geometry by ditching Euclid's parallel postulate.
 
  • #217
Mentz114 said:
A point of agreement ! I believe the non-locality required is present in all physics where spatial translational invariance is present. Unless a finite limit is placed on terms like [itex]|\mathbf{x}_1-\mathbf{x}_2|^{2}[/itex] there is manifest non-locality.
Bear in mind then that the Kochen-Specker theorem says that such a nonlocal account must be contextual and Hardy's theorem demonstrates that in such an account a given system must have an infinite number of dynamical degrees of freedom.
 
  • #218
DarMM said:
Bear in mind then that the Kochen-Specker theorem says that such a nonlocal account must be contextual and Hardy's theorem demonstrates that in such an account a given system must have an infinite number of dynamical degrees of freedom.
I am hearing two necessary requirements:
1) contextuality
2) an infinite dimensional state space

Abramsky already demonstrated that the former can be treated using sheaf theory, while the latter requires functional analysis.

A naive reply from my part would be that a pure mathematical cross between Morse theory - a methodology from nonlinear functional analysis - and Grothendieck's sheaf cohomology should be able to achieve what is needed.
 
  • Like
Likes DarMM
  • #219
A. Neumaier said:
The sublety is more apparent in a simpler experimental setting:

Suppose you prepare completely unpolarized light.

It in the first experiment you pass it through polarizers polarizing it horizontally and vertically. According to Born's rule, the subsequently observed photon counting probabilities add up to 1, hence you would conclude that the original ensemble has been split into two subensembles of linearly polarized photons.

It in the second experiment you pass it through polarizers polarizing it left circularly and right circularly. According to Born's rule, the subsequently observed photon counting probabilities add up to 1, hence you would conclude that the original ensemble has been split into two subensembles of circularly polarized photons.

But the original ensemble cannot simultaneously be an ensemble consisting of linearly polarized photons and an ensemble consisting of circularly polarized photons. Thus a polarizer cannot be said to select a subensemble but must be said to create a new ensemble!

This is meant by having disjoint samle spaces, depending on the experimental setup.
Sure, I've never claimed something else. It depends on the selection, i.e. the measurement used to select, into which subensembles you sort a given ensemble. Of course, I don't claim that before the measurement the photons had the properties measured. The only properties a system has is described by the state it is prepared in, and these properties are probabilities for outcomes of measurements.
 
  • #220
vanhees71 said:
It depends on the selection, i.e. the measurement used to select, into which subensembles you sort a given ensemble
Indeed the measurement outcomes sort the ensemble into subensembles.

However it's the state and the measurement choice together that define the ensemble in the quantum case. The state alone does not define an ensemble unlike in classical probability. Quantum observables are not alternate partitions of a common ensemble, but define alternate ensembles.
 
  • #221
DarMM said:
Indeed the measurement outcomes sort the ensemble into subensembles.

However it's the state and the measurement choice together that define the ensemble in the quantum case. The state alone does not define an ensemble unlike in classical probability. Quantum observables are not alternate partitions of a common ensemble, but define alternate ensembles.

But the Bohmian case shows that the ensemble and subensembles can be defined before the measurement.
 
  • #222
This formulation I find very confusing. For me a state represents operationally a preparation procedure. With this preparation procedure you create a well-defined ensemble. On this ensemble you can perform whatever measurement is possible. Then you can define subensembles by sorting them out dependent on the outcomes of these measurements. Of course, these subensembles are not predetermined as for a deterministic classical system. The QT randomness is not like classical randomness due to incomplete knowledge about the system (like the initial conditions of a die to predict the outcome when throwing it) but is a property of the system itself.
 
  • #223
atyy said:
But the Bohmian case shows that the ensemble and subensembles can be defined before the measurement.
In Bohmian Mechanics there is a single sample space, so indeed you can.
 
  • #224
vanhees71 said:
With this preparation procedure you create a well-defined ensemble
You don't. That's a mathematical fact of the formalism. A preparation and a context give a well-defined ensemble, not a preparation alone. In a classical theory a preparation alone creates a well defined ensemble.
 
  • #225
But the preparation does not predetermine what I measure. I can still choose any physically possible measurement. Which mathematical fact are you referring to?

In other words, why doesn't the preparation of a proton beam in the LHC define an ensemble of protons?
 
  • #226
DarMM said:
In Bohmian Mechanics there is a single sample space, so indeed you can.

But if BM is consistent with the minimal interpretation, then it would seem that one can also have subensembles defined before the measurement in the minimal interpretation (ie. the minimal interpretation doesn't force us to accept that the subensembles are chosen by the measurement).
 
  • #227
You cannot define subensembles before the measurement. This doesn't make sense at all, not even in classical physics: To create subensembles you must somehow choose them, i.e., you must sort the subensembles using some criterion, i.e., you have to observe something to choose the subensembles.
 
  • #228
vanhees71 said:
It depends on the selection, i.e. the measurement used to select, into which subensembles you sort a given ensemble.
To call it subensembles is misleading terminology.
vanhees71 said:
The only properties a system has is described by the state it is prepared in, and these properties are probabilities for outcomes of measurements.
By this definition it is a transformation of the original ensemble, of the same kind as when you apply a rotator in place of a polarizer.
 
  • Like
Likes Auto-Didact
  • #229
vanhees71 said:
For me a state represents operationally a preparation procedure. With this preparation procedure you create a well-defined ensemble.
vanhees71 said:
why doesn't the preparation of a proton beam in the LHC define an ensemble of protons?
According to your definition it only defines a state. DarMM says that states and ensembles are not synonymous. Why else would one use two different names for it? It seems that you and DarMM use the same term with a completely different meaning!
vanhees71 said:
You cannot define subensembles before the measurement. This doesn't make sense at all, not even in classical physics: To create subensembles you must somehow choose them, i.e., you must sort the subensembles using some criterion, i.e., you have to observe something to choose the subensembles.
How do you define ensembles on a precise/formal level?
 
  • #230
atyy said:
But the Bohmian case shows that the ensemble and subensembles can be defined before the measurement.
atyy said:
But if BM is consistent with the minimal interpretation, then it would seem that one can also have subensembles defined before the measurement in the minimal interpretation (ie. the minimal interpretation doesn't force us to accept that the subensembles are chosen by the measurement).
This is because additional hidden variables are posited. BM is not a minimal interpretation. The ensemble is determined in @vanhees71 version of the minimal interpretation by the state alone, but in BM by the state plus the position assignments. The latter provide the additional preferred basis mentioned by DarMM.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and Auto-Didact
  • #231
atyy said:
But if BM is consistent with the minimal interpretation, then it would seem that one can also have subensembles defined before the measurement in the minimal interpretation (ie. the minimal interpretation doesn't force us to accept that the subensembles are chosen by the measurement).
@A. Neumaier has stated this already but Bohmian Mechanics is adding additional variables which restore the ability to speak of a single ensemble. This makes its probability theory quite different from that of the quantum formalism.

So if Bohmian Mechanics is correct and its additional variables exist then the ensemble (note: not subensemble) is defined prior to a choice of measurement.

As an analogy in a similar "minimal" interpretation of Newtonian Mechanics one could say that you aren't forced to say spacetime isn't Lorentzian. However clearly in the theory itself spacetimes are not Lorentzian. Ultimately one could minimally interpret any theory in a sense to leave open completely different structures and truths that hold in a yet undiscovered completion.

Similarly the actual mathematical structure of QM literally does not have ensembles well-defined prior to a measurement choice, that's part of its actual mathematical structure and the statistics of real experiments do not act in accord with the notion of an ensemble defined from preparation alone.

Bohmian Mechanics as a different theory which would constitute a completion of QM would allow such a pre-defined ensemble notion. However the formalism and experimental results we currently have do not.
 
  • Informative
Likes Auto-Didact
  • #232
vanhees71 said:
But the preparation does not predetermine what I measure. I can still choose any physically possible measurement
Correct and the quantum formalism does not give a well-defined ensemble until this choice is specified.

vanhees71 said:
Which mathematical fact are you referring to?
The deviation of QM from Kolomogorov's probability theory as shown in for example the violations of the total law of probability.
 
  • #233
DarMM said:
@A. Neumaier has stated this already but Bohmian Mechanics is adding additional variables which restore the ability to speak of a single ensemble. This makes its probability theory quite different from that of the quantum formalism.

So if Bohmian Mechanics is correct and its additional variables exist then the ensemble (note: not subensemble) is defined prior to a choice of measurement.

As an analogy in a similar "minimal" interpretation of Newtonian Mechanics one could say that you aren't forced to say spacetime isn't Lorentzian. However clearly in the theory itself spacetimes are not Lorentzian. Ultimately one could minimally interpret any theory in a sense to leave open completely different structures and truths that hold in a yet undiscovered completion.

Similarly the actual mathematical structure of QM literally does not have ensembles well-defined prior to a measurement choice, that's part of its actual mathematical structure and the statistics of real experiments do not act in accord with the notion of an ensemble defined from preparation alone.

Bohmian Mechanics as a different theory which would constitute a completion of QM would allow such a pre-defined ensemble notion. However the formalism and experimental results we currently have do not.

Yes, what I mean is that the minimal interpretation does not say that ensembles and subsensembles cannot be defined, rather that it does not define a unique ensemble.
 
  • #234
A. Neumaier said:
To call it subensembles is misleading terminology.

By this definition it is a transformation of the original ensemble, of the same kind as when you apply a rotator in place of a polarizer.
Ok, I'll cancel "subensemble" in this sense from my vocabulary.

I found it useful to describe situations like the delayed-choice experiments, like the entanglement-swapping experiments.

There you prepare two polarization entangled photon pairs, which themselves are unentangled and then by performing a local Bell measurement with two photons with both photons from the two different pairs. One just needs to make a measurement protocol and then after the measurement (in this case literaly "after the fact") you can choose each of the four possible Bell states the two other photons are in without having ever been in common local interactions with any device. I called these four selections "subensembles", but it's perhaps indeed misleading, because the original ensemble is of course destroyed completely by the measurement process.
 
  • #235
A. Neumaier said:
According to your definition it only defines a state. DarMM says that states and ensembles are not synonymous. Why else would one use two different names for it? It seems that you and DarMM use the same term with a completely different meaning!

How do you define ensembles on a precise/formal level?
The problem of mutual understanding between us is that I think in terms of physics and you in terms of mathematics. As I said the physics logic for me is the following. First there are states and observables, and these have to be clearly distinguished.

On the physical operational level a state is a preparation procedure or, to put it mathematically, an equivalence class of preparation procedures. In my example the LHC is a "preparation machine" for (unpolarized) proton beams with a quite well-defined momentum and energy. These beams are prepared such that they collide in specific points along the beam line. For me the preparation procedure delivers a well-defined ensemble of colliding proton beams.

On the physical operational level an observable is (an equivalence class of) a measurement procedure. In my example you can define any kind of observable on "colliding proton beams". At the LHC these are given by the various detectors. An observable would, e.g., be the ##p_T## spectrum of charged particles or an invariant-mass spectrum of electron-positron pairs (dileptons) etc. etc.

It is important to note that the measurement is independent of the preparation, i.e., no matter how you prepare your system you can always perform any sensible measurement on it, e.g., preparing a proton beam with well-defined momentum you can always measure very precisely the position of the proton (or the proton distribution in the proton bunch). This is important to interpret, e.g., the uncertainty relation right (Heisenberg got it wrong at first and was corrected by Bohr): It's not describing the impossibility to measure position and momentum accurately at the same time but it describes the impossibility to prepare a particle with well-defined position and momentum simultaneously.

The mathematical formulation we have discussed very often, and I don't think that we differ much concerning it. Of course, I refer to the idealized measurements. In mathematical language, these are the projective measurements, which are clearly a subset of the more general POVMs.

Concerning the latter, in all the nice mathematical sources you quoted not a single one gives a clear physical description of a POVM measurement of position or the "fuzzy common measurement of position and momentum" (as I'd translate what seems to be intended by the very abstract formulations of the POVM formalism I've seen so far).
 
  • #236
DarMM said:
Correct and the quantum formalism does not give a well-defined ensemble until this choice is specified.The deviation of QM from Kolomogorov's probability theory as shown in for example the violations of the total law of probability.
Well, obviously we just have a different understanding of "ensemble" (see my previous posting of #235). For me it's sufficient to specify the state by some preparation procedure. The state provides probability distributions for the outcome of any sensible experiment you can do on the so prepared system. Of course the complete description of the random experiment you need to specify also the measurement (if I understand it right nowadays in the most general sense formally by a POVM).

What do you mean by "the total law of probability"? To my understanding for any completely defined measurement the probabilities fulfill the Kolmogorov axioms (at least for the standard projector valued measurement formalism in textbooks).
 
  • #237
atyy said:
Yes, what I mean is that the minimal interpretation does not say that ensembles and subsensembles cannot be defined, rather that it does not define a unique ensemble.
I assume the "it" is refers to the state. Well a state ##\rho## and a context ##\left\{A_{i}\right\}## define an ensemble under some Gelfand map ##G##. So in this sense an ensemble is not defined until you have a state and a context.

However this has nothing to do with Bohmian Mechanics, I'm not sure how it changes this statement.
 
  • #238
vanhees71 said:
Well, obviously we just have a different understanding of "ensemble" (see my previous posting of #235). For me it's sufficient to specify the state by some preparation procedure. The state provides probability distributions for the outcome of any sensible experiment you can do on the so prepared system. Of course the complete description of the random experiment you need to specify also the measurement (if I understand it right nowadays in the most general sense formally by a POVM).
The state can be specified by a preparation procedure yes. However the state does not define an ensemble, only a state and a measurement choice.

vanhees71 said:
For me the preparation procedure delivers a well-defined ensemble of colliding proton beams
It doesn't. It is in a sense a pre-ensemble. One simply needs to look at the statistical properties of various measurements upon the preparation to see this.

vanhees71 said:
What do you mean by "the total law of probability"?
I gave it in #207

vanhees71 said:
To my understanding for any completely defined measurement the probabilities fulfill the Kolmogorov axioms
Yes for a defined measurement choice and a preparation procedure the probabilities obey Kolomogorov's axioms. However the probabilities of various observables considered together do not. In essence QM is a bunch of entwined Kolmogorov theories.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and mattt
  • #239
DarMM said:
I assume the "it" is refers to the state. Well a state ##\rho## and a context ##\left\{A_{i}\right\}## define an ensemble under some Gelfand map ##G##. So in this sense an ensemble is not defined until you have a state and a context.

However this has nothing to do with Bohmian Mechanics, I'm not sure how it changes this statement.

Well, if BM = QM then do the hidden variables define a context?

Or is BM not equivalent to QM?
 
  • #240
atyy said:
Well, if BM = QM then do the hidden variables define a context?

Or is BM not equivalent to QM?
Not in general, i.e. out of equilibrium. Thus the general probability theory of Bohmian Mechanics is quite different from QM. One example being the existence of a single sample space.
 
  • #241
DarMM said:
Not in general, i.e. out of equilibrium. Thus the general probability theory of Bohmian Mechanics is quite different from QM. One example being the existence of a single sample space.

How about under the assumption of equilibrium?
 
  • #242
atyy said:
How about under the assumption of equilibrium?
It is still not equivalent since it posits additional structure not present in QM. Thus it is a nontrivial extension of QM.
 
  • #243
A. Neumaier said:
According to your definition it only defines a state. DarMM says that states and ensembles are not synonymous. Why else would one use two different names for it? It seems that you and DarMM use the same term with a completely different meaning!

How do you define ensembles on a precise/formal level?
vanhees71 said:
The problem of mutual understanding between us is that I think in terms of physics and you in terms of mathematics.
The main difference is that mathematicians are trained to use precise concepts and smell easily when something informal cannot be made precise. This is usually the case where informal mathematical arguments go wrong, hence our sensitivity to lack of conceptual precision. Physicists are much more liberal in this respect and aim for precision only when their informal thinking led them completely astray. Thus they tend not to notice the many subtleties inherent in the quest for good conceptual foundations.
vanhees71 said:
As I said the physics logic for me is the following. First there are states and observables, and these have to be clearly distinguished.
But I asked for the precise physical definition of what you call an ensemble (as contrasted to state). In your description the term didn't occur: you only explained the meaning of states and observables.
vanhees71 said:
On the physical operational level a state is a preparation procedure or, to put it mathematically, an equivalence class of preparation procedures.
This is only mock-mathematical, as preparation procedures are no mathematical entities, and the equivalence relation in question is not even specified.
vanhees71 said:
In my example the LHC is a "preparation machine" for (unpolarized) proton beams with a quite well-defined momentum and energy. These beams are prepared such that they collide in specific points along the beam line. For me the preparation procedure delivers a well-defined ensemble of colliding proton beams.
According to which notion of ensemble? That's the question of interest in the present context.

If ''ensemble of colliding proton beams'' is just another phrase for ''several colliding proton beams'' then it is plain wrong to later claim subensembles by filtering according to spin, say. The magnet creates two beams from one, hence two ensembles from one.

So what else did you mean?
 
  • #244
Is the protean nature of ensembles in QM a weakness in the minimalist ensemble interpretation?

My understanding so far: The theory of a given system is the double ##(H,\rho)##, the dynamics and the preparation. I.e. All physical content is contained in these terms. The triple ##(H,\rho,\sigma)## describes an ensemble in terms of possible outcomes of a measurement (or possible outcomes of a sequence of measurements), where ##\sigma## is the set of possibilities. The triple ##(H,\rho,\sigma')## describes an ensemble in terms of a different, incompatible set of measurement possibilities ##\sigma'##.

Could we say the physical content of the triples ##(H,\rho,\sigma)## and ##(H,\rho,\sigma')## is the same, and the choice of one over the other is merely a choice of appropriate descriptive terms for a measurement context. I.e. A choice of measurement context does not change any physical content of the preparation. It merely constrains the physicist to use a description appropriate for that context.

[edit] - Added some clarification.
 
Last edited:
  • #245
Morbert said:
My understanding so far: The theory of a given system is the double ##(H,\rho)##, the dynamics and the preparation. I.e. All physical content is contained in these terms. The triple ##(H,\rho,\sigma)## describes an ensemble in terms of possible outcomes of a measurement (or possible outcomes of a sequence of measurements), where ##\sigma## is the set of possibilities. The triple ##(H,\rho,\sigma')## describes an ensemble in terms of a different, incompatible set of measurement possibilities ##\sigma'##.
In your terms,
  • ##H##, the Hamiltonian, characterizes (together with the Hilbert space and its distinguished operators) a ''system'', i.e., an ''arbitrary'' system of the kind considered (e.g., a beam),
  • ##(H,\rho)##, where ##\rho## is a state, characterizes a ''preparation'', i.e., a ''particular'' system of this kind (e.g., the beam prepared in a particular way specified by values of controls, means of generation, etc.), and
  • ##(H,\rho,\sigma)## where ##\sigma## is a measurement setting (choice of POVM or, in the idealized case, of an orthonormal basis), characterizes an ''ensemble'', i.e., a statistical population measured or to be measured.
 
  • Like
Likes dextercioby

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
627
Replies
4
Views
628
Replies
1
Views
820
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
4
Views
986
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
34
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
69
Views
4K
Replies
5
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
4
Replies
115
Views
6K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
0
Views
548
Back
Top