A I can't understand axiom of regularity....

  • A
  • Thread starter Thread starter ankit.jain
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Axiom
ankit.jain
Messages
7
Reaction score
0
It states that no set can be an element of itself..what does it exactly mean?why can't. We consider the whole set as a single element?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
You have to exclude the possibility that a set can contain itself as an element because otherwise you will run into paradoxa: "The barber in this village shaves everyone except those who shave themselves."
So does the barber shave himself or not?

Of course you can consider sets which contain other sets as elements.
E.g. consider a set ##S=\{1,2,3\}##. Then the set of all subsets of ##S## is ##P(S) = \{∅,\{1\},\{2\},\{3\},\{1,2\},\{1,3\},\{2,3\},\{1,2,3\}\}##.
Please regard that although ##S## is an element of ##P(S)## neither of both contains itself as an element. ##P(S)## is called power set of ##S##.
 
fresh_42 said:
You have to exclude the possibility that a set can contain itself as an element because otherwise you will run into paradoxa: "The barber in this village shaves everyone except those who shave themselves."
So does the barber shave himself or not?

This is a very popular misconception. The axiom of regularity does not avoid any paradoxes. The barber paradox cannot be avoided by the axiom of regularity. It is the strengthening of the comprehension axiom that avoids the barber paradox.

Indeed, it has been shown that there are many nice models of ZFC- that are perfectly consistent (given ZFC- is consistent) and that do not satisfy the axiom of regularity. For an example of such models, see the nice book by Hrbacek and Jech.

As for the OP: it's just an axiom, and it's not an essential axiom. Almost all of math goes through perfectly fine if we choose to accept the axiom, or if we do not choose to accept the axiom. To 99% of mathematics, the axiom is irrelevant (and that can be given an informal argument). I myself choose not to accept the axiom of regularity because it is irrelevant. I never work with sets which are an element of itself anyway, even though I'm perfectly fine with them existing.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba, suremarc, Demystifier and 1 other person
micromass said:
It is the strengthening of the comprehension axiom that avoids the barber paradox.
Thank you for clarification.

The axiom of regularity does not avoid any paradoxes. The barber paradox cannot be avoided by the axiom of regularity.
At this point I got stuck. If the axiom of regularity reads ∀x (x ≠ ∅ ⇒ ∃y ∈ x (y∩x = ∅) ) so why isn't the construction S = {S} forbidden by it, since x = y = S are the only elements and therefore in contradiction to the axiom. At which point am I wrong?
 
fresh_42 said:
At this point I got stuck. If the axiom of regularity reads ∀x (x ≠ ∅ ⇒ ∃y ∈ x (y∩x = ∅) ) so why isn't the construction S = {S} forbidden by it, since x = y = S are the only elements and therefore in contradiction to the axiom. At which point am I wrong?

You are right that constructions of the form ##S = \{S\}## are forbidden by the regularity axiom. But that was not my point. My point is that it has been proven that the axiom of regularity is relative consistent with ZFC, but so is its negation. This means that if ZFC has a contradiction somewhere, then so will ZFC + regularity. The contradiction will just be slightly different, but it is there.

So if some kind of barber's paradox shows up without regularity, then some paradox will show up with regularity too.
 
  • Like
Likes fresh_42
Still not clear.
 
ankit.jain said:
Still not clear.
What exactly is still not clear?
ankit.jain said:
It states that no set can be an element of itself..what does it exactly mean?why can't. We consider the whole set as a single element?
Yes, the whole set is considered as a single element. The axiom of regularity implies that for any set S, S∈S is not allowed.

As micromass explained, this axiom isn't terribly important for most of Mathematics.
 
Yes. It isn't that important because development of the integers and arithmetic do not depend on it at all. It simply forces the notion of a "set" to agree with what our intuition says a set should represent. Infinite or circular inclusion chains do not make a whole lot of practical sense.
 
How can you ever say that you have precisely defined a set that contains itself? I am curious if there is a well-defined example of such a thing. If not, I think it is irrelevant to mathematics.
 
  • #10
FactChecker said:
How can you ever say that you have precisely defined a set that contains itself? I am curious if there is a well-defined example of such a thing. If not, I think it is irrelevant to mathematics.

There are axioms of anti-regularity that deal with such things. So there are quite precise way of dealing with this. It's still true it's irrelevant to most mathematics though.
 
  • Like
Likes FactChecker
  • #11
FactChecker said:
How can you ever say that you have precisely defined a set that contains itself? I am curious if there is a well-defined example of such a thing. If not, I think it is irrelevant to mathematics.
From my understanding, you don't have to define them. You simply omit the axiom of regularity/foundation and study the hypothetical "sets" that would violate it. \in is just a binary predicate relating two objects we happen to call "sets" in set theory. Every object in the domain of the first-order system of ZFC is called a "set". It is the axioms themselves that demand "sets" operate as we would envision collections of "things" in the real world. Of course, we can have other things in the universe for which the extensionality axiom doesn't apply. You then have to add an "is a set" predicate and preface the extensionality axiom with it
 
  • Like
Likes FactChecker
  • #12
mbs said:
From my understanding, you don't have to define them. You simply omit the axiom of regularity/foundation and study the hypothetical "sets" that would violate it. \in is just a binary predicate relating two objects we happen to call "sets" in set theory. Every object in the domain of the first-order system of ZFC is called a "set". It is the axioms themselves that demand "sets" operate as we would envision collections of "things" in the real world. Of course, we can have other things in the universe for which the extensionality axiom doesn't apply. You then have to add an "is a set" predicate and preface the extensionality axiom with it

Of course we can just leave out the regularity axiom, but that doesn't get us far. All that negating the foundation axiom does, is saying there is one set for which the foundation axiom fails. You don't even have any information regarding the set. And even if you do. For example, take a set ##x## for which ##x=\{x\}##. Is such a set ##x## unique? How do we check equality with such sets? The extensionality axiom is useless here.
So just leaving out the regularity axiom is not useful, to have something useful, we should replace it with a better axiom for which we can actually prove things with. For example https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aczel's_anti-foundation_axiom
 
  • Like
Likes pbuk, bcrowell and FactChecker
  • #13
mbs said:
From my understanding, you don't have to define them. You simply omit the axiom of regularity/foundation and study the hypothetical "sets" that would violate it. \in is just a binary predicate relating two objects we happen to call "sets" in set theory. Every object in the domain of the first-order system of ZFC is called a "set". It is the axioms themselves that demand "sets" operate as we would envision collections of "things" in the real world. Of course, we can have other things in the universe for which the extensionality axiom doesn't apply. You then have to add an "is a set" predicate and preface the extensionality axiom with it
I think I understand. So leaving it out does not necessarily mean that there is, in fact, a set that contains itself. It just means that you can not use that axiom (no set contains itself) in proofs.
 
  • #14
FactChecker said:
I think I understand. So leaving it out does not mean that there is, in fact, a set that contains itself, it just means that you can not use that axiom (no set contains itself) in proofs.

You're correct of course, but I interpreted his post as assuming the negation of regularity.
 
  • Like
Likes FactChecker
  • #15
micromass said:
You're correct of course, but I interpreted his post as assuming the negation of regularity.
I guess you could hypothetically define an example, just by saying that the set X has itself as an element. Although I would like to say that X is not well-defined, I would need to use the axiom to say that.
 
  • #16
micromass said:
Of course we can just leave out the regularity axiom, but that doesn't get us far. All that negating the foundation axiom does, is saying there is one set for which the foundation axiom fails. You don't even have any information regarding the set. And even if you do. For example, take a set ##x## for which ##x=\{x\}##. Is such a set ##x## unique? How do we check equality with such sets? The extensionality axiom is useless here.
So just leaving out the regularity axiom is not useful, to have something useful, we should replace it with a better axiom for which we can actually prove things with. For example https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aczel's_anti-foundation_axiom
Okay. I don't think I said anything that contradicts anything you're saying. A set for which the axiom of foundation fails is simply a (non-empty) set S in which every member of S contains another member of S. Simply removing the foundation axiom keeps such sets purely hypothetical. You would need addition axioms to formally construct the existence of all such sets (much like the axiom of infinity constructs the integers). Simply having one non-regular set isn't enough to prove anything.
 
  • #17
micromass said:
What a fascinating area of study - I couldn't understand why I had not seen this before, then realized that I finished full-time academic study two years before Aczel's paper. Can you point me to a good, relatively discursive book? I was never very fond of books containing long formal proofs of theorem after theorem with no apparent motivation and 30 years out of study has not made me any more so.
 
  • #18
MrAnchovy said:
What a fascinating area of study - I couldn't understand why I had not seen this before, then realized that I finished full-time academic study two years before Aczel's paper. Can you point me to a good, relatively discursive book? I was never very fond of books containing long formal proofs of theorem after theorem with no apparent motivation and 30 years out of study has not made me any more so.

The book by Hrbacek and Jech contains a nice chapter on this anti-foundation thing. It's a really great book to read. https://www.amazon.com/dp/0824779150/?tag=pfamazon01-20
 
  • #19
micromass said:
The book by Hrbacek and Jech contains a nice chapter on this anti-foundation thing. It's a really great book to read. https://www.amazon.com/dp/0824779150/?tag=pfamazon01-20
Many thanks, ordered from the train on the way home and it will be with me on Sunday apparently - how did life work before Amazon?
 
  • Like
Likes Samy_A

Similar threads

Replies
16
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
40
Views
4K
Replies
4
Views
2K
Replies
2
Views
2K
Replies
3
Views
2K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Replies
10
Views
2K
Replies
17
Views
2K
Back
Top