I Proof that 1 is an odd number using Peano Axioms of naturals

AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on proving that 1 is an odd number using Peano Axioms, with the premise that natural numbers start at 1. The initial definitions of oddness, specifically n = 2k + 1, fail to include 1, leading to confusion about its classification. A proposed solution redefines oddness as n + 1 = 2k, allowing 1 to be classified as odd with k = 1. The conversation highlights that definitions in mathematics are crucial, and without redefining oddness, 1 cannot be proven odd under the standard definition. Ultimately, the conclusion is that with appropriate definitions, 1 can indeed be classified as an odd number.
Andraz Cepic
Messages
31
Reaction score
3
So I was just writing a proof that every natural number is either even or odd. I went in two directions and both require that 1 is odd, in fact I think that 1 must always be odd for every such proof as the nature of naturals is inductive from 1.

I am using the version where 1 is the smallest number of natural numbers. Using the one with 0 shouldn't be a problem.

Now by the definition of oddness, a number n in naturals is odd iff n = 2k + 1 for some k in naturals.
Thereby 1 "could" be 1 = 2*0 + 1, however 0 does not exist from Peano's axioms, thus such an operation is not defined in naturals, moreover using n = 2k - 1 as the definition of oddness is also not sufficient, as the natural numbers have no notion of -1.

Therefore, my question is what am I missing here, as I do not yet know almost any abstract algebra to fully understand such rigor here(I'll be a math freshman starting this October), but this question is getting me nervous :D. Could it be that with these axioms we cannot define evenness or oddness of the members of the set they describe?
 
Mathematics news on Phys.org
If your natural numbers start at 1 rather than 0, I don't think you'd be able to succeed by defining an odd number as ##2k+1##, for the reason you pointed out.

However the following problem:
Andraz Cepic said:
moreover using n = 2k - 1 as the definition of oddness is also not sufficient, as the natural numbers have no notion of -1.
is easily fixed.

Instead of defining an odd number to be a number ##n## for which there exists a number ##k## such that ##n=2k-1## which, as you point out, is undefined, define it to be a number ##n## for which there exists a number ##k## such that ##n+1=2k##. Then ##n=1## is odd with ##k=1##.
 
I think you're getting nervous unnecessarily. In maths things are what they are defined to be. If we take ##\mathbb{N}## not to include ##0## and define odd and even as ##2n+1## and ##2n## respectively, then this doesn't cover the number ##1##.#

Note that if the definition of odd is ##2n+1## for some ##n \in \mathbb{N}##, then nothing you can do is going to prove that ##1## is odd from that; precisely because ##1## fails that definition.

We see that ##2, 4, 6 \dots## are even and that ##3, 5, 7 \dots## are odd.

We would then have to define ##1## to be odd. Later, when we have ##0## we can redefine odd and even and take care of ##1## then.

Note that an inductive argument can just as easily start with ##3## as with ##1##. You could prove that ##3, 5, 7 \dots## are odd without saying anything about ##1##.
 
PeroK said:
I think you're getting nervous unnecessarily. In maths things are what they are defined to be. If we take ##\mathbb{N}## not to include ##0## and define odd and even as ##2n+1## and ##2n## respectively, then this doesn't cover the number ##1##.#

Note that if the definition of odd is ##2n+1## for some ##n \in \mathbb{N}##, then nothing you can do is going to prove that ##1## is odd from that; precisely because ##1## fails that definition.

We see that ##2, 4, 6 \dots## are even and that ##3, 5, 7 \dots## are odd.

We would then have to define ##1## to be odd. Later, when we have ##0## we can redefine odd and even and take care of ##1## then.

Note that an inductive argument can just as easily start with ##3## as with ##1##. You could prove that ##3, 5, 7 \dots## are odd without saying anything about ##1##.
Hmm so I was right to hypothesise that we cannot prove this theorem with naturals starting at 1 as 1 fails the definitions of oddness and evenness, except of course we define oddness of n as n+1=2k for some k, then 1 satsfies it perfectly. I did not even think about this solution!

Thank you :)
 
  • Like
Likes PeroK
Thread 'Video on imaginary numbers and some queries'
Hi, I was watching the following video. I found some points confusing. Could you please help me to understand the gaps? Thanks, in advance! Question 1: Around 4:22, the video says the following. So for those mathematicians, negative numbers didn't exist. You could subtract, that is find the difference between two positive quantities, but you couldn't have a negative answer or negative coefficients. Mathematicians were so averse to negative numbers that there was no single quadratic...
Insights auto threads is broken atm, so I'm manually creating these for new Insight articles. In Dirac’s Principles of Quantum Mechanics published in 1930 he introduced a “convenient notation” he referred to as a “delta function” which he treated as a continuum analog to the discrete Kronecker delta. The Kronecker delta is simply the indexed components of the identity operator in matrix algebra Source: https://www.physicsforums.com/insights/what-exactly-is-diracs-delta-function/ by...
Thread 'Unit Circle Double Angle Derivations'
Here I made a terrible mistake of assuming this to be an equilateral triangle and set 2sinx=1 => x=pi/6. Although this did derive the double angle formulas it also led into a terrible mess trying to find all the combinations of sides. I must have been tired and just assumed 6x=180 and 2sinx=1. By that time, I was so mindset that I nearly scolded a person for even saying 90-x. I wonder if this is a case of biased observation that seeks to dis credit me like Jesus of Nazareth since in reality...
Back
Top