Thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality

In summary, Bell's move from the first equation to the second equation is explained by TI as involving an assumption that is violated in QM. This move is significant because it is used to derive the Bell inequality.
  • #1
N88
225
12
TL;DR Summary
Concerning p.198 of Bell's famous 1964 paper http://cds.cern.ch/record/111654/files/vol1p195-200_001.pdf How does TI explain Bell's move from the first equation to the second equation?
Concerning p.198 of Bell's famous 1964 paper http://cds.cern.ch/record/111654/files/vol1p195-200_001.pdf

How does TI explain Bell's move from the first equation to the second equation?

Under TI, what is the physical significance of this move?

Thank you.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
N88 said:
How does TI explain Bell's move from the first equation to the second equation?

Why should TI have to explain it? The move from the first equation to the second equation involves an assumption which is violated in QM. Since TI is an interpretation of QM, it can't explain something which violates QM.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #3
PeterDonis said:
Why should TI have to explain it? The move from the first equation to the second equation involves an assumption which is violated in QM. Since TI is an interpretation of QM, it can't explain something which violates QM.
So what is that assumption via your explanation, thanks?
 
  • #4
N88 said:
what is that assumption via your explanation, thanks?

Have you read the paper? What does it say in the sentence right after the first equation? That sentence even starts with the words "The vital assumption is..."
 
  • #5
PeterDonis said:
Have you read the paper? What does it say in the sentence right after the first equation? That sentence even starts with the words "The vital assumption is..."
Yes, I've read the paper and that assumption. And I agree with that assumption. And I note Bell says that he uses that first equation to make the move that I am enquiring about.

But how does he use that qualifier of the first equation, and that equation itself, to make that move that I am enquiring about?

PS: You said that QM violates this assumption? Bell's eqn (3) seems not to?
 
  • #6
N88 said:
But how does he use that qualifier of the first equation, and that equation itself, to make that move that I am enquiring about?

What move? The move from equation (1) to equation (2)? That's just the standard formula for an expectation value of a quantity, where the quantity in this case is the product of A and B.

N88 said:
You said that QM violates this assumption? Bell's eqn (3) seems not to?

Bell's equation (3) is the QM expectation value, which does indeed violate the assumption used in equations (1) and (2), because it violates the inequality that Bell derives in the rest of the paper based on that assumption. Which is the whole point of the paper. So, once again, have you read the paper? Because the questions you are asking don't seem like questions that someone who has read and understood the paper would be asking.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #7
PeterDonis said:
What move? The move from equation (1) to equation (2)? That's just the standard formula for an expectation value of a quantity, where the quantity in this case is the product of A and B.
Bell's equation (3) is the QM expectation value, which does indeed violate the assumption used in equations (1) and (2), because it violates the inequality that Bell derives in the rest of the paper based on that assumption. Which is the whole point of the paper. So, once again, have you read the paper? Because the questions you are asking don't seem like questions that someone who has read and understood the paper would be asking.
The move that I am enquiring about is at the top of p.198; from the first eqn there to the second eqn there.
 
  • #8
N88 said:
The move that I am enquiring about is at the top of p.198; from the first eqn there to the second eqn there.

Ok. This is still irrelevant to the thermal interpretation, since it's part of the derivation of the Bell inequality, which has nothing to do with QM.

As far as I can tell, to go from the first equation at the top of p. 198 to the second, he is simply using equation (1), which says that both A and B only take the values +1 or -1.
 
  • #9
PeterDonis said:
Ok. This is still irrelevant to the thermal interpretation, since it's part of the derivation of the Bell inequality, which has nothing to do with QM.

As far as I can tell, to go from the first equation at the top of p. 198 to the second, he is simply using equation (1), which says that both A and B only take the values +1 or -1.

So how do you see Bell using his eqn (1)?

I am trying to go further than as far as you can tell. That's why I thought the TI might provide me with an Aldi good/different insight.
 
  • #10
N88 said:
how do you see Bell using his eqn (1)?

Um, exactly the way he says in the paper?

N88 said:
I am trying to go further than as far as you can tell.

I have no idea what this means.

N88 said:
That's why I thought the TI might provide me with an Aldi good/different insight.

I don't understand what you need insight about or why you think any QM interpretation might provide it. Bell's reasoning in the paper is perfectly clear, and, as I've already said, has nothing whatever to do with any interpretation of QM, since his derivation of his inequality is not based on QM. The only use of QM in the paper at all is to point out that QM's expectation value violates the inequality.
 
  • #11
PeterDonis said:
Um, exactly the way he says in the paper? [emph. added]

I don't understand what you need insight about. Bell's reasoning in the paper is perfectly clear, and, as I've already said, has nothing whatever to do with any interpretation of QM, since his derivation of his inequality is not based on QM. The only use of QM in the paper at all is to point out that QM's expectation value violates the inequality.

But, as far as I can see: Bell does not say exactly what way he uses his eqn (1). So it might help to interpret my seeking as: Why does Bell used eqn (1) in the way that he does in his move atop p.198? What is the physical significance of his way? Thanks.
 
  • #12
N88 said:
Bell does not say exactly what way he uses his eqn (1).

Sure he does; he says "using (1)" right after the two equations at the top of p. 198. Yes, he leaves it to you to see exactly how using (1) gets you from the first to the second; are you unable to see how that works?

N88 said:
Why does Bell used eqn (1) in the way that he does in his move atop p.198?

Um, because that's a necessary step in the logic to get the inequality he wants?

N88 said:
What is the physical significance of his way?

What is the physical significance of equation (1)? Look at it. It's just saying that A and B are observables that can only produce the results +1 and -1 when measured, and that the things that affect which result gets produced are the corresponding setting of the measurement device (##\vec{a}## or ##\vec{b}##) and the "hidden variables" ##\lambda##.
 
  • #13
PeterDonis said:
Sure he does; he says "using (1)" right after the two equations at the top of p. 198. Yes, he leaves it to you to see exactly how using (1) gets you from the first to the second; are you unable to see how that works?

Could you tell me how you see that it works, please?

Um, because that's a necessary step in the logic to get the inequality he wants?

This seems back-to-front to me.

What is the physical significance of equation (1)? Look at it. It's just saying that A and B are observables that can only produce the results +1 and -1 when measured, and that the things that affect which result gets produced are the corresponding setting of the measurement device (##\vec{a}## or ##\vec{b}##) and the "hidden variables" ##\lambda##.

No, that is not my question here. I've been asking for the physical significance of the way that Bell uses his (1) to make the move atop p.198.
 
  • #14
N88 said:
Could you tell me how you see that it works, please?

We have the first equation at the top of p. 198:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = - \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) \left[ A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) - A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) \right]
$$

Since by equation (1), each ##A## can only take on the values ##\pm 1##, then for any vector, such as ##\vec{b}##, we must have ##A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) = 1##, so we can insert it anywhere we like as a factor. So we can insert it into the last term on the RHS of the above:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = - \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) \left[ A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) - A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) \right]
$$

Then we just flip the sign by reversing the order of the terms, and factor out ##A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda)## in the obvious way, to get the second equation at the top of p. 198:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) \left[ A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) - 1 \right]
$$
 
  • #15
PeterDonis said:
We have the first equation at the top of p. 198:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = - \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) \left[ A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) - A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) \right]. (X)
$$

Since by equation (1), each ##A## can only take on the values ##\pm 1##, then for any vector, such as ##\vec{b}##, we must have ##A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) = 1##, so we can insert it anywhere we like as a factor. So we can insert it into the last term on the RHS of the above:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = - \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) \left[ A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) - A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) \right]. (Y)
$$

Then we just flip the sign by reversing the order of the terms, and factor out ##A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda)## in the obvious way, to get the second equation at the top of p. 198:

$$
P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) - P(\vec{a}, \vec{b}) = \int d \lambda \rho(\lambda) A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) \left[ A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda) - 1 \right]. (Z)
$$

OK, many thanks. So the overall effect is that Bell has made an assumption that leads to $$- A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda)$$ in (X) being equal to $$ - A(\vec{a}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{b}, \lambda) A(\vec{c}, \lambda$$ in (Y).

Now can you explain please what QM (or TI) has to say about this? Rather than being about locality (as you suggested earlier) isn't it more to do with (something like) non-commuting observables not permitting such an equality? In other words: since I know Bell fairly well, I'd like to know what QM says of the situation.

Thanks again.
 
  • #16
Bell's inquality was known to mathematicians as the Triangle inequality as early as the 1920s. It's just a statement of the relation between the expectation values of variables defined on a common sample space.

Ultimately in the CHSH presentation for example the inequality basically assumes that there is a distribution ##p\left(a,b,c,d\right)## giving the probability of outcomes for each variable. In a given round we only measure two variables say ##a,c## and we have probabilities for their outcomes ##p\left(a,c\right)##. That these are marginals of the overall distribution is what gives the inequality.

How QM violates the inequality is that there is no ##p\left(a,b,c,d\right)##, the outcomes in a given trial are not the marginals of a four outcome case.

However this has nothing to do with the Thermal Interpretation in particular.
 
  • #17
DarMM said:
Bell's inquality was known to mathematicians as the Triangle inequality as early as the 1920s. It's just a statement of the relation between the expectation values of variables defined on a common sample space.

Ultimately in the CHSH presentation for example the inequality basically assumes that there is a distribution ##p\left(a,b,c,d\right)## giving the probability of outcomes for each variable. In a given round we only measure two variables say ##a,c## and we have probabilities for their outcomes ##p\left(a,c\right)##. That these are marginals of the overall distribution is what gives the inequality.

How QM violates the inequality is that there is no ##p\left(a,b,c,d\right)##, the outcomes in a given trial are not the marginals of a four outcome case.

However this has nothing to do with the Thermal Interpretation in particular.

Many thanks for your reply. I agree re TI. My interest in TI was in seeking alternative explanations as to where Bell goes wrong physically; TI (as I understand it) being another theory that accept's Bell's inequality mathematically.

I am seeking to understand the physical objections to Bell's inequality. To understand the reasons given for its violation by experiments.

This comparison might make my interest clearer. Here are 3 inequalities with a common LHS.

##|E(a,b)-E(a,c)| ≤ 1-E(a,b)E(a,c)## = True under Bell (1964) and its experiment.
##|E(a,b)-E(a,c)| ≤ 1+E(b,c)## = False under QM and experiment = Bell's famous inequality.
##|E(a,b)-E(a,c)| ≤ 3/2+E(b,c)## = True under Bell (1964) and its experiment.

So Bell is the odd one out. And, as I see it, the difference is this: as in Post #15 above, Bell does not maintain the requirement that the correlations relevant to expectations must be derived from test results obtained in the same instance. (As stated in the line before Bell's first equation.)

So in this sense, it seems to me that Bell involves a common mathematical/physical error. Mathematically and physically, it seems to me: Bell breaks the requirement about working with results obtained in the same instance.

In other words; see Post #15 above: he appears to bust one instance and makes it two and gets an invalid result. Whereas, when instances are not busted, valid results twice follow mathematically and physically and locally.
 
  • #18
N88 said:
TI (as I understand it) being another theory that accept's Bell's inequality mathematically.
TI is consistent with standard quantum mechanics, which violates the Bell inequalities in the appropriate contexts.
N88 said:
I am seeking to understand the physical objections to Bell's inequality. To understand the reasons given for its violation by experiments.
Bell inequalities are theorems about classical probabilistic models, whose assumptions already contradict both quantum theory and experiment (since the conclusions do). Hence they say nothing at all about quantum systems.

To understand the reasons for their violation by experiments it is no help to analyze the proof of the inequalities (which you try to do) since the problem is already in the assumptions made.
 
  • Like
Likes mattt and N88
  • #19
A. Neumaier said:
TI is consistent with standard quantum mechanics, which violates the Bell inequalities in the appropriate contexts.

Bell inequalities are theorems about classical probabilistic models, whose assumptions already contradict both quantum theory and experiment (since the conclusions do). Hence they say nothing at all about quantum systems.

To understand the reasons for their violation by experiments it is no help to analyze the proof of the inequalities (which you try to do) since the problem is already in the assumptions made.
Thank you; this is very helpful. But I question whether Bell is about classical probability models: since the two valid inequalities above are derived under locality and standard probability theory?

Also. It seems to me that the widespread belief -- that Bell-inequalities show that nature is nonlocal -- needs to be challenged by showing what can be derived locally by means of Bell's approach and ordinary probability theory. For, also, Bell did expect that "dilemmas" (associated with his work ) would be overcome.

May I take it that TI is fully Einstein-local?
 
  • #20
Bell assumes no retrocausality, no nonlocal effects, all variables come from a common sample space and that there is a single world.

QM violates the resulting equalities, thus one of these is wrong.
 
  • Like
Likes N88
  • #21
N88 said:
Now can you explain please what QM (or TI) has to say about this?

Absolutely nothing. As I've already said, this whole derivation in Bell's paper has nothing to do with QM. It is a derivation regarding a class of local hidden variable models that is intended to show that no such model can match the predictions of QM. That's the whole point of the paper. Obviously QM and interpretations of QM can't have anything to say about a class of models that are not QM and can't match the predictions of QM.
 
  • #22
N88 said:
TI (as I understand it) being another theory that accept's Bell's inequality mathematically.

Huh? QM, and all interpretations of QM, cannot possibly "accept Bell's inequality mathematically", since they violate it.
 
  • #23
N88 said:
Here are 3 inequalities with a common LHS.

Where are you getting the other two (the ones that are not Bell's inequality) from?

N88 said:
the two valid inequalities above are derived under locality and standard probability theory?

You didn't derive them; you just pulled them out of thin air.
 
  • #24
N88 said:
May I take it that TI is fully Einstein-local?

What does "Einstein-local" mean?
 
  • #25
N88 said:
the widespread belief -- that Bell-inequalities show that nature is nonlocal

No, the fact that QM violates the Bell inequalities shows that nature is either nonlocal, or retrocausal, or many-worlds, or whatever the short version of "not all variables come from a common sample space" is.
 
  • #26
PeterDonis said:
No, the fact that QM violates the Bell inequalities shows that nature is either nonlocal, or retrocausal, or many-worlds, or whatever the short version of "not all variables come from a common sample space" is.
Complimentarity or failure of unicity.
 
  • #27
N88 said:
The move that I am enquiring about is at the top of p.198; from the first eqn there to the second eqn there.

Although not so labeled, this is where the Realism assumption is added. The Realism assumption is that there is a counterfactual c, in addition to a and b. So just as a and b are separable: a and c are separable; and b and c are separable as well. Separable meaning: they are independent; essentially saying locality applies.
 
  • #28
DarMM said:
Bell assumes no retrocausality, no nonlocal effects, all variables come from a common sample space and that there is a single world.

QM violates the resulting INequalities, thus one of these is wrong. [EDIT]
I like this because it brings a possible point of difference into clearer focus.

#1. From my POV: Bell does not assume that all relevant correlations arise from test results obtained in the same instance; see #2 next.

#2. He recognises #1 as a physical fact of the experiment that he is studying.

#3. So he rightly makes #2 a condition on the use of his first equation; (1).

#4. However. When he uses (1) -- as he says he does -- to, move from the first equation atop p.198 to the second: he breaches (1).

#5. The breach in #4 arises from the point discussed in Post-15 above.

#6. That is: in breaching* a physical matter-of-fact, his inequality is liable to be violated by QM; and it is.

#7. Now you say: "QM violates the resulting inequalities, thus one of these assumptions [that you list above] is wrong."

#8. Whereas I propose that "QM violates the resulting inequalities because Bell violates a well-recognized physical matter-of-fact of the setting that he analyses."

#9. Is this an agreeable proposal?

#10. The corollary being that, when we avoid this breach, we can derive valid inequalities: doubly valid because they agree with QM, and with locality.

HTH.

* Busting up one instance to create an invalid new one: invalid because we know that it breaches QM.
 
  • #29
N88 said:
When he uses (1) -- as he says he does -- to, move from the first equation atop p.198 to the second: he breaches (1).

How?

N88 said:
#5. The breach in #4 arises from the point discussed in Post-15 above.

I don't see how. Post #15 says nothing about the reasoning using (1) to go from the first equation at the top of p. 198 to the second being incorrect.
 
  • #30
PeterDonis said:
What does "Einstein-local"mean?
I understand "Einstein-local" to mean "No influence propagates superluminally".
 
  • #31
DrChinese said:
Although not so labeled, this is where the Realism assumption is added. The Realism assumption is that there is a counterfactual c, in addition to a and b. So just as a and b are separable: a and c are separable; and b and c are separable as well. Separable meaning: they are independent; essentially saying locality applies.
Is "counterfactual" the right word to use re c ? I take c to be another unit-vector in 3-space.
 
  • #32
N88 said:
I understand "Einstein-local" to mean "No influence propagates superluminally".

That's still not quite precise, because "influence" is vague.

If we're talking about non-relativistic QM, then there is no restriction on how fast anything can propagate; but non-relativistic QM is only an approximation.

If we're talking about relativistic QM, i.e., QFT, then we have what is called "signal locality", which means that actual information (as opposed to "influences") cannot propagate faster than light; the only way to tell what happened at some other measurement that is spacelike separated from the measurement you just made is to wait for the person who made the other measurement to send you their results by ordinary light-speed or slower means. Even if you and the other person measured entangled particles, you can't tell that from your own measurement alone; only from the correlation between the two, which you can only find out by getting the other person's results by ordinary light-speed or slower means, can you determine that there were correlations that violated the Bell inequalities. Violating the Bell inequalities is what is usually termed "nonlocality", but as you can see, this nonlocality is perfectly consistent with signal locality (and also with microcausality, discussed next).

QFT also has something called "microcausality", which means that spacelike separated measurements must commute, i.e., their results must be independent of the order in which they happen. This is simply because if the measurements are spacelike separated, there is no invariant order in which they happen; the order depends on your choice of reference frame. This is sometimes also seen as a version of "locality", but that might not be the best way to look at it, because, as noted above, it is perfectly consistent with correlations between spacelike separated measurements that violate the Bell inequalities.

I'm not sure which, if any, of the above correspond to what you mean by "Einstein locality".
 
  • Like
Likes N88
  • #33
PeterDonis said:
That's still not quite precise, because "influence" is vague.

If we're talking about non-relativistic QM, then there is no restriction on how fast anything can propagate; but non-relativistic QM is only an approximation.

If we're talking about relativistic QM, i.e., QFT, then we have what is called "signal locality", which means that actual information (as opposed to "influences") cannot propagate faster than light; the only way to tell what happened at some other measurement that is spacelike separated from the measurement you just made is to wait for the person who made the other measurement to send you their results by ordinary light-speed or slower means. Even if you and the other person measured entangled particles, you can't tell that from your own measurement alone; only from the correlation between the two, which you can only find out by getting the other person's results by ordinary light-speed or slower means, can you determine that there were correlations that violated the Bell inequalities. Violating the Bell inequalities is what is usually termed "nonlocality", but as you can see, this nonlocality is perfectly consistent with signal locality (and also with microcausality, discussed next).

QFT also has something called "microcausality", which means that spacelike separated measurements must commute, i.e., their results must be independent of the order in which they happen. This is simply because if the measurements are spacelike separated, there is no invariant order in which they happen; the order depends on your choice of reference frame. This is sometimes also seen as a version of "locality"
, but that might not be the best way to look at it, because, as noted above, it is perfectly consistent with correlations between spacelike separated measurements that violate the Bell inequalities.

I'm not sure which, if any, of the above correspond to what you mean by "Einstein locality". [Emphasis added.]
Many thanks for this helpful detail.

I would like to be consistent with relativistic QM and microcausality. So it seems to me that "signal locality" would be bound by Einstein-locality : more clearly defined as "No beable propagates superluminally".

Then, it seems to me and I would hope: "nonlocality" would have no physical relevance or significance; being relegated to a synonym for Einstein's "spooky action at a distance" and an antonym for his "principle of separability" -- at least in my dictionary.

Would such a position give you any difficulties?
 
  • #34
N88 said:
it seems to me that "signal locality" would be bound by Einstein-locality : more clearly defined as "No beable propagates superluminally".

I don't think you can say that because the existence of correlations that violate the Bell inequalities suggests that there are nonlocal "beables" that would violate your statement here. In other words, such correlations suggest that there has to be something connecting spacelike separated measurements, even if that something can't be used to send actual information faster than light (i.e., signal locality holds).

N88 said:
"nonlocality" would have no physical relevance or significance

How can that be since it's directly observable? We have experimentally confirmed that you can get correlations that violate the Bell inequalities, and that's what "nonlocality" means.
 
  • Like
Likes ftr
  • #35
N88 said:
Is "counterfactual" the right word to use re c ? I take c to be another unit-vector in 3-space.

Does it exist alongside a and b, which are what we can actually measure on an entangled pair? If you say that we can measure 2, but other settings also exist (such as c) which could have been measured: that is the definition of a counterfactual. Certainly in classical terms, a very reasonable assumption. But QM does not make predictions about measurements that are counterfactual. So yes, c is a counterfactual (unit vector).
 
<h2>What is thermal interpretation?</h2><p>Thermal interpretation is a concept in physics that explains the behavior of particles at the atomic level. It states that the properties of particles, such as their position and momentum, are not determined until they are measured. This interpretation is based on the idea that particles have a random, thermal nature and cannot be predicted with certainty.</p><h2>What is Bell's inequality?</h2><p>Bell's inequality is a mathematical expression that tests the concept of local realism in quantum mechanics. It states that certain correlations between particles should not exceed a certain limit if local realism is true. If the correlations exceed this limit, it suggests that local realism is not a valid explanation for the behavior of particles.</p><h2>How does thermal interpretation relate to Bell's inequality?</h2><p>Thermal interpretation is one of the explanations for the violation of Bell's inequality. It suggests that the correlations between particles are not due to some hidden variables, but rather a result of the random, thermal nature of particles. This interpretation is supported by experiments that have shown violations of Bell's inequality.</p><h2>What are the implications of thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality?</h2><p>Thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality have significant implications for our understanding of the behavior of particles at the quantum level. They suggest that the properties of particles are not predetermined, but rather a result of random processes. This challenges the traditional concept of determinism in physics and has led to further exploration of the nature of reality.</p><h2>How is thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality relevant to everyday life?</h2><p>While thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality may seem like abstract concepts, they have real-life applications. Our understanding of these concepts has led to the development of technologies such as quantum computing and cryptography. Additionally, they have sparked philosophical debates about the nature of reality and our place in the universe.</p>

What is thermal interpretation?

Thermal interpretation is a concept in physics that explains the behavior of particles at the atomic level. It states that the properties of particles, such as their position and momentum, are not determined until they are measured. This interpretation is based on the idea that particles have a random, thermal nature and cannot be predicted with certainty.

What is Bell's inequality?

Bell's inequality is a mathematical expression that tests the concept of local realism in quantum mechanics. It states that certain correlations between particles should not exceed a certain limit if local realism is true. If the correlations exceed this limit, it suggests that local realism is not a valid explanation for the behavior of particles.

How does thermal interpretation relate to Bell's inequality?

Thermal interpretation is one of the explanations for the violation of Bell's inequality. It suggests that the correlations between particles are not due to some hidden variables, but rather a result of the random, thermal nature of particles. This interpretation is supported by experiments that have shown violations of Bell's inequality.

What are the implications of thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality?

Thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality have significant implications for our understanding of the behavior of particles at the quantum level. They suggest that the properties of particles are not predetermined, but rather a result of random processes. This challenges the traditional concept of determinism in physics and has led to further exploration of the nature of reality.

How is thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality relevant to everyday life?

While thermal interpretation and Bell's inequality may seem like abstract concepts, they have real-life applications. Our understanding of these concepts has led to the development of technologies such as quantum computing and cryptography. Additionally, they have sparked philosophical debates about the nature of reality and our place in the universe.

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
608
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
37
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
24
Views
3K
  • Quantum Physics
6
Replies
199
Views
12K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
3
Replies
94
Views
11K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
5
Replies
153
Views
10K
Replies
18
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
16
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
2
Replies
65
Views
7K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
11K
Back
Top