Before we nitpick your 4 steps, I'd like to address some other statements you made.
lugita15 said:
... currently there are various experimental loopholes that prevent the kind of ideal Bell test which would be able to definitively test whether this is a local deterministic universe.
Because of the LR requirements/restrictions, which, in effect, preempt (and thereby render irrelevant wrt nature) the locality assumption, Bell tests, even loophole-free one's, can't ever be used to determine an underlying nonlocality.
As for the assumption of a fundamental deterministic evolution. It's, in principle, nontestable. It's an unfalsifiable assumption. Just as the assumption of a fundamental nondeterminism is.
lugita15 said:
In particular, as zonde has pointed out, it is difficult to test the prediction that you get perfect correlation at identical polarizer settings, because you would have to "catch" literally all the photons that are emitted by the source, and that requires really efficient photon detectors. All we can say is that when the angles of the polarizers are the same, the correlation is perfect for the photon pairs we DO detect. But that leaves open the possibility, seized on by zonde and other local determinists, that the photon pairs we do detect are somehow special, because the detector is biased (in an unknown way) towards detecting photon pairs with certain (unspecified) characteristics, and that the photon pairs we do NOT detect would NOT display perfect correlation, and thus the predictions of QM would be incorrect.
This just seems to be 'clutching at straws', so to speak. Since the correlation is perfect at θ = 0° for the entangled pairs that are detected, then I see no reason to assume that it would be different if all entangled pairs could be detected.
lugita15 said:
No, it just means that the experiments are not good enough to definitively answer which is right and which is wrong. They strongly suggest quantum mechanics is right ...
You said that wrt certain recent Bell tests the LR predictions were correct. We know that LR and QM predictions
must be different wrt entanglement setups. So, if the LR predictions were correct, then the QM predictions had to be wrong wrt the tests in question. But now you say that the test results suggest that QM was right? So, which is it?
lugita15 said:
... but due to practical loopholes they leave open a slim possibility for a local deterministic theory.
As I said, the loopholes are irrelevant, imo.
lugita15 said:
Sorry, there's a miscommunication. When I say "local hidden variables", I mean the philosophical stance you call "local determinism", not the formal model you call "local realism", so keep that in mind when reading my posts.
I think that ease of communication would be much better served if we simply write local determinism when we're referring to the philosophical assumptions, and LR when we're referring to the circumscribed LR formalism.
lugita15 said:
I'm trying to show that the predictions of QM cannot be absolutely correct in a local deterministic universe. As I said, the thing to be deduced from my four steps is not the claim that nature is nonlocal. Rather it is the claim that if the predictions of quantum mechanics are completely correct, than nature is nonlocal or nondeterministic.
1. Entangled photons behave identically at identical polarizer settings.
2. In a local deterministic universe, the polarizer angles the photons will and won't go through must be agreed upon in advance by the two entangled photons.
3. In order for the agreed-upon instructions (to go through or not go through) at -30 and 30 to be different, either the instructions at -30 and 0 are different or the instructions at 0 and 30 are different.
4. The probability for the instructions at -30 and 30 to be different is less than or equal to the probability for the instruction at -30 and 0 to be different plus the probability for the instructions at 0 and 30 to be different.
Step 2. doesn't represent a
local common cause, or locality (independence). The photons might be exchanging ftl transmissions sometime after their emission from a common source, but before interacting with the polarizers.
From step 1. we might assume that the value of λ, the variable determining whether a photon will go through a polarizer or not, is the same for photons 1 and 2 of any given pair when θ = 0° .
If the value of λ is the same for photons 1 and 2 of an entangled pair when θ = 0°, then is there any reason to suppose that λ would be different for photons 1 and 2 of an entangled pair wrt any other θ, such as 30°?
Before we deal with that, we might speculate about the nature of λ in these experiments involving light and polarizers. The intensity of the light they transmit is affected by the polarizer's orientation. In a polariscopic setup, the intensity of the light transmitted by the analyzing polarizer varies as cos
2θ. If we think of the optical disturbances incident on the polarizers as rotating wave shells whose expansion is constrained and directed by the transmission lines, then we can visualize the relationship between the polarizer setting and the axis of rotation as determining the amplitude of the wavefront filtered by the polarizer. So, for our purposes, the assumption that the rotational axes of entangled photons is identical seems to fit with the experimental result noted in step 1.
This common rotational axis of entangled photons, represented by λ, is also compatible with the assumption that it's produced locally via a common emission source.
Back to the preceding question. If photons 1 and 2 of any entangled pair have the exact same rotational axis, then how would we expect the rate of coincidental detection to vary as θ varies?
Using another QM observation we note that rate of individual detection doesn't vary with polarizer orientation, so we assume that λ is varying randomly from entangled pair to entangled pair. We also note that rate of coincidental detection only varies with θ, and, most importantly, as cos
2θ. Is this behavior compatible with our conceptualization of λ? It seems to be.
Start with a source emitting entangled photons with λ varying randomly. The emitter is flanked by two detectors A and B. Whatever the rate of coincidental detection is in this setup is normalized to 1. After putting identical polarizers in place, one between the emitter and A and one between the emitter and B, we note that the maximum rate of coincidental detection is .5 what it was without the polarizers, and that it varies from .5, at θ = 0° to 0 at θ = 90° as cos
2θ.
Now visualize this setup without the emitter in the middle and with the polarizers aligned (θ = 0°). We note a common rotational axis extending between the polarizers. Now rotate one or both of the polarizers to create a θ of 30°. We note a common rotational axis extending between the polarizers. Now rotate one or both of the polarizers to create a θ of 60°. We note a common rotational axis extending between the polarizers.
It's just like a polariscope, except that the source emitting random λ's is in the middle rather than at one end or the other, so both polarizers are analyzers, and the rate of coincidental detection is a function of the same angular dependency, and analogous to the detected intensity, as in a regular polariscopic setup.
Thus, the nonlinear angular dependencies observed in Bell tests are intuitive, and compatible with a local deterministic view.