Understanding bell's theorem: why hidden variables imply a linear relationship?

Physics news on Phys.org
  • #152
harrylin said:
Thanks, that's rather complex, I'll have to study it...
In what way does the model differ from the linear one in Wikipedia?
- http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Bell's_theorem#Overview
harrylin said:
I do think that hidden variables imply a linear relationship with 100% detection and without "data picking".
On second thought, I think you might be right about that.
If you stick to Bell's form, and make ρ(λ) the uniform distribution (all λ equally likely, meaning no 'data picking') then I think you get this:
C(a,b) = ρ(λ) ∫ sign [cos2(a-λ)] sign [cos2(b-λ)] dλ = 1 - ((4θ)/∏) , where θ = |a-b|, the angular difference between the polarizer settings,
for the correlation coefficient (in bold), which, in the words of the OP, is a linear relationship (or linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection).

Now, how does this differ from zonde's treatment at, https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3856186&postcount=54 ?
 
Last edited:
  • #153
ThomasT said:
On second thought, I think you might be right about that.
If you stick to Bell's form, and make ρ(λ) the uniform distribution (all λ equally likely, meaning no 'data picking') then I think you get this:
C(a,b) = ρ(λ) ∫ sign [cos2(a-λ)] sign [cos2(b-λ)] dλ = 1 - ((4θ)/∏) , where θ = |a-b|, the angular difference between the polarizer settings,
for the correlation coefficient (in bold), which, in the words of the OP, is a linear relationship (or linear correlation between θ and rate of coincidental detection).

Now, how does this differ from zonde's treatment at, https://www.physicsforums.com/showpost.php?p=3856186&postcount=54 ?
OK ... and then, was Lugita's correction in #148 perhaps not right? (and if so, why not?). I thought that I knew this, but now I'm confused. Hopefully all this confusion will help to next understand this better. :-p
 
  • #154
harrylin said:
OK ... and then, was Lugita's correction in #148 perhaps not right? (and if so, why not?).
I think it was ok. (But I must stress: do not take my word for anything wrt this stuff. I'm trying to sort things out as I go. Eg., I'm apparently missing some, probably simple, thing wrt Herbert's and lugita's proofs, because I still don't understand how they arrive at the conclusions they do.)
You said:
harrylin said:
I do think that hidden variables imply a linear relationship with 100% detection and without "data picking".
And lugita replied:
lugita15 said:
There's a small subtlety here that was covered earlier this thread. You should really use the term "sublinear" or "at most linear". That's because the Bell inequality in (say) Herbert's proof is of the form A is less than or equal to B+C, not of the form A=B+C, which is what's required for linearity.
Which is a more strictly correct way of saying what you said because (I'm assuming) there are other things that can be tweaked besides assumed efficiencies, and data picking which (I assume) can result in different predictions.

But it seems that if Bell's archetypal LR formulation is adhered to, and perfect efficiencies, etc. are assumed, then it predicts a linear correlation between θ and the rate of identical (and nonidentical) paired detections.

harrylin said:
I thought that I knew this, but now I'm confused. Hopefully all this confusion will help to next understand this better. :-p
I'm confused too, but I do feel that I'm learning certain, hopefully important, bits of the puzzle from these threads.
 
  • #155
ThomasT said:
But it seems that if Bell's archetypal LR formulation is adhered to, and perfect efficiencies, etc. are assumed, then it predicts a linear correlation between θ and the rate of identical (and nonidentical) paired detections.
No, even if everything is perfect and nothing is tweaked, Bell's inequality is still an INequality, not an equality, so it cannot guarantee linearity. The reason people often say that local determinism implies a linear correlation is that the linear relationship is the one that gives the closest possible agreement with quantum mechanics. The nonlinear relationships allowed by the Bell inequality lead to an even bigger disagreement, so they're uninteresting.

Anyway ThomasT, have you looked over my reasoning in post #142 in going from step 2 to step 3? Is there anything you disagree with or do not understand in that post?
 
  • #156
lugita15 said:
No, even if everything is perfect and nothing is tweaked, Bell's inequality is still an INequality, not an equality, so it cannot guarantee linearity.
I wasn't referring to a Bell inequality, but rather to the calculation of the correlation coefficient (which is what I take the OP to be about), which, in the ideal, using Bell's form, is a linear function.

lugita15 said:
The reason people often say that local determinism implies a linear correlation is that the linear relationship is the one that gives the closest possible agreement with quantum mechanics.
In one sense, yes, because the linear correlation matches the QM prediction wrt 3 data points. But in another sense, no, because the nonlinear correlations are nonlinear (cosine) correlations (just as the QM correlation is a nonlinear, cosine, correlation), even though they only match the QM prediction at most, afaik, at one data point.

lugita15 said:
Anyway ThomasT, have you looked over my reasoning in post #142 in going from step 2 to step 3? Is there anything you disagree with or do not understand in that post?
Lets look at step 2. I wouldn't phrase the inference(s) that might be made given step 1 in that way. Would this make any difference wrt how one eventually frames the situation and what might thereby be inferred about nature from the experimental results?
 
  • #157
ThomasT said:
Lets look at step 2. I wouldn't phrase the inference(s) that might be made given step 1 in that way. Would this make any difference wrt how one eventually frames the situation and what might thereby be inferred about nature from the experimental results?
Well, you said you thought the phrasing in step 2 was a bit too anthropomorphic, and I responded that instead of saying the particles AGREE in advance what angles to both go through and what angles not to, we can instead say that it is DETERMINED in advance what angles the particles would both go through and what angles they would not go through. Given this rephrasing do you see how step 2 follows from step 1? If not, I can explan the reasoning. (The reasoning from step 1 to step 2, by the way, is the famous EPR argument, which predates Bell.)
 
  • #158
lugita15 said:
Well, you said you thought the phrasing in step 2 was a bit too anthropomorphic, and I responded that instead of saying the particles AGREE in advance what angles to both go through and what angles not to, we can instead say that it is DETERMINED in advance what angles the particles would both go through and what angles they would not go through. Given this rephrasing do you see how step 2 follows from step 1? If not, I can explan the reasoning. (The reasoning from step 1 to step 2, by the way, is the famous EPR argument, which predates Bell.)
Either phrasing allows nonlocal communication between particles.

So, this is what we're on now: what can be inferred from step 1, and be phrased in a non-anthropocentric way, that corresponds to an assumption of locality.

The point, and what I'm wondering about, is exactly where the assumption of locality enters into your and Herbert's proofs.

Your step 2 doesn't qualify as a locality assumption. It just says that whether the photons will or won't be transmitted by the polarizers is determined in advance of the photons' interaction with the polarizers. Such determination might be due to nonlocal transmissions between the paired photons. Your step 2, as stated, doesn't exclude this.
 
  • #159
ThomasT said:
Either phrasing allows nonlocal communication between particles.

So, this is what we're on now: what can be inferred from step 1, and be phrased in a non-anthropocentric way, that corresponds to an assumption of locality.

The point, and what I'm wondering about, is exactly where the assumption of locality enters into your and Herbert's proofs.

Your step 2 doesn't qualify as a locality assumption. It just says that whether the photons will or won't be transmitted by the polarizers is determined in advance of the photons' interaction with the polarizers. Such determination might be due to nonlocal transmissions between the paired photons. Your step 2, as stated, doesn't exclude this.
You're right, there can be some nonlocal theories in which it is determined in advance which angles the photons would both go through and which ones they won't. But Step 2 doesn't say that ONLY local deterministic theories are such that the good and bad angles are determined in advance. It just says that ALL local deterministic theories have the good and bad angles determined in advance. Other kinds of theories may also satisfy this condition, in which case they too will lead to a Bell inequality.
 
  • #160
lugita15 said:
You're right, there can be some nonlocal theories in which it is determined in advance which angles the photons would both go through and which ones they won't. But Step 2 doesn't say that ONLY local deterministic theories are such that the good and bad angles are determined in advance. It just says that ALL local deterministic theories have the good and bad angles determined in advance. Other kinds of theories may also satisfy this condition, in which case they too will lead to a Bell inequality.
Ok, so your step 2 doesn't provide a criterion for distinguishing local from nonlocal. So how does any step that follows from your step 2 do that?

Suppose we restate the inference (step 2) from step 1 to say that entangeled photons have a relationship due to a local common cause (such as emission from the same atom during the same atomic transition a la Aspect and atomic cascades)? Then how might step 3 be stated? (Keeping in mind that, wrt the restated step 2, we still haven't encoded a locality condition into our line of reasoning.)

Since step 4 is the conclusion, then step 3 has to be the explicitly stated, and uniquely local, locality condition.

What's your locality condition/criterion?

It can't be your current step 3, because it doesn't follow from the known behavior of light wrt crossed polarizers, or from steps 1 and 2.

What I'm, eventually, getting at is that your and Herbert's proofs are insufficient. Bell's analysis is necessary, and sufficient, to show that Bell-LR models of quantum entanglement are ruled out. What it might mean beyond that is, imo, an open question.
 
Last edited:
  • #161
ThomasT said:
lugita15 said:
The reason people often say that local determinism implies a linear correlation is that the linear relationship is the one that gives the closest possible agreement with quantum mechanics.
In one sense, yes, because the linear correlation matches the QM prediction wrt 3 data points. But in another sense, no, because the nonlinear correlations are nonlinear (cosine) correlations (just as the QM correlation is a nonlinear, cosine, correlation), even though they only match the QM prediction at most, afaik, at one data point.
It's a closest match in terms of smallest difference between the two functions, either absolute or RMS. Let's say we have some arbitrary function F and pin down just two points F(0) = 1 (100% match) and F(∏/2) = 0 (100% mismatch). Then it is easy to show that Bell's theorem requires F(∏/(2n)) ≤ 1 - 1/n, n=1..∞. Points 0, ∏/4 and ∏/2 match QM prediction of cos^2(x) and all other points are strictly below cos^2(x). Behaviour of F between those points can vary in a non-obvious ways, but straight line is still the closest fit.
 

Attachments

  • test.png
    test.png
    4.2 KB · Views: 430
  • #162
Delta Kilo said:
It's a closest match in terms of smallest difference between the two functions, either absolute or RMS.
Yes, and thanks for the illustration. My point was only that rate of coincidental detection would be expected, given the known behavior of light, to vary nonlinearly as θ varies, and that a linear correlation would, given the known behavior of light, be unexpected -- in a, presumably, local deterministic world.
 
  • #163
ThomasT said:
Ok, so your step 2 doesn't provide a criterion for distinguishing local from nonlocal. So how does any step that follows from your step 2 do that?
It's true that local deterministic theories are not the only theories that satisfy the condition described in step 2; some nonlocal theories satisfy it as well. But the important point is that ALL local deterministic theories satisfy it. If I wanted to, I could have stated my conclusion as, all local deterministic theories and some nonlocal theories contradict the experimental predictions of QM. But nonlocal theories that satisfy the condition described in step 2 aren't really interesting, so I don't usually talk about them.
Since step 4 is the conclusion, then step 3 has to be the explicitly stated, and uniquely local, locality condition.
No, step 3 is not a locality condition, just a trivial application of the transitive property of equality.
What's your locality condition/criterion?
Strictly speaking, none of my steps constitute a locality condition. Step 2 describes a condition that is satisfied by ALL local deterministic theories, but not ONLY local deterministic theories.
It can't be your current step 3, because it doesn't follow from the known behavior of light wrt crossed polarizers, or from steps 1 and 2.
Step 3 does follow from step 2. If you still disagree, look at my post #142 and tell me what you don't understand or disagree with.
What I'm, eventually, getting at is that your and Herbert's proofs are insufficient.
Why are they insufficient?
 
  • #164
ThomasT and I continued this discussion for a bit offline, but now I'm returning to this thread. Here is my umpteenth restatement of http://quantumtantra.com/bell2.html, which hopefully makes clearer the salient points in the reasoning:

1. Entangled photons always have identical behavior when sent through polarizers oriented at identical angles.
2. It is determined in advance what polarizer angles the photons would both go through and what angles the photons would both not go through.
3. If the results at -30° and 0° differ, then either the results at -30° and 0° differ or the results at 0° and 30° differ. (For short we say: If C, then A or B.)
4. P(C)≤P(A or B) (P denotes probability)
5. P(A or B)≤P(A)+P(B)
6. P(C)≤P(A)+P(B)

Where A denotes statement "The result at -30° differs from the result at 0°", B denotes the statement "The result at 0° differs from the result at 30°", and C denotes the statement "The result at -30° differs from the result at 30°".

Let me walk through the proof. Step 1 is an experimental prediction of quantum mechanics, and a pretty well-tested one at that (neglecting loopholes and superdeterminism).

Step 2, probably the most important step, is a consequence of local determinism: if there are no nonlocal influences, then the behavior of photon 1 when hitting a polarizer 1 oriented at angle x cannot depend on the setting y of the distant polarizer 2, so its behavior at any given angle x must be determined in advance. And by step 1, the behavior of photon 1 when sent through a polarizer oriented at angle x must be the same as the behavior of photon 2 when sent through an identically oriented polarizer. So we can meaningfully and unambiguously speak about "the result you would get if you sent either of the photons through a polarizer oriented at angle x", or "the result at x" for short, for all angles x, regardless of what angles (say y and z) we happen to actually orient our polarizers at. This is crucial for the rest of the proof, which utilizes the notion of "the result at x" in the phrasing of statements A, B, and C. In fact, another way of saying step 2 for our purposes is "A, B, and C have well-defined predetermined truth values independent of what angles the polarizers happen to measure at."

Step 3 is a trivial consequence of the transitive property of equality. If the results at -30° and 0° are the same and the results at 0° and 30° are the same, then clearly the results at -30° and 30° must be the same. But this is just another way of saying that if the results at -30° and 30° differ, then the results at -30° and 0° must differ or else the results at 0° and 30° must differ, which is precisely step 3.

The rest is smooth sailing. One of the laws of probability says that if the statement "If M then N" is true (i.e. that N is true in all the cases that M is true.), then we can conclude that the probability of M is less than or equal to the probability of N, from which step 4 follows. Another law of probability says that the probability that M or N is true is less than or equal to the probability that M is true plus the probability that N is true, from which step 5 follows. And then step 6 follows from steps 4 and 5.

But step 6, known as a Bell inequality, is in direct contradiction with the experimental predictions of quantum mechanics. According to QM, P(A)=.25 and P(B)=.25, but P(C)=.75, so we actually have P(C)>P(A)+P(B), in direct contradiction to what we have concluded from the assumption of local determinism.

I think that pretty much the only step that can reasonably be disputed is step 2, because it involves some philosophical discussion.
 
  • #165
Now ThomasT has proposed an alternate scenario, in which he says local determinism is in agreement with the predictions of QM, the reasoning above notwithstanding:
Consider a situation involving the production of entangled photon pairs but where polarizers are placed between the emitter and polarizer on each side. Like this:

Alice's detector <--- polarizer a <--- polarizer a_1 <--- Emitter ---> polarizer b_1 ---> polarizer b ---> Bob's detector

Polarizers a_1 and b_1 are kept aligned.
It seems clear to me that when the photons hit a1 and b1, they either both go through or both don't go through since the two polarizers are oriented at the same angle. Either way, their entanglement is broken, and they acquire a state of definite polarization either parallel or perpendicular to the orientation of a1. Assuming they end up polarized parallel, they will go through the polarizers and reach the second pair of polarizers a and b. Then the probability for each of the photons to go through its respective polarizer is the cosine squared of the difference between the polarization angle of the photon and the setting of the polarizer it now encounters. But now the photons are no longer entangled, so these probabilities are independent of each other: even if a and b have the same orientation, it need not be true that the two photons must do the same things. Instead, each photon has an independent probability cos2(x-x1) of going through, where x is the angle setting of polarizers a and b, and x1 is the angle of polarizers a1 and b1.

Thus since we no longer have identical behavior at identical angles a and b, we can no longer speak about "the result at x" without regard to which of the two particles we're talking about, and thus we can no longer say "If C then A or B" and the rest of our reasoning, so for this scenario the logic of the proof does not prevent local determinism from matching the experimental predictions of QM.
 
  • #166
lugita15 said:
But now the photons are no longer entangled, so these probabilities are independent of each other: even if a and b have the same orientation, it need not be true that the two photons must do the same things. Instead, each photon has an independent probability cos2(x-x1) of going through, where x is the angle setting of polarizers a and b, and x1 is the angle of polarizers a1 and b1.

well explained lugita.

can we re-entangle them via entanglement swapping (prior to interaction with the second set of polarizers)?

I ask because, I feel that, this modification in the experiment might result in a stronger proof of the entanglement phenomena.

btw - the above experiment, as suggested by Thomas, provides a more convincing proof as well
 
Last edited:
  • #167
lugita15 said:
Strictly speaking, none of my steps constitute a locality condition.
Ok, so isn't it necessary to include some sort of explicit locality assumption in order to say that your line of reasoning proves that the predictions of QM contradict local determinism?

Taking step 1 as the determinism assumption (ie., determinism means that identical antecedent conditions always produce the same results), then would it be ok to state step 2 as, eg., the assumption that the events on one side of the experiment do not affect the events on the other side?

lugita15 said:
... we no longer have identical behavior at identical angles a and b ...
Ok, you're saying that in the alternate setup that identical settings wrt the analyzing polarizers (polarizers a and b aligned) would not always produce identical results (identical results means that either both detectors register detection or both do not register detection wrt any particular coincidence window).

I'm saying that in the alternate setup you'd still get identical results at identical settings (polarizers a and b aligned), but that the rate of identical detection would be reduced.
 
  • #168
ThomasT said:
Ok, so isn't it necessary to include some sort of explicit locality assumption in order to say that your line of reasoning proves that the predictions of QM contradict local determinism?
The only thing I meant when I said that I don't have a locality condition in the strictest sense is that, it's possible for some (dumb) nonlocal theories to also satisfy the conditions I lay out in the proof. You can have a theory in which there are such things as FTL signals, but it just happens to be the case that photon behavior is independent of distant polarizer settings, not because of relativity, but just because that's the nature of photons. Such a nonlocal theory would satisfy the conditions of the proof, and would thus also be ruled out. So the proof rules out all local deterministic theories and some nonlocal theories as well, but the nonlocal theories it rules out are so uninteresting that I don't usually mention them.
Taking step 1 as the determinism assumption (ie., determinism means that identical antecedent conditions always produce the same results), then would it be ok to state step 2 as, eg., the assumption that the events on one side of the experiment do not affect the events on the other side?
It doesn't matter to me too much how you characterize the two assumptions. The important thing is that you agree that a local determinist must believe in both of them, so that we can unambiguously talk about "the result at x" independent of which of the two photons we're talking about and which angles y and z the polarizers are oriented at. Still, if you want to know how I characterize things, I would say that step 1 is essentially an experimental prediction of QM. I think that saying the two particles have the same antecedent conditions, and thus that step 1 is a consequence of determinism, is a bit too restrictive an assumption, but that doesn't matter one way or another for our purposes. As far as step 2 goes, I think it makes sense to call it an assumption of local determinism, because the important thing is that somehow or other we get to the conclusion that "the result at x" is determined in advance for all x.
Ok, you're saying that in the alternate setup that identical settings wrt the analyzing polarizers (polarizers a and b aligned) would not always produce identical results (identical results means that either both detectors register detection or both do not register detection wrt any particular coincidence window).
That is precisely what I'm saying. Don't you agree that as soon as their polarizations are measured by a1 and b1, the entanglement is broken off and their quantum states of the two photons become definite polarization states?
I'm saying that in the alternate setup you'd still get identical results at identical settings (polarizers a and b aligned)
What is your basis for saying this? This is a simple quantum mechanics problem in which there should be no dispute. What do you disagree with in my analysis of the problem? I could replace words with math if you like.
 
  • #169
lugita15 said:
That is precisely what I'm saying. Don't you agree that as soon as their polarizations are measured by a1 and b1, the entanglement is broken off and their quantum states of the two photons become definite polarization states?
Afaik, the disturbances transmitted by polarizers a1 and b1 and incident on polarizers a and b don't have to be entangled in order for you to get identical results when a and b are aligned. Just that with a1 and b1 in the setup you get a reduced rate of identical detection.

If that's not correct, then what's the predicted rate of different results in the alternate setup?

Wrt the first two steps, ok, so step 2 includes the assumptions of locality and determinism, and step 1 is necessary to get to step 3. They're interchangeable.

I think something like the following would be clearer:

1. Assumption: Determinism holds. (ie., identical antecedent conditions always produce the same results)
2. Assumption: Locality holds. (ie., events on one side of the experiment don't affect events on the other side)

But I understand how you get to 3 from your 1 and 2.
 
  • #170
ThomasT said:
Afaik, the disturbances transmitted by polarizers a1 and b1 and incident on polarizers a and b don't have to be entangled in order for you to get identical results when a and b are aligned.
And what's your basis for saying that?
ThomasT said:
If that's not correct, then what's the predicted rate of different results in the alternate setup?
Let me lay out exactly what the probabilities look like. First, you start out with the photons in an entangled state encounteering polarizers a1 and b1 oriented at the same angle x1, so they either both go through or they both do not go through, and it is a 50-50 chance which of these occurs. If they don't go through, our story ends there and nothing reaches or goes through polarizers a and b. If they go through, they are now each in a quantum state with definite polarization in the x1 direction. They behave like any other photons which have come out of an x1-oriented polarizer, regardless of the fact that they were entangled at one point. So when photon 1 encounters polarizer a, oriented at angle x, it operates according to Malus' law and goes through with probability cos^2(x-x1). And similarly when photon 2 encounters polarizer b, also oriented at angle x, it also goes through with probability cos^2(x-x1). These are independent probabilities, since the photons are now unconnected.

Thus the probability that neither photon makes it through to the end is .5+.5sin^4(x-x1), and the probability that both photons make it through to the end is .5cos^4(x-x1). And clearly these probabilities do not add up to 1, except when x and x1 are the same or they are 90 degrees apart.
ThomasT said:
Wrt the first two steps, ok, so step 2 includes the assumptions of locality and determinism, and step 1 is necessary to get to step 3.
Good, at least we're agreed on that.
ThomasT said:
But I understand how you get to 3 from your 1 and 2.
OK, so you agree that a local determinist cannot possibly disagree with my two assumptions, and you agree that my assumptions are sufficient to get to step 3. And you agreed earlier that from step 3 onward everything is inevitable. So then what is the source of our current disagreement? Do you just believe that the proof has to have some flaw because you think it would work equally well in your alternate scenario? If so, can you present your analysis of the scenario and show how you think it has identical behavior at identical angle settings? I can present my analysis in greater detail if you like.
 
  • #171
lugita15 said:
And what's your basis for saying that?
DrC mentioned in a few threads that there are PDC setups where photons not entangled in polarization give identical results when the analyzing polarizers are aligned, but at other settings the results differ from entanglement results. I vaguely remember a paper that actually recounted such an experiment, but don't have the reference. Maybe DrC will weigh in on this. Calling DrC. (I'll send him a PM on this if he hasn't posted in this thread in the next day or so.)

I just tried to present a simpler situation where, I thought, you'd also get identical results at identical polarizer settings even though the disturbances incident on the analyzing polarizers aren't entangled in polarization.

lugita15 said:
Thus the probability that neither photon makes it through to the end is .5+.5sin^4(x-x1), and the probability that both photons make it through to the end is .5cos^4(x-x1). And clearly these probabilities do not add up to 1, except when x and x1 are the same or they are 90 degrees apart.
We're only talking about the situation where x and x1 are the same (where, equivalently, x-x1 = 0, where Theta = 0, where polarizers a and b are aligned).

So, what you wrote seems to be in agreement with the prediction that the alternate setup will produce identical results at identical settings of the analyzing polarizers.

lugita15 said:
OK, so you agree that a local determinist cannot possibly disagree with my two assumptions, and you agree that my assumptions are sufficient to get to step 3. And you agreed earlier that from step 3 onward everything is inevitable.
Yes.

lugita15 said:
So then what is the source of our current disagreement? Do you just believe that the proof has to have some flaw because you think it would work equally well in your alternate scenario?
If your step 1 applies to nonentanglement setups where the local deterministic (LD) predictions agree with the QM predictions, but where both of those disagree with your prediction, then it would seem that something is wrong in saying that your proof proves that local determinism is incompatible with QM.

If you instead state your local determinism assumptions this way:

1. Assumption: Determinism holds. (ie., identical antecedent conditions always produce the same results)
2. Assumption: Locality holds. (ie., events on one side of the experiment don't affect events on the other side)

Then, do these assumptions lead to,

If C, then A or B ?

If so, then why not just do it that way?
 
Last edited:
  • #172
lugita15 said:
1. Entangled photons always have identical behavior when sent through polarizers oriented at identical angles.
2. It is determined in advance what polarizer angles the photons would both go through and what angles the photons would both not go through.
3. If the results at -30° and 0° differ, then either the results at -30° and 0° differ or the results at 0° and 30° differ. (For short we say: If C, then A or B.)
4. P(C)≤P(A or B) (P denotes probability)
5. P(A or B)≤P(A)+P(B)
6. P(C)≤P(A)+P(B)

Where A denotes statement "The result at -30° differs from the result at 0°", B denotes the statement "The result at 0° differs from the result at 30°", and C denotes the statement "The result at -30° differs from the result at 30°".

As usual, the error is hidden in the fuzzy description of the experiment. What is the experiment we are talking about? More specifically, what does "The result at -30° differs from the result at 0°" mean? Let us examine this more closely.

It appears we are comparing an outcome at -30° with an outcome at 0°, for example we have an entangled pair of photons one heads of to the -30 instrument and another to the 0 instrument and we compare if the outcomes match. This makes sense. But then you talk of "The result at 0° differs from the result at 30°". Where did 30° come from? We had two entangled photons which we measured at -30 and 0, all of a sudden 30 appears which would suggest one of the following possibilities:

a) You were magically able to measure two photons at 3 angles (-30°, 0°, +30°)
b) You measured two different pairs of entangled photons.
c) You are not talking about an actual performable experiment but about a hypothetical theoretical what might have been for a single pair.

So which is it? Now let us examine your claim (3).
3. If the results at -30° and 0° differ, then either the results at -30° and 0° differ or the results at 0° and 30° differ. (For short we say: If C, then A or B.)
This statement is true ONLY for the possibilities (a) and (c) above. However any experiments that could ever be performed are of the type (b). QM predictions are for type (b) experiments. It is therefore not surprising that inequalities obtained for (a) and (c) contradict an experiment performed as (b). A type (b) experiment necessarily requires the use of a different set of entangled particles to measure the probabilities of A, B, C. As a result, we have 3 different Kolmogorov probability measures which can not and should not be combined in a single probability expression as has been done in (4). In other words, there is no physical reason to expect the outcome of one set of photons to place constraints on the outcome of a different set of photons in scenario (b), however two outcomes from the same set of photons like in (a) and (c) can legitimately place constrains on a third outcome from the exact same set!

So let me summarize: (3) and (4) are valid ONLY for case (a) and (c) and NOT for case (b). QM predictions and every possible experiment that can ever be performed falls under case (b). Two outcomes from a single set of particles CAN place constraints on a third outcome from the very same set of particles. However, there is no basis in physics or logic for two outcomes from one set of particles to constrain the outcome of a different set of particles not correlated with the first one!

If this is still not clear, I would encourage that you re-read the above bolded paragraph and think about it for a moment. It might also be useful to read-up on "degrees of freedom".

It continues to amaze me that this fact escapes a great majority, and even more sad is the concerted effort to prevent others from understanding, this by those who should know better. I'm tired :rolleyes:
 
  • #173
billschnieder said:
Where did 30° come from? We had two entangled photons which we measured at -30 and 0, all of a sudden 30 appears which would suggest one of the following possibilities:

a) You were magically able to measure two photons at 3 angles (-30°, 0°, +30°)
b) You measured two different pairs of entangled photons.
c) You are not talking about an actual performable experiment but about a hypothetical theoretical what might have been for a single pair.

So which is it? Now let us examine your claim (3).

This statement is true ONLY for the possibilities (a) and (c) above. However any experiments that could ever be performed are of the type (b). QM predictions are for type (b) experiments. It is therefore not surprising that inequalities obtained for (a) and (c) contradict an experiment performed as (b). A type (b) experiment necessarily requires the use of a different set of entangled particles to measure the probabilities of A, B, C. As a result, we have 3 different Kolmogorov probability measures which can not and should not be combined in a single probability expression as has been done in (4). In other words, there is no physical reason to expect the outcome of one set of photons to place constraints on the outcome of a different set of photons in scenario (b), however two outcomes from the same set of photons like in (a) and (c) can legitimately place constrains on a third outcome from the exact same set!

...

It continues to amaze me that this fact escapes a great majority, and even more sad is the concerted effort to prevent others from understanding, this by those who should know better. I'm tired :rolleyes:

This is called realism. That would make it half of local realism, and it is part and parcel of why local realism is rejected post Bell.

Bill, once again you are posting your personal theories which do not follow the mainstream. According to the rules here, you should not post:

"Challenges to mainstream theories (relativity, the Big Bang, etc.) that go beyond current professional discussion"

You need to be citing references for your claims that are from acceptable sources, and we both know that cannot happen as you are basically fringe. You say as much in your last paragraph. I too am tired of following behind you to clean up your misleading statements for casual readers of this and other threads.

Once again, cease or I will report you as I did last time. It is a fact that there are plenty of threads for you to hijack. Please do not make us watch your every post for fringe comments like this. You are an intelligent person who could be helpful here if you would skip the soapbox. This is not the place for fringe comments. Try an unmoderated board instead.
 
  • #174
ThomasT said:
DrC mentioned in a few threads that there are PDC setups where photons not entangled in polarization give identical results when the analyzing polarizers are aligned, but at other settings the results differ from entanglement results. I vaguely remember a paper that actually recounted such an experiment, but don't have the reference. Maybe DrC will weigh in on this. Calling DrC. (I'll send him a PM on this if he hasn't posted in this thread in the next day or so.)

I think the situation you are referring to is as follows:

With a single Type I PDC crystal, you get pairs of photons coming out which have the properties of being entangled on some bases (momentum for example) but are NOT polarization entangled. The input is V> and the output is the pair H>H>. Therefore they match ONLY at the special angles 0/90/etc. They do not match at 45 degrees (for both) or any other angle, instead they follow Product state statistics.

My apologies if something I said implied otherwise. :smile:
 
  • #175
I will repeat myself for those who still were not paying attention:

(3) and (4) are valid ONLY for case (a) and (c) and NOT for case (b). QM predictions and every possible experiment that can ever be performed falls under case (b). Two outcomes from a single set of particles CAN place constraints on a third outcome from the very same set of particles. However, there is no basis in physics or logic for two outcomes from one set of particles to constrain the outcome of a different set of particles not correlated with the first one!

If DrC has something meaningful to say, he will respond to what I said with reasoned arguments why he thinks the above is false.
 
  • #176
ThomasT said:
DrC mentioned in a few threads that there are PDC setups where photons not entangled in polarization give identical results when the analyzing polarizers are aligned, but at other settings the results differ from entanglement results.
As DrChinese said, he was talking about identical behavior when both polarizers are oriented at a particular special angle. That's very different from identical behavior at identical angles for all angles.
ThomasT said:
I just tried to present a simpler situation where, I thought, you'd also get identical results at identical polarizer settings even though the disturbances incident on the analyzing polarizers aren't entangled in polarization.
Well, your scenario doesn't seem to work, and it seems like any such scenario cannot work even in principle.
ThomasT said:
We're only talking about the situation where x and x1 are the same (where, equivalently, x-x1 = 0, where Theta = 0, where polarizers a and b are aligned).
I think you're misunderstanding what x and x1 are. I'm defining x1 to be the (common) orientation of polarizers a1 and b1, and x to be the (common) orientation of a and b.
ThomasT said:
So, what you wrote seems to be in agreement with the prediction that the alternate setup will produce identical results at identical settings of the analyzing polarizers.
No, I'm not in agreement with that, unless by "identical settings" you mean that all four polarizers are aligned, and I doubt you mean that. But I maintain that if polarizers a1 and b1 are oriented at x1, and polarizers a and b are oriented at x, where x and x1 are different, then you no longer have to get identical behavior.
ThomasT said:
If your step 1 applies to nonentanglement setups where the local deterministic (LD) predictions agree with the QM predictions, but where both of those disagree with your prediction, then it would seem that something is wrong in saying that your proof proves that local determinism is incompatible with QM.
But it seems clear to me that step 1, identical behavior at identical angles for all angles, is a special property of quantum entanglement, so the logic doesn't work for nonentanglement setups.
ThomasT said:
If you instead state your local determinism assumptions this way:

1. Assumption: Determinism holds. (ie., identical antecedent conditions always produce the same results)
2. Assumption: Locality holds. (ie., events on one side of the experiment don't affect events on the other side)

Then, do these assumptions lead to,

If C, then A or B *?
These assumptions would suffice to get to "If C, then A or B" if we also assume that the two entangled particles have identical antecedent conditions, which I think is an overly restrictive assumption. I think it's cleaner just to assume identical behavior at identical angles, since it's an experimental prediction of QM.
 
  • #177
Strangely, I am forced to agree with Bill on that. Step 3 of the 'proof' in #164 is only applicable to case (c), that is hypothetical theoretical result for a single pair which cannot be directly measured. The transition to step 4 of the proof is not made explicit and as such is wide open to the kind of attacks we see here.

The missing ingredient is the probability distribution ρ(λ), independent of measurement angles. Having stable probability distribution which does not change from one experiment to another is what holds the whole thing together. It brings the necessary repeatability and allows one to estimate expectation values for different angles in separate experiments.

Frankly, the math of Bell's theorem is so simple, I don't see a point in trying to avoid it. It only leads to unnecessary confusion.
 
  • #178
Delta Kilo said:
Strangely, I am forced to agree with Bill on that. Step 3 of the 'proof' in #164 is only applicable to case (c), that is hypothetical theoretical result for a single pair which cannot be directly measured. The transition to step 4 of the proof is not made explicit and as such is wide open to the kind of attacks we see here.

The missing ingredient is the probability distribution ρ(λ), independent of measurement angles. Having stable probability distribution which does not change from one experiment to another is what holds the whole thing together. It brings the necessary repeatability and allows one to estimate expectation values for different angles in separate experiments.

Frankly, the math of Bell's theorem is so simple, I don't see a point in trying to avoid it. It only leads to unnecessary confusion.

Now he has managed to derail you too. LOL. You have to remember that Bill's real point has nothing to do with lugita15's proof, he is trying to say that counterfactual reasoning does not have a physical basis and also does not have a basis in QM. Both of these go without saying, counterfactual cases are not physical by definition. But they clearly exist in the local realistic world, which is what Bell rules out. lugita15's example is perfect, and Bill is using intentionally convoluted logic to push his desired conclusion.

Obviously, lugita15's example follows Bell and Bell should not be in question here. Look at the title of the thread and you will see what a good job Bill has done with his latest hijack.
 
  • #179
DrChinese said:
I think the situation you are referring to is as follows:

With a single Type I PDC crystal, you get pairs of photons coming out which have the properties of being entangled on some bases (momentum for example) but are NOT polarization entangled. The input is V> and the output is the pair H>H>. Therefore they match ONLY at the special angles 0/90/etc. They do not match at 45 degrees (for both) or any other angle, instead they follow Product state statistics.

My apologies if something I said implied otherwise. :smile:
Ok, thanks. I had misunderstood the situation. Not your fault.

A bit off topic, but I'm curious, wrt this situation how do the results vary for other orientations (the orientations that don't always produce identical results) of the aligned polarizers?
 
  • #180
lugita15 said:
I think you're misunderstanding what x and x1 are. I'm defining x1 to be the (common) orientation of polarizers a1 and b1, and x to be the (common) orientation of a and b.
Ok. I misunderstood.
lugita15 said:
I maintain that if polarizers a1 and b1 are oriented at x1, and polarizers a and b are oriented at x, where x and x1 are different, then you no longer have to get identical behavior.
Ok. When x and x1 are aligned, then you'd always get identical results, and as x is offset from x1 then the percentage of identical results would vary as cos2|x-x1|. Is that correct?

Anyway, it appears that my critique of your argument using the alternate setup doesn't work.

lugita15 said:
But it seems clear to me that step 1, identical behavior at identical angles for all angles, is a special property of quantum entanglement, so the logic doesn't work for nonentanglement setups.
Yes, that seems to be the case. Thanks.

As far as I understand then, your argument does seem valid wrt showing that, wrt entanglement setups, the predictions of QM are incompatible with the assumption(s) of local determinism.

But I haven't thoroughly considered bill's or DK's objections yet.
 
  • #181
ThomasT said:
But I haven't thoroughly considered bill's or DK's objections yet.
My only objection is to replacing math with handwaving. It makes it all too easy to overlook some small detail and leave the proof open to attacks. Sorry if I didn't make myself clear.
 
  • #182
billschnieder said:
As usual, the error is hidden in the fuzzy description of the experiment. What is the experiment we are talking about?
We are talking about the experiment discussed by Herbert http://quantumtantra.com/bell2.html. Basically, it involves sending two polarization-entangled photons to two different polarizers, set independently by two people.
More specifically, what does "The result at -30° differs from the result at 0°" mean?
You have told me before that you believe in counterfactual definiteness, in the sense that the question "What would happen if you send this photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x?" always has a well-defined answer for all angles x, regardless of whether you happen to actually send the photon through a polarizer oriented at that particular angle. Of course, you can phrase this question in different ways based on whether you did or did not carry out the measurement; if you did carry out it becomes "What result did you get when you sent the photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x", and if you didn't it becomes "What result would you have gotten if you had sent the photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x?". But that is just the fault of linguistics, and the basic question is the same regardless of whether in any particular case it happens to be a factual question or a counterfactual question, since in either case you admitted that the question is valid and has a meaningful answer.

And since you believe in local determinism, for you the fact of identical behavior (of the two photons in entangled pair) at identical angle settings (of the two polarizers) implies that the answer to this question must be determined in advance for all angles x. And not only that, the fact of identical behavior at identical angle settings also implies that the answers to the question for the two photons must be the same for all angles x. Thus for all angles x we can meaningfully talk (even if we don't know what it is) about "the result we would have if we send either photon in this pair through a polarizer oriented at angle x" independent of which of the two photons we're talking about or what angle settings we choose for the two polarizers when we send the two photons through. It is this long thing in quotes that we abbreviate as "the result at angle x".

So when I say "The result at -30° differs from the result at 0°", I really mean "The result you would get if you send either of the photons in the pair through a polarizer oriented at -30° is different from the result you would get if you send either of the photons in the pair through a polarizer oriented at 0°".
Let us examine this more closely.

It appears we are comparing an outcome at -30° with an outcome at 0°, for example we have an entangled pair of photons one heads of to the -30 instrument and another to the 0 instrument and we compare if the outcomes match. This makes sense. But then you talk of "The result at 0° differs from the result at 30°". Where did 30° come from? We had two entangled photons which we measured at -30 and 0, all of a sudden 30 appears which would suggest one of the following possibilities:

a) You were magically able to measure two photons at 3 angles (-30°, 0°, +30°)
b) You measured two different pairs of entangled photons.
c) You are not talking about an actual performable experiment but about a hypothetical theoretical what might have been for a single pair.
I mean possibility c). I am talking about the result I would get if I perform a particular experiment on a particle, regardless of whether I actually perform that experiment. Now how do I connect this to real experiments, which are obviously concerned with possibility b)? I make the crucial assumption, which I expect that you disagree with or think is misleading, that the following two probabilities are always equal:
1. The probability that this photon would go through a polarizer if it is oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is actually oriented at angle x.
2. The probability that this photon would go through a polarizer if it is oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is NOT actually oriented at angle x, but instead some different angle y.

Now why do I assume that these two probabilities are equal? Because I am assuming that the answers to the following two questions are always the same:
1. What result would you get if you send this photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is actually oriented at angle x?
2. What result would you get if you send the photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is NOT oriented at angle x, but instead some different angle y?

And why do I assume that these questions have the same answer? That seems to me to be a consequence the no-conspiracy condition: the properties (or answers to questions) that are predetermined cannot depend on the specific measurement decisions that are going to be made later, since by assumption those decisions are free and independent.

I hope that clarifies some of my reasoning.
 
  • #183
Delta Kilo said:
Strangely, I am forced to agree with Bill on that. Step 3 of the 'proof' in #164 is only applicable to case (c), that is hypothetical theoretical result for a single pair which cannot be directly measured.
Yes, but even if we can't directly measure "the result at x" (meaning "the result we would get if we send either of the photons through polarizer oriented angle x") for all angles x, the assumption of counterfactual definiteness still allows us to talk meaningfully about it even if we don't know what it is.
The transition to step 4 of the proof is not made explicit and as such is wide open to the kind of attacks we see here.
The reasoning required in getting from step 3 to step 4 is utterly trivial. It is a basis law of probability that if the statement "If M then N" is true, then the probability of M is less than or equal to the probability of N. So if the statement "If C then A or B" is true, then the probability of C is less than or equal to the probability of A or B.
The missing ingredient is the probability distribution ρ(λ), independent of measurement angles. Having stable probability distribution which does not change from one experiment to another is what holds the whole thing together. It brings the necessary repeatability and allows one to estimate expectation values for different angles in separate experiments.
I don't think any discussion about the distribution of hidden variables is required. All we need to do is use the no-conspiracy condition to link measured probabilities of outcomes to unmeasured (i.e. "hypothetical") probabiities of outcomes.
Frankly, the math of Bell's theorem is so simple, I don't see a point in trying to avoid it. It only leads to unnecessary confusion.
To me, Bell's original math, for instance integration over hidden variables, is unnecessarily complicated. It often obscures salient philosophical points in the reasoning, such as how locality creates the necessity of hidden variables. So I much prefer a proof like Herbert's, even if it carries the vaguaries of natural language, because I am confident that the reasoning can be made precise.
 
  • #184
lugita15 said:
I hope that clarifies some of my reasoning.

No it doesn't because you did not adress what I said at all:

You said you were referring to (c). However, QM predictions and every possible experiment that can ever be performed falls under case (b). Two outcomes from a single set of particles CAN place constraints on a third outcome from the very same set of particles. However, there is no basis in physics or logic for two outcomes from one set of particles to constrain the outcome of a different set of particles not correlated with the first one!


How does your reasoning survive the above? I do not yet see from your response that you even understand the criticism.

You say:

1. What result would you get if you send this photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is actually oriented at angle x?
2. What result would you get if you send the photon through a polarizer oriented at angle x, given that the polarizer is NOT oriented at angle x, but instead some different angle y?
As explained above, it is well and good so long as we are talking about just the one photon but then you can't compare it to anything QM or experiment will tell you. There is no reason to expect a mathematical relationship between the results at angle "x" and "y" for one photon to be the same as the relationship between the result at "x" for one photon and the result "y" for a different photon not correlated with it. This is pretty much what you are trying to do here and it is wrong.
 
Last edited:
  • #185
ThomasT said:
Ok. When x and x1 are aligned, then you'd always get identical results, and as x is offset from x1 then the percentage of identical results would vary as cos2|x-x1|. Is that correct?
It is true that you get always get identical results when x and x1 are aligned. But if they're not aligned, then the probability that you get identical results is messy: it's .5+.5sin^4(x-x1)+.5cos^4(x-x1) (see post #170 for an explanation).
As far as I understand then, your argument does seem valid wrt showing that, wrt entanglement setups, the predictions of QM are incompatible with the assumption(s) of local determinism.
And that is precisely what I claim the argument achieves. You can come up with (arguably far-fetched) local deterministic explanations of many if not most phenomena in quantum mechanics, but quantum entanglement alone has special preperties that make it different.
But I haven't thoroughly considered bill's or DK's objections yet.
You have a few different options. You can abandon local determinism, you can hide behind an experimental loophole like zonde does, you can escape via superdeterminism like Nobel Laureate Gerard t'Hooft. But I don't think objections of the kind that E.T. Jaynes or billschneider raise carry any water. It seems like these objections generally question whether proponents of Bell are really applying the no-conspiracy condition, i.e. the exclusion of superdeterminism, correctly in the course of the reasoning.
 
Last edited:
  • #186
lugita15 said:
But I don't think objections of the kind that E.T. Jaynes or billschneider raise carry any water. It seems like these objections generally question whether proponents of Bell are really applying the no-conspiracy condition, i.e. the exclusion of superdeterminism, correctly in the course of the reasoning.
Like I thought, you do not even understand the argument. Assuming that you want to understand it, let me put it in even simpler terms. The triangle inequality gives you a relationship between the three sides of a single triangle AB + BC >= AC. It is valid for a single triangle but it is not valid if you take AB from one triangle and BC from a different triangle and AC from yet another triangle.

The argument which you refused to address above is telling you that for a single triangle, the lengths AB and BC place constraints on the third length AC by virtue of the fact that they belong to the same triangle (this is what the inequality is all about). But the lengths AB and BC from two separate triangles can not possibly place any constraints on the length AC of a third triangle! This is exactly the naive mistake you and others keep making over and over except using probabilities to do it. :cry:
 
  • #187
billschnieder said:
No it doesn't because you did not adress what I said at all:

You said you were referring to (c). However, QM predictions and every possible experiment that can ever be performed falls under case (b). Two outcomes from a single set of particles CAN place constraints on a third outcome from the very same set of particles. However, there is no basis in physics or logic for two outcomes from one set of particles to constrain the outcome of a different set of particles not correlated with the first one!


How does your reasoning survive the above?
I thought I did address this, but let me try again. We send numerous photon pairs through the polarizers, orienting the two polarizers at a variety of angle settings. Sometimes we turn the polarizers to the specific angle settings x and y, other times we don't. We observe that we when we do turn the two polarizers to x and y, we get that the probability that the photons do the same thing when sent through these polarizers is a certain number p. From this we conclude, via the reasoning I lay out in my post #182, that even for the photon pairs for which we don't turn the two polarizers to x and y, it is still true that we would have a probability p of the photons doing the same thing if we do turn the polarizers to the angles x and y. We are assuming that the photons we don't subject to a certain experiment would, if we do subject them to that experiment, behave the same as those that we do subject to that experiment, because how can the question of what would a photon do under circumstance x be dependent on whether it is actually under circumstance x? After all, the photons presumably do not "know" yet whether they will face cricumstance x, so don't you believe that the photon's behavior under all possible circumstances is predetermined and thus independent of the circumstances it faces?
 
  • #188
billschnieder said:
Like I thought, you do not even understand the argument. Assuming that you want to understand it, let me put it in even simpler terms. The triangle inequality gives you a relationship between the three sides of a single triangle AB + BC >= AC. It is valid for a single triangle but it is not valid if you take AB from one triangle and BC from a different triangle and AC from yet another triangle.
I am certainly willing to try to understand your point of view, and I apologize if I do not at the moment. I agree that it would be invalid to take sides of arbitrary triangles and claim that they must satisfy the triangle inequality. But I think what I'm doing is akin to arguing that the three triangles must be congruent, and thus we can freely plug in side lengths from any of the three triangles into the inequality.
 
  • #189
lugita15 said:
Assuming they end up polarized parallel, they will go through the polarizers and reach the second pair of polarizers a and b. Then the probability for each of the photons to go through its respective polarizer is the cosine squared of the difference between the polarization angle of the photon and the setting of the polarizer it now encounters. But now the photons are no longer entangled, so these probabilities are independent of each other: even if a and b have the same orientation, it need not be true that the two photons must do the same things. Instead, each photon has an independent probability cos2(x-x1) of going through, where x is the angle setting of polarizers a and b, and x1 is the angle of polarizers a1 and b1.

just to make sure we got your post above correctly...

Case 1: let's assume a1 and b1 are aligned to each other and polarizers a and b are aligned to each other (but not to a1 and b1)

i.e. a1 and b1 are at, say -- 0 degrees and a1 and b1 are at, say -- 30 degrees.

in that case the photons will show exactly same behavior at a1 and b1...however when they reach a and b...they might not show same behavior?
i.e. photon a might pass through polarizer a, however its not necessary that photon b will pass through polarizer b?

Case 2: all four are aligned i.e. a1 is aligned to b1 and a and b

i.e. a1, b1, a, b all are at, say -- 0 degrees

if the photons pass through a1 and b1, what can we say about their behavior at a and b?
 
Last edited:
  • #190
San K said:
just to make sure we got your post above correctly...

Case 1: let's assume a1 and b1 are aligned to each other and polarizers a and b are aligned to each other (but not to a1 and b1)

i.e. a1 and b1 are at, say -- 0 degrees and a1 and b1 are at, say -- 30 degrees.

in that case the photons will show exactly same behavior at a1 and b1...however when they reach a and b...they might not show same behavior?
i.e. photon a might pass through polarizer a, however its not necessary that photon b will pass through polarizer b?
Yes, exactly. One photon may go through and the other may not (see post #170 for all the probabilities).
San K said:
Case 2: all four are aligned i.e. a1 is aligned to b1 and a and b

i.e. a1, b1, a, b all are at, say -- 0 degrees

if the photons pass through a1 and b1, what can we say about their behavior at a and b?
They will both be guaranteed to go through. Think about it, once they go through a1 and b1, they lose their entanglement and become polarized in the 0 degree direction. Thus they have a 100% probability of going through another 0 degree polarizer.

That's a general rule: once a photon has come out of one polarizer, regardless of whether it's entangled or not, it will now be polarized in the direction of the polarizer and thus will go through any number of subsequent polarizers oriented in the same direction.
 
Last edited:
  • #191
lugita15 said:
I agree that it would be invalid to take sides of arbitrary triangles and claim that they must satisfy the triangle inequality. But I think what I'm doing is akin to arguing that the three triangles must be congruent, and thus we can freely plug in side lengths from any of the three triangles into the inequality.
Well, no, I'm afraid this is not going to work. The individual triangles are not congruent and it would be wrong to plug side lengths from different triangles into the inequality. This is exactly the kind of things Bill is talking about.

The correct analogy would be a source continuously spewing out lots and lots of triangles of all sorts of sizes and shapes. The inequality obviously holds for the average values of side lengths of all triangles. Now the key feature of the theorem is that given large enough run, we can correctly estimate the averages by measuring only some small percentage of all triangles and only one side at a time, provided the source is not influenced by our choice of which side of which triangle to measure.
 
  • #192
Delta Kilo said:
Well, no, I'm afraid this is not going to work. The individual triangles are not congruent and it would be wrong to plug side lengths from different triangles into the inequality. This is exactly the kind of things Bill is talking about.

The correct analogy would be a source continuously spewing out lots and lots of triangles of all sorts of sizes and shapes. The inequality obviously holds for the average values of side lengths of all triangles. Now the key feature of the theorem is that given large enough run, we can correctly estimate the averages by measuring only some small percentage of all triangles and only one side at a time, provided the source is not influenced by our choice of which side of which triangle to measure.
Finally a good example - thanks! (And of course, the sample must not be biased in some way).
 
  • #193
Delta Kilo said:
Well, no, I'm afraid this is not going to work. The individual triangles are not congruent and it would be wrong to plug side lengths from different triangles into the inequality. This is exactly the kind of things Bill is talking about.
Well, I think I'm interpreting the triangle analogy a bit differently from you. For me, an individual triangle corresponds to the set of all photon pairs for which the polarizers are set to some particular angle settings x and y. And the side lengths of a triangle correspond to probabilities. So we have three triangles we're interested in, corresponding to orienting the polarizers to -30° and 0°, 0° and 30°, and -30° and 30°. For each of the triangles, we only know one of the side lengths. For instance, for the angle settings -30° and 0° we only know the answer to the question "what is the probability that, for a randomly chosen particle pair, the result at -30° differs from the result at 0°?"

Now billschneider is raising the objection that I am taking one side length out of each of these triangles, since that's all I know, and I am plugging them into the triangle inequality. I plead guilty to that charge, but I have good reason, namely that I am arguing that the three triangles are congruent. In other words, I am arguing that following two questions have the same answer, even though the first one is found experimentally and the second is not:
1. Out of the particle pairs for which you actually orient the polarizers at -30° and 0°, what is the percentage of particle pairs for which the two photons would give different results at -30° and 0°?
2. Out of the particle pairs for which you actually orient the polarizers at (say) 0° and 30°, what is the percentage of particle pairs for which the two photons would give different results at -30° and 0°?

And my basis for asserting this, for equating the measured probability and the unmeasured (and presumably unmeasurable) probability, is an application of the no-conspiracy condition. So this seems to be the dividing line between proponents of Bell and people like billschneider: it is a disagreement about whether the no-conspiracy condition is being applied property.
 
  • #194
Delta Kilo said:
My only objection is to replacing math with handwaving. It makes it all too easy to overlook some small detail and leave the proof open to attacks. Sorry if I didn't make myself clear.
My misunderstandings are nobody's fault but my own. :smile: What I'm trying to do is precede/accompany/interpret the mathematical representation(s) with some sort of conceptual understanding.

I currently have no doubt that Bell's (and Herbert's and lugita15's) local hidden variable (local realistic, local determistic) formulation(s) is (are), definitively, incompatible with QM (and experiment) wrt entanglement setups. The only question in my mind has to do with interpreting the meaning (ie., what might be reasonably inferred about the underlying reality) of Bell's (and equivalent) theorem(s). That is, do experimental violations of Bell-type inequalities imply the existence of nonlocal transmissions in nature, or is there some other explanation for their violation that would preclude/supercede that inference? It's wrt that question that I find Bill's (and others) objections to Bell's (and Bell-type) formulation(s) at least worthy of consideration (insofar as I think that I don't yet really understand them, and insofar as I have this intuitive sense that there really is a way of understanding BI violations that does preclude/supercede the inference of nonlocality in nature).
 
Last edited:
  • #195
ThomasT said:
As far as I understand then, your argument does seem valid wrt showing that, wrt entanglement setups, the predictions of QM are incompatible with the assumption(s) of local determinism.
lugita15 said:
And that is precisely what I claim the argument achieves.
Ok, we're basically agreed on that then. And thanks for taking the time for us to hash out your argument via email.

Let me qualify my above statement somewhat. To wit, in my understanding, your argument is valid wrt showing that, wrt entanglement setups, the predictions of QM are incompatible with a particular formulation involving the assumption(s) of local determinism.

lugita15 said:
... quantum entanglement alone has special preperties that make it different.
I'm not so sure about that. That is, I think it just might boil down to entangled entities having motional properties that are related in classically understandable ways. And, of course, maybe not. The problem is that the extant experimental evidence doesn't definitively answer that question. Just not enough data yet.
 
  • #196
ThomasT said:
Ok, we're basically agreed on that then. And thanks for taking the time for us to hash out your argument via email.

Let me qualify my above statement somewhat. To wit, in my understanding, your argument is valid wrt showing that, wrt entanglement setups, the predictions of QM are incompatible with a particular formulation involving the assumption(s) of local determinism.
What do you mean a particular formulation? Do you believe that there is any step in my proof that any local determinist could possibly disagree with, even in principle? I thought you agreed with me that step 1 is an experimental prediction of QM, step 2 is a logical consequence of local determinism, step 3 follows from steps 1 and 2, and steps 4-6 are just application of the laws of probability. So where am I "formulating" or restricting things in any way?
 
  • #197
lugita15 said:
What do you mean a particular formulation? Do you believe that there is any step in my proof that any local determinist could possibly disagree with, even in principle? I thought you agreed with me that step 1 is an experimental prediction of QM, step 2 is a logical consequence of local determinism, step 3 follows from steps 1 and 2, and steps 4-6 are just application of the laws of probability. So where am I "formulating" or restricting things in any way?
The particular form of steps 1 and 2 doesn't matter, but their content has to be some sort of expression of the assumptions of locality and determinism.

It then follows that:

3. If C, then A or B
4. P(C)≤P(A or B) (P denotes probability)
5. P(A or B)≤P(A)+P(B)
6. P(C)≤P(A)+P(B)

Where:
C = different results at (-30_30)
A = different results at (-30_0)
B = different results at (30_0)
-------------------------------------------
Your conclusion, based on the way you've formulated your line of reasoning, is that the assumptions of locality and determinism necessarily lead to the prediction in your step 6. (a prediction which is incompatible with QM and experiment).

But I, being a local determinist, might have a somewhat different way of looking at the experimental situation, which might be compatible (or at least not incompatible) with the assumptions of locality and determinism.

The salient point will be that you have not taken into consideration the known behavior of light wrt crossed polarizers in situations where locality and determinism are not (at least not normally or historically) in question.
 
  • #198
ThomasT said:
The particular form of steps 1 and 2 doesn't matter, but their content has to be some sort of expression of the assumptions of locality and determinism.

It then follows that:

3. If C, then A or B
4. P(C)≤P(A or B) (P denotes probability)
5. P(A or B)≤P(A)+P(B)
6. P(C)≤P(A)+P(B)

Where:
C = different results at (-30_30)
A = different results at (-30_0)
B = different results at (30_0)
-------------------------------------------
Your conclusion, based on the way you've formulated your line of reasoning, is that the assumptions of locality and determinism necessarily lead to the prediction in your step 6. (a prediction which is incompatible with QM and experiment). [..]
Hi Tom, that is wrong: as far as we know, no experiment has provided such hypothetical (perhaps even impossible) results. We discussed that in the thread on Herbert's proof, which is still open: https://www.physicsforums.com/showthread.php?t=589134
 
  • #199
harrylin said:
Hi Tom, that is wrong ...
Hi Harry, what's wrong?
 
  • #200
ThomasT said:
Hi Harry, what's wrong?
The word "experiment" - as elaborated in the thread on Herbert's proof. Real experimental results are not as Herbert claims.
 
Back
Top