QLogic
- 44
- 18
But you get Hawking radiation from using QFT on a curved background.
And what does this have to do with whether black holes radiate or not?QLogic said:The star undergoes a process initially similar to collapse into a black hole, but the process doesn't reach the stage of the forming of a horizon.
That's what I was wondering above. Basically if the collapse stops there is no black hole to radiate and since Hawking radiation is radiation from a black hole it means there is no Hawking radiation.martinbn said:And what does this have to do with whether black holes radiate or not?
Yes. This is not questioned: QFT on a curved background predicts that a BH resulting from a collapse radiates.QLogic said:So the only way to stop a black hole from radiating in QFT on curved spacetimes is to have no black hole.
This isn't my understanding of Hawking radiation. Hawking radiation is usually defined as radiation that results from the state restricted to observables outside the horizon being a mixed state of KMS form.Elias1960 said:There is a mass M, if it is of an actually collapsing star or a BH is irrelevant, because what we can measure outside is anyway the same. Hawking radiation is simply thermal radiation with a particular temperature depending on this mass M. If we see it coming from the direction of a BH candidate, and trace back the corresponding classical light ray, it ends (starts) from the collapsing surface before horizon creation
Maybe some people consider it that way, but IMHO it makes no sense.QLogic said:This isn't my understanding of Hawking radiation. Hawking radiation is usually defined as radiation that results from the state restricted to observables outside the horizon being a mixed state of KMS form.
In Hawking's derivation, the Hawking modes are those modes which go through the star during the collapse and, because of the change which happens while they are inside, appear different than they have started, thus, differ from the vacuum modes. To name this a "fully kinematic effect in the post-horizon formation spacetime" is at best misleading (but I would guess simply nonsense). You need the element of change, without it there is no Hawking radiation. Which is what the paperQLogic said:If you have a star, i.e. no horizon, the mixed state has quite a different form that lacks Hawking radiation's completely thermal profile. Also Hawking radiation does not originate from the surface of the star since it's a fully kinematic effect in the post-horizon formation spacetime.
Elias1960 said:Maybe some people consider it that way, but IMHO it makes no sense.
I've given two papers, one from an expert on QFT in curved spacetime where the fact that it is a kinematic effect is not only mentioned but described as "well known". I can give several other sources that say this. One of the papers even explains exactly how it is a kinematic effect. What is actually wrong with what Visser is saying?Elias1960 said:"fully kinematic effect in the post-horizon formation spacetime" is at best misleading (but I would guess simply nonsense)
It's not thermal until a horizon has formed. Prior to the formation of the horizon the vacuum has a statistical profile that differs from the Minkowski profile but it's not yet thermal so it usually isn't called radiation.Elias1960 said:As long as the collapse continues, the change of the vacuum state continues, thus, new radiation appears.
Of course. The radiation is still a property of the state itself though, not of the dynamics. Hawking radiation is a property of the statistics inherent in the vacuum. You need a horizon for states to have those statistics and the horizon itself can only be created by the dynamics, but the radiation is not produced by the collapse dynamics that form the horizon. It's simply a property of the state.Elias1960 said:proves for a Hawking-like situation, but which is a quite general principle which follow from the way Hawking radiation is derived - it is caused by the difference between the time-evolved in-vacuum and the out-vacuum. But without change, the vacuum is stable and therefore there is no difference
That it ignores the trans-Planckian problem.QLogic said:I've given two papers, one from an expert on QFT in curved spacetime where the fact that it is a kinematic effect is not only mentioned but described as "well known". I can give several other sources that say this. One of the papers even explains exactly how it is a kinematic effect. What is actually wrong with what Visser is saying?
If you use Schwarzschild time, the horizon never forms. So, the radiation will be never thermal. In fact, the difference is completely negligible already in the Planckian region.QLogic said:It's not thermal until a horizon has formed. Prior to the formation of the horizon the vacuum has a statistical profile that differs from the Minkowski profile but it's not yet thermal so it usually isn't called [Hawking?] radiation.
A radiation which stops immediately after the dynamics stops and therefore the state remains unchanged, and you need a horizon to have it even if in Schwarzschild coordinates you have no horizon at any finite time. Sorry, I continue to consider such claims as misleading at best.QLogic said:The radiation is still a property of the state itself though, not of the dynamics. Hawking radiation is a property of the statistics inherent in the vacuum. You need a horizon for states to have those statistics ...
I have no doubt that this is textbook terminology. There is no doubt that I'm questioning the mainstream approach, given that (better as far as) it ignores the trans-Planckian problem. Any textbook which introduces Hawking radiation but does not discuss the trans-Planckian problem is misleading at best. In democratic physics, you can easily find the 51% votes to prove me wrong.QLogic said:I will say as a side note that I am the one using standard terminology here. It's difficult to have a discussion if you don't stick to standard terminology and in standard terminology Hawking radiation is kinematic. It's a bit strange to have to argue for textbook terminology.
That it's a statistical property of a state restricted to observables outside the horizon has nothing to do with the Trans-Planckian problem.Elias1960 said:That it ignores the trans-Planckian problem.
It doesn't stop. Prior to the hole's formation there is no Hawking radiation. After the horizon forms there is. The radiation emitted during collapse discussed in Padmanabhan's paper is not Hawking radiation.Elias1960 said:A radiation which stops immediately after the dynamics stops
QLogic said:That it's a statistical property of a state restricted to observables outside the horizon has nothing to do with the Trans-Planckian problem.
This would be a contradiction with relativistic causality or relativistic symmetry.QLogic said:That it's a statistical property of a state restricted to observables outside the horizon ...
It doesn't stop. Prior to the hole's formation there is no Hawking radiation. After the horizon forms there is.
Elias1960 said:Schwarzschild time covers only the part before horizon formation
What happens during the evaporation process is already part of a different theory, it is not covered by standard semiclassical QFT, because one has, somehow, to incorporate backreaction. How to do this without specifying preferred coordinates is completely unclear.PeterDonis said:This is only true for an "eternal" black hole that never evaporates. If the hole evaporates, it is no longer true that "horizon formation" occurs at ##t = + \infty## in Schwarzschild coordinates.
In fact, the usual definition of Schwarzschild coordinate time doesn't even work in such a spacetime.
Ok, one can formulate it this way. But I think my remark remains correct, given that I specify the time coordinate I use, so that I can use "before" and "after" horizon formation in their usual meaning as referring to the particual system of coordinates used. Those who don't specify the coordinates should live with the fact that their statements can be rejected as false if applied to some systems of coordinates they are false.PeterDonis said:I think a better way of phrasing your underlying (valid) point would be that @QLogic needs to be a lot more specific about exactly what he means by "before" and "after" horizon formation. Most ways of specifying what those terms mean are highly coordinate-dependent. There are ways of doing it in an invariant manner, but it's not easy, and it's not altogether clear whether such an invariant definition has all of the properties he is implicitly assuming.
One can, indeed, use the possibility of a system of coordinates with a time so that the horizon already exists as a reasonable way to give "before horizon formation" and "after horizon formation" a coordinate-independent meaning.PAllen said:A further point is simply that is false that Schwarzschild time only covers events before horizon formation, even in a classical non evaporating collapse. Instead, there is a clear demarcation of exterior events into which horizon formation is the causal future, versus not the causal future, thus possibly present. For the whole region in which horizon formation is not causal future, it is plausible to consider the horizon as currently existing.
But then who cares about Schwarzschild time coordinate? Physics s about coordinate independent statements.Elias1960 said:...
One can, indeed, use the possibility of a system of coordinates with a time so that the horizon already exists as a reasonable way to give "before horizon formation" and "after horizon formation" a coordinate-independent meaning.
But this does not make my claim about the Schwarzschild time coordinate false..
Then one would better avoid talking about "before/after horizon creation" too.PAllen said:But then who cares about Schwarzschild time coordinate? Physics s about coordinate independent statements.
The statement that the horizon is not in the causal future of some exterior event is a coordinate independent statement.Elias1960 said:Then one would better avoid talking about "before/after horizon creation" too.
It is, moreover, far from sure that the theory we need to describe back-effects will not have preferred coordinates.
Elias1960 said:I can use "before" and "after" horizon formation in their usual meaning as referring to the particual system of coordinates used.
Given that we know that the complete solution has such a domain, and we also now that the part not covered is in the causal future of events covered, it makes clearly sense. To claim that it is meaningless is, in my opinion, artificial.PeterDonis said:No, you can't, because standard Schwarzschild coordinates don't cover the horizon, and don't cover the event of horizon formation. So talking about "before" and "after" horizon formation is meaningless in Schwarzschild coordinates.
But translating the everyday "before/after" using such a "not in the causal future" seems quite artificial. I think to use "before/after" as in classical physics, assuming some particular time coordinate which should be identified in the context.PAllen said:The statement that the horizon is not in the causal future of some exterior event is a coordinate independent statement.
Elias1960 said:the part not covered is in the causal future of events covered
Elias1960 said:I think to use "before/after" as in classical physics, assuming some particular time coordinate which should be identified in the context.
??PeterDonis said:This is not correct. The entire region not covered by Schwarzschild exterior coordinates is not in the causal future of the entire region that is covered by Schwarzschild exterior coordinates.
No. Once I know the event is causally after the ones covered by the Schwarzschild time coordinate, I can use the relations "before" and "after" too. This is simply the region where I can assign the Schwarzschild time being ## t=\infty##.PeterDonis said:Then you need to pick a time coordinate that actually distinguishes "before" and "after" the event of horizon formation. The Schwarzschild time coordinate does not.
Elias1960 said:Even if you restrict Schwarzschild time (without necessity) to the part outside the collapsing star, the causal future of this part covers also the whole inner part of the star.
Elias1960 said:This is simply the region where I can assign the Schwarzschild time being ##t=\infty##.
Elias1960 said:One can easily extend exterior Schwarzschild time by some continuation inside the collapsing star if this seems, for whatever reason, necessary.
Elias1960 said:The relevant physical content is that the consideration of the part covered by these coordinates is sufficient to explain completely all what becomes, whenever, visible to the external observer.
You can, but you are not obliged to. If the theory is covariant, you can restrict yourself to one particular choice of coordinates, do all the computations in these coordinates, and present the conclusions in these coordinates too.PeterDonis said:"The region which happens to be covered by these coordinates" is not the same as "these coordinates". As @PAllen has already pointed out, physics is contained in coordinate-independent invariants, and all the claims that need to be made, including the one of yours quoted above, can be made completely independent of any choice of coordinates.
But if all what I want to do is to define (identify correctly) the before-after relationship between pairs of events where at least one is covered by the chart, it is not necessary to switch. For every event A inside the horizon there exists for every value of the time coordinate t an event ##A_t \to A## which is in the chart, has there the time coordinate t, and is in the causal past of A, so that it makes sense to say that ##A_t## is before A independent of any coordinates. Then, for event B inside the chart, with time coordinate ##t_B##, we can say, already using the notion of "before/after" defined by the time of the chart, that B happens before ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## simply because ##t_B < t_B+\varepsilon##. Once t is time-like, both orders are never in conflict with each other. So we can also combine them, and say that B happens before A, given that B happens before ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## and ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## happens before A.PeterDonis said:No, it isn't. If you take the limit ##t \rightarrow \infty## in the Schwarzschild exterior coordinate chart, you get the horizon. You don't get any events inside the horizon. To cover events inside the horizon, you have to switch charts.
Full agreement. If you agree that the region inside the star which is outside the horizon can be covered by some extension of the Schwarzschild time too, and are ready to tolerate that a reference to Schwarzschild time is simply sloppy language for the time coordinate of a system of coordinates on ##\mathbb{R}^4## which covers the inner part of the star outside the horizon as well, and uses Schwarzschild time outside the star, fine.PeterDonis said:We're not talking about inside the collapsing star. We're talking about inside the horizon. Big difference. We all understand that there is a portion of the spacetime region occupied by the collapsing star that is outside the horizon, and that portion can be covered by exterior Schwarzschild coordinates. But the region inside the horizon (which includes both a portion occupied by the collapsing star and a vacuum portion) cannot.
Of course, except for the "not correct". What would be the causal future of a connected set? The natural definition is that an event outside the set itself is in its causal future if it is in the causal future of at least one event of the set. What else? The other natural definition would be that it has to be in the causal future of them all. But then myself tomorrow would be not in the causal future of the actual (as defined by myself via Einstein synchronization) Milky way, so this is hardly plausible.PeterDonis said:No, this is not correct. It is true that there is a portion of the exterior region (outside the horizon) that has the entire interior region (inside the horizon) in its causal future. But this portion is very, very far from being the entire exterior region. And even for the portion of the exterior region that does have the entire interior region in its causal future, the Schwarzschild time coordinate still does not cover that interior region: it goes to infinity as the horizon is approached. An observer in the exterior region must adopt some other time coordinate if he wants to have one that will cover events at and inside the horizon.the causal future of this part covers also the whole inner part of the star.
Elias1960 said:If the theory is covariant, you can restrict yourself to one particular choice of coordinates, do all the computations in these coordinates, and present the conclusions in these coordinates too.
Elias1960 said:if all what I want to do is to define (identify correctly) the before-after relationship between pairs of events where at least one is covered by the chart, it is not necessary to switch.
Elias1960 said:are ready to tolerate that a reference to Schwarzschild time is simply sloppy language for the time coordinate of a system of coordinates on ##\mathbb{R}^4## which covers the inner part of the star outside the horizon as well
Elias1960 said:The natural definition is that an event outside the set itself is in its causal future if it is in the causal future of at least one event of the set. What else?
Elias1960 said:The other natural definition would be that it has to be in the causal future of them all. But then myself tomorrow would be not in the causal future of the actual (as defined by myself via Einstein synchronization) Milky way, so this is hardly plausible.
I have shown that this claim is wrong, by extending the notion of "before" and "after" to particular situations where only one of the events is covered by the chart. Means, in the way I have used them, "before" and "after" can be used in a well-defined and meaningful way, which is compatible with the common sense notions of "before" and "after".PeterDonis said:Having just one of the events covered by the chart is not enough. Both need to be.
I don't understand what you are doing in the rest of this paragraph with trying to define "before" and "after",
Yes, it is. The point being? Coordinate-dependent statements remain meaningful statements once the coordinates are defined. In the usual coordinate-dependent notion, where "A happens before B" means ##t(A) < t(B)##, it may be as well that they are space-like separated. The coordinate-independent statement which follows (but is weaker) is that A is not in the future light cone of B.PeterDonis said:but in any case, for any event ##A## in the exterior region that is not in the past light cone of the event of horizon formation, there are events inside the horizon that are spacelike separated from ##A## and for which no invariant time ordering relative to ##A## can therefore be defined. This is a coordinate-independent statement.
Once the claim is that these coordinates cover only the part before horizon formation, not the whole spacetime, this is obviously impossible.PeterDonis said:I'm not ready to tolerate this unless you can show me such a coordinate chart and demonstrate that it covers the entire spacetime.
So, here it remains to say that we obviously completely disagree about what makes sense to define as notions of before and after some set of events. If I would like to refer to your notions, I would formulate them immediately in terms of light cones, any use of "before" and "after" would only, for obvious reasons, cause confusion. "Before" and "after" make sense in a coordinate-dependent way, partially, as I have shown, even outside the chart.PeterDonis said:That an event outside the set is in its causal future if it is in the causal future of all the events of the set. See below.
Only a very tiny portion of the Milky Way today can possibly causally affect you tomorrow, so you do not want to say that you tomorrow is in the causal future of the entire Milky Way today--only of that tiny portion that can causally affect you tomorrow.
Elias1960 said:I have shown that this claim is wrong, by extending the notion of "before" and "after" to particular situations where only one of the events is covered by the chart.
Elias1960 said:"A happens before B" means ##t(A) < t(B)##
Reread this:PeterDonis said:I don't see how you've done that. Your definition of "before" and "after" uses the time coordinate of the chart:
Obviously this is only well-defined if both A and B are covered by the chart.
So, we have two different partial order relations. One, ##<_1##, is defined between pairs of events inside the chart, the other one, ##<_2##, is the global one restricted to pairs of time-like separated events. Both are compatible with each other. We can combine them. This is a third partial order relation ##<_3## containing both of them. That means, if ## A <_1 B## or ## A <_2 B## then also ## A <_3 B##, and ##<_3## is also transitive.Elias1960 said:But if all what I want to do is to define (identify correctly) the before-after relationship between pairs of events where at least one is covered by the chart, it is not necessary to switch. For every event A inside the horizon there exists for every value of the time coordinate t an event ##A_t \to A## which is in the chart, has there the time coordinate t, and is in the causal past of A, so that it makes sense to say that ##A_t## is before A independent of any coordinates. Then, for event B inside the chart, with time coordinate ##t_B##, we can say, already using the notion of "before/after" defined by the time of the chart, that B happens before ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## simply because ##t_B < t_B+\varepsilon##. Once t is time-like, both orders are never in conflict with each other. So we can also combine them, and say that B happens before A, given that B happens before ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## and ##A_{t_B+\varepsilon}## happens before A.
Elias1960 said:Reread this
I have only ever thought of Peter's definition (of causal future of a set of events) as sensible, and I have never seen yours used anywhere. Just wondering if you have any reference defining your notion. Note that above, you have subtly changed 'causal future of a set of events', which was your prior claim, to simply 'before and after'.Elias1960 said:...So, here it remains to say that we obviously completely disagree about what makes sense to define as notions of before and after some set of events. If I would like to refer to your notions, I would formulate them immediately in terms of light cones, any use of "before" and "after" would only, for obvious reasons, cause confusion. "Before" and "after" make sense in a coordinate-dependent way, partially, as I have shown, even outside the chart.
PAllen said:I have only ever thought of Peter's definition (of causal future of a set of events) as sensible, and I have never seen yours used anywhere. Just wondering if you have any reference defining your notion.
Elias1960 said:The natural definition is that an event outside the set itself is in its causal future if it is in the causal future of at least one event of the set.
Correct, and this is the aim. The argument is useful to reject any claims about something happening only after horizon formation. Such claims have been made, for example, here:PeterDonis said:By the method you describe, I can construct an argument for any event whatever outside the horizon being before any event whatever inside the horizon. So I don't see how your method is useful.
QLogic said:It's not thermal until a horizon has formed. Prior to the formation of the horizon the vacuum has a statistical profile that differs from the Minkowski profile but it's not yet thermal so it usually isn't called radiation.
Feel free to disagree with my use of of words. All I can/have to do is to explain what I mean using this words, and this I have done. I do not claim, or care, that my use is 100% established. This is, last but not least, a forum containing necessarily a lot of informal talk.PAllen said:Note that above, you have subtly changed 'causal future of a set of events', which was your prior claim, to simply 'before and after'.
Note also, I disagree with using the term "actual" to refer the result of convention, even a very useful convention.
Elias1960 said:The argument is useful to reject any claims about something happening only after horizon formation.
Elias1960 said:Feel free to disagree with my use of of words.
Thanks. I can see how that is a useful mathematical definition for proofs. However, it seems to have little utility as a definition of physically meaningful or every day sense of 'before or after', especially for unbounded sets.vis_insita said:Wald, General Relativity, defines ##J^+(S)=\bigcup_{p\in S}J^+(p)##, which looks exactly like the definition @Elias1960 is using.
I have never seen a different definition of ##J^+(S)## (MTW, and Hawking and Ellis seem to use the same) and as far as I understand the discussion (which is admittedly not very far) this seems to be the relevant one. So, I find the objections to this particular point a little surprising.
Given the context of an informal discussion in a forum, I can presuppose that a common sense compatible notion of "before" is used. I was unable to expect that such a discussion will be around this word (which I continue to consider as essentially unproblematic).PeterDonis said:But it can't reject such claims unless you can show that the claim you're trying to reject is using the same definition of "before" as you are.
This is something I can accept. To answer arguments of others, I try to use their language, as far as I'm able to interpret it. This may fail.PeterDonis said:I'm not disagreeing with your use of words in itself. I'm just saying that I don't see how your use of words contributes anything to the discussion. However, to be fair, I don't see how @QLogic's use of words was contributing anything either.
I would consider this example as artificial. If one asks about the future of some set, the set is usually one much less than everything. Then, it may be quite natural to exclude the actual set itself from the future of this set. This can be done explicitly if one likes, replacing ##J^+(S)=\bigcup_{p\in S}J^+(p)## which obviously contains S by ##\left(\bigcup_{p\in S}J^+(p)\right)\setminus S##. But to exclude beyond this regions where every trajectory reaching that region has to go through the set some time before from the future of the set is IMHO simply absurd.PAllen said:Consider Minkowski space as a whole. This definition, applied to all of Minkowski space as a set, says all of Minkowski space is in its own causal future and also in its own causal past. I think most people's common sense would be that the future of 'all there ever was or will be' is empty, similarly for the past, which follows from definition @PeterDonis proposed as the physically meaningful one.
Fine. But what would be the point of considering this set? It has certainly no relation to Hawking radiation.PAllen said:Also, of course, in spacetime with BH formed from collapse, for every exterior world line, there will be a first event on it for which the horizon is not all in the causal future. Following this, more and more of the horizon and interior are not in the causal future.
PAllen said:Thanks. I can see how that is a useful mathematical definition for proofs.
However, it seems to have little utility as a definition of physically meaningful or every day sense of 'before or after', especially for unbounded sets.
Consider Minkowski space as a whole. This definition, applied to all of Minkowski space as a set, says all of Minkowski space is in its own causal future and also in its own causal past. I think most people's common sense would be that the future of 'all there ever was or will be' is empty, similarly for the past, which follows from definition @PeterDonis proposed as the physically meaningful one.
I'll dispute your judgment of absurd in a later post, pointing out separate utility for the different notions.Elias1960 said:I would consider this example as artificial. If one asks about the future of some set, the set is usually one much less than everything. Then, it may be quite natural to exclude the actual set itself from the future of this set. This can be done explicitly if one likes, replacing ##J^+(S)=\bigcup_{p\in S}J^+(p)## which obviously contains S by ##\left(\bigcup_{p\in S}J^+(p)\right)\setminus S##. But to exclude beyond this regions where every trajectory reaching that region has to go through the set some time before from the future of the set is IMHO simply absurd.
Fine. But what would be the point of considering this set? It has certainly no relation to Hawking radiation.
Actually, that is exactly the point of the alternative concept.Elias1960 said:Already the fact that for the intersection ##\bigcap_{p\in S}J^+(p)## the causal future of the whole set would be smaller than that of each of its points seems absurd.
Fine. But what would be the point of considering this set? It has certainly no relation to Hawking radiation.
For the world line, I was not talking about any notion at all of future of a set, but the hopefully unambiguous notion of causal future of an event. This statement is true of all external world lines using just the notion of causal future of an event. I cannot cannot conceive of what you can claim as absurd about a statement of the evolution of causal future along a world line.Elias1960 said:About this imho absurd notion we read:
Fine. But what would be the point of considering this set? It has certainly no relation to Hawking radiation.
vis_insita said:It was argued that a before/after-relationship defined relative to one chart may be extended to events which are not covered by that chart. In that situation causal (or chronological) future works in agreement with common sense
vis_insita said:...
This observer is in the strange situation that although his next birthday comes after his previous birthday, he is unable to state any temporal relationship between his next birthday, and some events in the universe that he knows happened simultaneously to his last birthday. Even worse, literally nothing happens to that observer anymore after everything that happened at his last birthday.
As a common sense definition of chronological order this doesn't seem to be a very happy effort either.
...
PAllen said:Instead it was a definition of how to extend the notion of causal future to a set. The key concept of causal future of a point is that the point can influence any future point. To generalize to a set, it seems most meaningful to require the set as a whole can influence can influence any point it it’s causal future.
PeterDonis said:Since Wald and Hawking & Ellis were previously brought up, it seems appropriate to refer to their term for what is being described in the above quote, and what I was describing earlier. That term is Domain of Dependence. In Wald, Chapter 8, the future domain of dependence of an achronal set ##S##, denoted ##D^+(S)##, is defined as the set of all points ##p## in the spacetime such that every past inextendible causal curve through ##p## intersects ##S##. (Note the "every".)
This is interesting and shows that the statement "the whole (future) horizon and interior is in the future of the whole exterior" is an absurd triviality. Replacing the whole exterior with the unique equivalent achronal surface, you find this surface is past infinity. Thus the statement I just gave in quotes is really saying nothing more than "the whole (future) horizon and interior is in the future of past infinity". So what ??!PeterDonis said:A key property of the set ##S## in the above is that it must be achronal, i.e., no two points in the set can be connected by a timelike curve. This restriction is not made in the earlier definition of the causal future of a set; however, if you think about it, it makes sense to restrict attention for practical purposes to the causal future of achronal sets, since if we have a set ##S## that is not achronal, we can always find some achronal set ##S^\prime## that has the same causal future as ##S## (heuristically, we just remove any points in ##S## that are in the causal future of other points in ##S##, since they add nothing to the causal future of ##S## as a whole).