What does it take to solve the measurement problem? (new paper published)

In summary, the paper argues that quantum mechanics has a measurement problem which requires a solution, and that no current interpretation of quantum mechanics solves the problem. They speculate what a solution of the measurement problem might be good for.
  • #106
What is it that's observed, which needs a collapse to describe it? These pseudophilosophical texts are all too enigmatic to make sense.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #107
vanhees71 said:
What is it that's observed, which needs a collapse to describe it?
The fact that we only observe single outcomes. For example, we observe Schrodinger's cat to be either alive or dead, but without the collapse postulate, unitary QM predicts that it ends up in a superposition of alive and dead.
 
  • #108
What has this to do with the collapse? The collapse occurs when the measurement result is obtained, simply as a postulate, i.e., if the state before the measurement is ##\hat{\rho}## and you measure the observable ##A## with the outcome ##a## (an eigenvalue of the corresponding self-adjoint operator ##\hat{A}##), and the eigenspace is spanned by the CONS ##|a,\alpha \rangle##, then it's assumed that after the measurement the state has to be descibed by
$$\hat{\rho}'=\frac{1}{\mathrm{Tr} (\hat{P}_a \hat{\rho} \hat{P}_a)} \hat{P}_a \hat{\rho} \hat{P}_a) \quad \text{with} \quad \hat{P}_a =\sum_{\alpha} |a, \alpha \rangle \langle a,\alpha|.$$
This doesn't explain, why there is "a single outcome".

For me this holds true for very specific kinds of measurements, which can only quite rarely realized for very simple systems. One example are single photons run through a polarization filter. Then FAPP there is a collapse in the above described sense, i.e., if a specific photon goes through the filter it's in a linear-polarization state given by this projection, but in no way can this description explain, whether and why a given specific photon goes through the filter or not. All I can say, given the state before the photon hits the filter is the probablity that it will go through.

For me all this refers to the fundamental postulates of the quantum formalism, which cannot be explained by simpler assumptions of some more comprehensive theory (yet). The fundamental postulates have been figured out by a lot of intertwined observation-model-building processes, and they cannot be mathematically proven or otherwise be inferred. It's as with Newtonian mechanics, where you also have Newton's postulates, which cannot be explained by anything but by the fact that they work (within their realm of applicability).
 
  • #109
vanhees71 said:
What has this to do with the collapse?
You can't get single outcomes without it. With just unitary evolution you don't get single outcomes.

vanhees71 said:
This doesn't explain, why there is "a single outcome".
Whether it "explains" it depends on what you consider to be an "explanation". But mathematically, the state after applying the collapse postulate describes a single outcome having happened. The state before applying the collapse postulate does not.

I suppose one could say all this is interpretation dependent, since on an ensemble interpretation states don't apply to individual runs of experiments anyway.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #110
My question is simply, what has to be explaned?

For me the alleged interpretation of the collapse postulate doesn't make sense. It doesn't explain the single outcome but the preparation procedure by filtering, and whether this is realized in a specific experiment depends on the measurement procedure/manipulation of the object under investigation and cannot be stated as a generally valid postulate.

E.g., you can also prepare a linearly polarized photon by using a polarizing beam splitter (like a birefringent) crystal. This entangles the polarization (H or V wrt. the chosen orientation of the crystal) with the momentum of the photon. Also here you cannot predict, which momentum and thus polarization any given photon will take (except if it's prepared already as being H or V polarized before), and this is not described by a projection but by a unitary operator (for an ideal PBS).
 
  • #111
vanhees71 said:
My question is simply, what has to be explaned?
That's going to depend on what you think needs to be explained.

vanhees71 said:
It doesn't explain the single outcome but the preparation procedure by filtering
A measurement with a single outcome is a preparation procedure by filtering. If I pass a photon through a horizontal polarizer and it is transmitted (instead of absorbed), I can either say I've measured its polarization and the result (single outcome) is "horizontal", or I can say I've filtered it so that only horizontally polarized photons get through. It's the same thing either way.

And either way I need the collapse postulate to get to the final state where I just have a horizontally polarized photon in the output beam of the polarizer. If I just use unitary evolution, I get a superposition of "horizontally polarized photon in the output beam of the polarizer" and "vertically polarized photon absorbed by the polarizer".
 
  • #112
No, it doesn't need to be a preparation procedure. E.g., a photon usually a photon is detected via the photoelectric effect and then is gone and not prepared in another state. Of course, when doing a filter measurement, it's described FAPP by the projection/collapse postulate. This is of course not described by a unitary evolution, since it's described within the "open-quantum-system formalism", i.e., you "trace out" the equipment the photon is interacting with to be measured and, maybe, prepared in a new state.
 
  • #113
vanhees71 said:
Of course, when doing a filter measurement, it's described FAPP by the projection/collapse postulate.
This is also the case for a photon measured (and destroyed) by a detector. Otherwise you wouldn't be able to explain why just one detector fires in any experiment with multiple detectors (for example, a beam splitter with a detector in each output arm). Unitary evolution predicts a superposition of "detector A fires" and "detector B fires" for a case like that.
 
  • #114
We always detect one photon only once (as also with massive particles). That's why Born introduced the probability interpretation of the quantum state in contradiction with Schrödinger's original interpretation as a classical-field description of particles. Born's rule, in my opinion, is also simply one of the other independent postulates of QT, and it has nothing to do with the collapse postulate.
 
  • #115
vanhees71 said:
We always detect one photon only once
Of course, I'm not saying we don't. I'm saying that if we only use unitary evolution and do not use the collapse postulate, QM does not predict this. It predicts a superposition of detection by different detetors, not a single detection by just one detector.
 
  • Like
Likes Simple question
  • #116
vanhees71 said:
That's why Born introduced the probability interpretation of the quantum state
Yes, but that "interpretation" still doesn't narrow down very much. Advocates of all of the known QM interpretations say that they are consistent with Born's probability interpretation of the state and the Born rule.

vanhees71 said:
Born's rule, in my opinion, is also simply one of the other independent postulates of QT, and it has nothing to do with the collapse postulate.
Yes, that's how we view them in our 7 Basic Rules.
 
  • #117
It's of course again a matter of interpretation. For me the meaning of the state is strictly probabilistic, i.e., a single-photon state tells me the probability to find the photon with a detector at a given position (note, it's not the position of the photon, because a photon has no position observable in the usual sense) and, if I bother to measure it, a given polarization. It's not to be interpreted in a classical-field sense. This was the original interpretation by Schrödinger of his wave function for a (nonrelativistic massive) particle, i.e., Schrödinger thought he could describe the electron as a classical field rather than as a classical point particle, but of course pretty soon it turned out that this is incompatible with what's observed, i.e., an electron is detected always as a point but not as a continuously smeared charge distribution as is predicted by the Schrödinger equation, when interpreting the wave function as a classical field with ##-e|\psi(t,\vec{x})|^2## as a continuous charge distribution. That's why Schrödinger introduced the probabilistic interpretation, and it's the only consistent interpretation of the quantum state until today. As with any fundamental law you can only explain how the physicists historically came to this theory, including its interpretation (in the sense of how the mathematical description has to be applied to the description of real-world observations and measurements), but you cannot explain "why it must be so", except you find some new, more comprehensive theory, for which QT follows in some approximate sense. So far we neither have such a more comprehensive theory nor do we have any idea, whether there's any need for it.

The one big issue, of course, is the question of quantum gravity (or in your preferred geometric interpretation of gravity a quantum theory of spacetime), but I don't think that this has anything to do with the measurement (pseudo-)problem of the philosophers. It's simply lack of empirical guidance that pushes some theorists into the right ansatz for the resolution of this quibble.
 
  • #118
vanhees71 said:
Of course there are (approximations of) ideal von Neumann "filter measurements", e.g., using a polarization filter, which lets through only photons with linear polarization in a given direction. Then the projection postulate holds, and you have a kind of "collapse of the state".
What about the Stern-Gerlach apparatus that measures spin of a massive particle? Would you say that the projection postulate holds in this case?
 
  • #119
vanhees71 said:
This doesn't explain, why there is "a single outcome".
The minimal statistical interpretation also does not explain why there is a single outcome.
 
  • #120
vanhees71 said:
My question is simply, what has to be explaned?
From my perspective, the collapse just declares in a simplified way that the agents expectation is changed after an information update. It is just a "reset" required before again applying unitary evolution. What needs to be explained is the detailed HOW the interaction/observation by the agent is processed and revise the expectation of the agent.

As the unitary evolution only defines the agents expectations - in between - information updates, what happens AT the "information updates" is like some boundary process, that is left unexplained in QM.

I view this missing thing as an internal process of the agent. And the process of how the agents state is "changed" by post-processing new input, seems to me to be like a "repreparation". But without ensembles. The preparation refers then not to an ensemble, but to the single agents state. That view can still view the agents "state" as isomorphic to the "information about an ensemble" in some cases, but the state of a single agent makes sense always, even when the ensemble realization does not.

Also, if one like I do, think that agents are simply matter systems interacting, what is missing in QM is ultimately to understand how the hamiltonian emerges as two agents interact. The postulated hamiltonian evolution in between measurements, must then be in principle sequence of "collapses".

As long as we don't understand this better, the collapse postulate seems required, but it does itself not really "explain" anything. It's just required to "reset" the evolution after measurements. But the physics of this reset is not understood. This is also the sense is which I see this as connected to the unification quest.

/Fredrik
 
  • #121
I don't understand the issue with single outvomes. How can there be anything else? What is a multiple outcome?
 
  • #122
As I see it:

Given the hamiltonian and unitary evolution (this is input; not "explained") and an initial state, QM just predicts probabilities. So what happens when we make an observation; then obviously we gain new information, that must revise our expectations of the future. This is not explained or described in depth as a physical phenomena in QM - this is "missing". Lacking this, we throw in the "collapse postulate" which explain nothing, but it declares the supposed influence of a single observation of the future expectations, but leaving you unsatisfied.

I think this part in QM leaves alot of space to wish for more.

The heart of the matter is the causal connection between single events and expectations of the future. Ie. how single events, forges the "dice". And the "dice" is in my thinking implicitly defined by the state of the agent. This is the connetion between single event events, and guiding or normative probabilities that we still miss. You can simply assume that you just instantly revise the state after some idealised observation. But I think this glosses over some deeper dynamics. IT describes was is supposed to happen, but not why or how.

So when the agent corresponds to the usual "classical laboratory" watching an atom, then the "dice" is indeed made up by massive amounts of statistics or repeats which matches well the ensemble interpretation. Then a single events will not deform the dice, it takes massive statistics to do so. But this view gets problematic when the "classical agent" is then part of the system, such as the schrödinger cats etc. Resorting to decoherence explanations is I think just a way to curing something with more of the same.

/Fredrik
 
  • #123
Fra said:
From my perspective, the collapse just declares in a simplified way that the agents expectation is changed after an information update. It is just a "reset" required before again applying unitary evolution. What needs to be explained is the detailed HOW the interaction/observation by the agent is processed and revise the expectation of the agent.
In my opinion it has nothing to do with the agent, which state I associate with the system after a measurement but with the specific experiment I'm doing, i.e., with how the measured system interacts with the measurement device. The collapse assumption is only then the right choice for the update of the state after the measurement, if the equipment is realizing (with some good approximation) a filter measurement. Otherwise you have to think about another update of the state.
Fra said:
As the unitary evolution only defines the agents expectations - in between - information updates, what happens AT the "information updates" is like some boundary process, that is left unexplained in QM.
The unitary evolution describes the time evolution of the states (probability amplitudes) for a closed system. What happens to the partial system of interest, follows by "tracing out" the other parts (measurement devices, "environment") and is not a unitary time evolution anymore, and this time evolution includes dissipation and decoherence. The "information update" for us is completely irrelevant to this dynamics. It's just reading off a measurement result from a scale or from a computer file.
 
  • Like
Likes DrChinese
  • #124
martinbn said:
What is a multiple outcome?
If one particle is sent and several detectors respond.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen and vanhees71
  • #125
A. Neumaier said:
If one particle is sent and several detectors respond.
That is still a single outcome.
 
  • Like
Likes gentzen
  • #126
martinbn said:
I don't understand the issue with single outvomes. How can there be anything else? What is a multiple outcome?
There certainly can be other "classical outcomes," which are not single outcomes. You would probably classify such measurements as "weak measurements," and only regard the projective measurements with "single outcomes" as true measurements. Noisy detector readings are sometimes better interpreted as approximations to the expectation value (which could even evolve in time) of the measurement operator, instead of interpreting each individual noisy measurement record as a "single outcome".

Of course, those other "classical outcomes" still don't quality as "multiple outcomes," and especially not as complex superpositions of "single classical outcomes". But this has "theoretical" issues anyway, first it would need a "physically" preferred basis of the Hilbert space, and second some "physical" distinction between i and -i. Both are certainly "doable" to a certain extent, for example i and -i are often associated with time direction, and absorption processes often translate into an imaginary part of some "nearly classical quantity". Still, the whole setup is missing gauge invariance, and even so specific experimental arrangements often come with their preferred gauge fixing, it is still a hard call to claim that quantum mechanics by default would predict such gauge dependent measurement outcomes.

The measurement process in quantum mechanics by default is modelled by Hermitian measurement operators and "possible classical outcomes" that can be associated with such operators. Interpretations like MWI that claim one could do without should be suspicious, by default...
 
  • #127
martinbn said:
That is still a single outcome.
It depends how one counts. Those discussing the unique outcome problem say that there are two outcomes, one at each detector. This is not observed, hence should be explained. The quest for an explanation is the unique outcome problem.

If you count differently, the problem still persists, but there is no longer a simple word for it.
 
  • #128
But the "unique outcome problem" is solved by Born's probabilistic interpretation of the state. So, where's the problem?
 
  • #129
martinbn said:
I don't understand the issue with single outvomes. How can there be anything else? What is a multiple outcome?
… many different answers and discussions by different people …
A. Neumaier said:
This is not observed, hence should be explained. The quest for an explanation is the unique outcome problem.
vanhees71 said:
But the "unique outcome problem" is solved by Born's probabilistic interpretation of the state. So, where's the problem?
I guess martinbn asked why we need an axiom like Born‘s in the first place. And now you come and ask „where‘s the problem“, the „unique outcome problem“ is solved by Born‘s …

Independent of the quality of the different answers and discussions, this reaction feels very strange to me.
 
  • #130
gentzen said:
I guess martinbn asked why we need an axiom like Born‘s in the first place.
No, he explicitly asked for the issue with single outcomes:
martinbn said:
I don't understand the issue with single outcomes. How can there be anything else? What is a multiple outcome?

gentzen said:
the „unique outcome problem“ is solved by Born‘s …
Born's rule doesn't solve this issue but simply postulates it away!

This is the simple-minded way of solving all unexplained issues in physics: simply postulate what needs to be explained! But it gives a false sense of accomplishment.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Quantum Waver, physika, Simple question and 3 others
  • #131
gentzen said:
… many different answers and discussions by different people …I guess martinbn asked why we need an axiom like Born‘s in the first place. And now you come and ask „where‘s the problem“, the „unique outcome problem“ is solved by Born‘s …

Independent of the quality of the different answers and discussions, this reaction feels very strange to me.
Why? Physics is an empirical science, and Schrödinger's interpretation of the physical meaning of his wave function was not in accordance with the observations, i.e., single electrons were not detected as little "smeared clouds of continuous charge distributions" but as dots on a photoplate. On the other hand Schrödinger's ##|\psi(t,\vec{x})|^2## were correctly describing the distributions of these dots when applying his wave equation. So Born draw the conclusion that ##|\psi(t,\vec{x})|^2## describes the probability density for finding an electron at the place ##\vec{x}## (when measured at time ##t##). That with one ingenious insight resolved the wave-particle duality of the old quantum theory. Obviously even today the prize to pay, i.e., that nature is inherently behaving probabilistically, seems to be too high, so that they look for other (deterministic?) "explanations", but that's a philosophical (religious?) rather than scientific issue.
 
  • #132
A. Neumaier said:
No, he explicitly asked for the issue with single outcomes:
Born's rule doesn't solve this issue but simply postulates it away!

This is the simple-minded way of solving all unexplained issues in physics: simply postulate what needs to be explained! But it gives a false sense of accomplishment.
Born's rule indeed does solve this issue by a postulate, which, as anything in the natural sciences, is justified by its consistency with all observations. That's all you need for an accomplishment in physics and, btw, to get a (somewhat belated) Nobel prize ;-)).
 
  • #133
vanhees71 said:
In my opinion it has nothing to do with the agent, which state I associate with the system after a measurement but with the specific experiment I'm doing, i.e., with how the measured system interacts with the measurement device.
It's not unexpected that you see it differently. How the measured system interacts with the measurement device is in my view simply "how the measured system interacts with the agent".

The key difference is the "measurement device" is part of the macroscopic world, which is for all practical purposes never saturated with information about the quantum system. In my general view, this assymmetry holds only as a exceptional limiting case.

vanhees71 said:
The collapse assumption is only then the right choice for the update of the state after the measurement, if the equipment is realizing (with some good approximation) a filter measurement. Otherwise you have to think about another update of the state.
Thinking about this general update of the state is what understanding the state of the agent is about for me.

vanhees71 said:
The unitary evolution describes the time evolution of the states (probability amplitudes) for a closed system.
The general inside agent/observer is always an open system - except in between information updates - where there is unitary evolution IMO, whose form should be followed be selfconsistency of the prior information (state + hamiltonian). This holds until the agent is perturbed again.

But I admit that this esotheric things supposedly become relevant only when considering unification of forces. IF one simply postulates(or experimentally findeS) a hamiltonian, none of the above I write makes sense, because then we are considerinf only effective theories (where the implict observer is FIXED and not actively participating in the interactions except in the idealised way of measuremtns we are used to).

/Fredrik
 
  • #134
A. Neumaier said:
It depends how one counts. Those discussing the unique outcome problem say that there are two outcomes, one at each detector. This is not observed, hence should be explained. The quest for an explanation is the unique outcome problem.

If you count differently, the problem still persists, but there is no longer a simple word for it.
Then the question is why some outcomes dont occur, rather than why a single outcome occurs.
 
  • #135
martinbn said:
Then the question is why some outcomes dont occur, rather than why a single outcome occurs.
Conservation laws apply at all scales. When you send 1 electron, you detect 1 electron.
 
  • #136
The real question is how can the circumstances of these measurements be related to anything else than us? Given that without the collapse postulate and measurement, Nature is fundamentally indeterminate.
*Us is a collective term for agents who can record outcomes in memory for storage
 
  • #137
martinbn said:
Then the question is why some outcomes dont occur, rather than why a single outcome occurs.
CoolMint said:
Conservation laws apply at all scales. When you send 1 electron, you detect 1 electron.
I think the issue is, if you have an experiment that concludes with either detector 1 or detector 2 going off, QM will give you probabilities for these events. But it will also give you probabilities for complementary events built from superpositions, though they do not have to correspond to "both detectors go off". E.g. Considering the state ##\frac{1}{\sqrt{2}}(|D_1\rangle + |D_2\rangle)## $$p(D_1) = \mathrm{tr}|D_1\rangle\langle D_1|\rho$$ $$p(D_2) = \mathrm{tr}|D_2\rangle\langle D_2|\rho$$ $$p(?) = \frac{1}{2}\mathrm{tr}|D_1+D_2\rangle\langle D_1+D_2|\rho$$The third outcome never occurs even though its probability is nonzero.
 
  • #138
CoolMint said:
Conservation laws apply at all scales. When you send 1 electron, you detect 1 electron.
But unitary quantum mechanics implies conservation laws only for the quantum expectations!
 
  • #139
No, quantum mechanics implies conservation laws event by event. There was a short debate about this in connection with the (infamous) Bohr-Kramers theory. This was disproven by Bothe with his coincidence measurements concerning Compton scattering: As to be expected energy-momentum conservation was fulfilled event by event.
 
  • #140
vanhees71 said:
No, quantum mechanics implies conservation laws event by event.
Can you point to a theoretical argument proving this?
vanhees71 said:
There was a short debate about this in connection with the (infamous) Bohr-Kramers theory. This was disproven by Bothe with his coincidence measurements concerning Compton scattering: As to be expected energy-momentum conservation was fulfilled event by event.
This is an experimental proof, not a consequence of quantum mechanics.

Moreover, the argument by @CoolMint was about particle number conservation, for which this experimental proof says nothing.
 
Last edited:

Similar threads

  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
49
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
922
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
25
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
2
Views
784
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
5K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
17
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
12
Views
2K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
27
Views
3K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
11
Replies
376
Views
10K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
2
Replies
42
Views
3K
Back
Top