vanesch said:
Yes, that is I think what Bohmians call "naive operator realism". But according to Bohm we're deluded in thinking there is something such as a definite spin. There are only positions of particles, and "spinor wavefunctions". We're just doing a complicated experiment of interactions of magnetic fields on particles, and see how they move in magnetic fields. But they don't have such a thing as spin. We're DELUDED
Well, you might be, but I'm not!

Seriously though, I think there is a pretty radical difference between the kind of delusion I was talking about in the context of MWI, and the kind of delusion you are thinking of here. In the former case, we really are deluded about everything we believe -- I think the state of the world is such that there's a coffee cup in front of me right now, but it just ain't so, and so on for *everything*.
In Bohmian mechanics, however, we were merely "deluded" in the sense of perhaps too-quickly jumping to a specific model about what it means for a particle to have a spin. We all think, in the back of our minds, that this means electrons are like little rotating charged basketballs with a certain rotation axis -- that's what all the textbooks tell us, right before they tell us that really we're not supposed to think of it that way literally. But we can't help it because they don't tell us how we *are* supposed to think of it literally! Anyway, to whatever extent we do think of spin that way, yes, we are deluded. But that is easily fixable. Now we know how to think of it correctly -- it is a "contextual property" of particles (i.e., not really a property at all!). It is a kind of funny two-valuedness that lives in the wave function and makes the particles act in a certain "two-valued" way in certain experimental arrangements. So be it. If we are wedded to the stupid basketball picture (which we weren't supposed to believe anyway), too bad for us.
By the way, having mentioned the phrase "contextual property", now seems like a good time to explain the cute little illustration that David Albert mentions in his book ("QM and experience", highly recommended). Say we have a spin 1/2 particle (with some particular wf and some particular Q_0) and we send it towards a stern-gerlach device with its B-field gradient pointing in the +z direction. And say that the particle emerges from the "spin up along z" output port of the device. So if we are thinking of the electron not according to the Bohm picture, but as a little rotating basketball, we would say: aha, the spin axis is in the +z direction.
Now rewind, so we have exactly the same particle in exactly the same state coming toward the same SG device, but now rotate the SG device 180 degrees so the B-field gradient is now in the -z direction. What happens? Well, if we believe the electron is a spinning basketball, the "F = - mu dot grad B" force will be in the opposite direction as before, meaning the particle will be deflected down instead of up, meaning it will once again emerge from the output port labelled "spin up along z". That is, if we think of the electron as a spinning basketball, this "upside down" SG device is just as good as the rightsideup device -- they are both devices which "measure the z component of the electron's spin."
However, according to Bohmian mechanics, the particle in the second case will emerge from the "spin DOWN along z" port of the apparatus, assuming it comes in with exactly the same wave function and initial position. Something like: the particle gets pulled into whichever packet it is "on the side of" when the packets start splitting apart in the device. So this means that, if Bohmian mechanics is right, the two devices (rightside up and upside down) are not equivalent -- use one you get one answer, use the other you get a different answer for "the same" question. Of course, the point is just to illustrate that, if Bohm is right, they aren't really the same question at all. Spin measurements don't reveal the value of some pre-existing property, "spin", that particles possesses in addition to other properties (position, mass, charge, ...). In fact spin measurements don't reveal the pre-existing value of anything, i.e., they aren't measurements of anything, i.e., they aren't even really measurements.
This is an example of what it means for spin to be a "contextual property" -- technically, "contextual" means that the value you get depends not just on which QM operator corresponds to your measurement, but more -- how, specifically, that measurement is performed. (The two devices above both correspond to the \sigma_z operator, right? So according to QM, what's the difference between them? They both measure \sigma_z.) But according to Bohm, they are not equivalent. Hence the cautionary remarks about "naive realism about operators."
Hehe, it is funny that I got against my MWI view exactly the same remark: things we measure and observe should correspond to something "real" out there, from ttn, a Bohmian.
They do! I mean, according to Bohm, the "spin measurements" *do* tell you *something* about the real world -- e.g., what the wf of the particle was and/or where the particle was. It's just that you have misinterpreted things if you naively assume that what you learn is the value of some pre-existing "spin" property of the electron. It's not a failure of realism... just a failure of your reasoning!
But ok, Bohmian mechanics rose in my appreciation, honestly. I see it now as a first heroic effort, against all of the Copenhagen stuff, to build a consistent theory.
That's a good statement. You called me a Bohmian, which I guess I am. But I am more of a reactionary, really. It is because Bohm is so good relative to how widely it is known/understood that I feel I should tip the balance slightly in its favor by advocating it. In a different world, where Bohm was well-known and presented as a possible way of thinking about QM in all the textbooks, maybe I'd advocate something else. But it needs a fair hearing.
And - they will have a hard time admitting it - but Bohmians are in fact first-generation MWI-ers ! They postulate reality to the wavefunction, together with its absolute unitary evolution. As such, they do away with the cleveage between "measurement processes" and "physical interactions", the inconsistency in Copenhagen QM, because what Albert, today, considers as a measurement, Bruce, tomorrow, will analyse as a physical interaction. And the wave function comes out totally different.
This is the good part.
I would prefer to think of this as "building a consistent theory, as against Copenhagen" rather than "first generation MWI-ers"... but whatever...
What is terribly ugly, however, is the BLATANT nonlocality in the evolution equations of this token.
Yup. Now you understand why I was at pains to bring out the nonlocality of orthodox Copenhagen QM, too. Bohm is blatantly nonlocal. Orthodox QM is rather vaguely, confusingly, opaquely nonlocal -- it's nonlocal, no question about it, but the whole thing is so damn confusing and fuzzy it's hard to know exactly what it's saying about anything. And this has unfortunately helped Copenhagen maintain its hegemony over hidden variable theories. So I am doing my best to spread the truth and see that Bohm actually gets a fair hearing, instead of being simply ruled out of court because it is nonlocal.
By the way, Bell once said that it was "to the great credit" of Bohm's theory for bringing out the nonlocality that was inside QM all along, but hidden away by all the fuzziness and obscurity regarding measurement and collapse and all that. And of course, Bell was motivated to think about nonlocality when he "saw the impossible done" -- i.e., saw Bohm's papers showing that (contra von Neumann's alleged proof to the contrary) a hidden variable theory *was* possible.
And of course as a Bohmian, I like this perspective. It makes the blatantness of Bohmian nonlocality into a good thing!
It depends just as much as what happens to a proton inside a star on Andromeda as on what you are doing in the lab.
I don't think it is likely that many particles on Earth remain entangled with any particles on andromeda. The decoherence effect is too strong. Of course, in principle, there's nothing to prevent this "wild" nonlocality. You could make a pair of particles in the singlet state and let them fly until they were separated by a billion light years (and shield the hell out of them to keep them entangled) and still, letting one of them enter a region with a certain magnetic field would cause the other, instantaneously, billions of light years away, to deflect.
What is also a bit ugly is to postulate a preferred basis.
One of the nice points made in Roderich Tumulka's dialogue (that I cited a few posts back) is that the idea of a symmetry among different bases is just a myth. The symmetry is broken by the Hamiltonian. As he writes in that paper (if memory serves) "you might as well Fourier transform Maxwell's equations"!
Plus, even leaving that debate aside, if you're going to have a preferred basis, surely the position basis is the most natural, most obvious candidate. Especially if you're thinking of QM as a theory that emerged to describe subatomic *particles* -- particles, if they have any "preferred" property at all, have *positions*.
So, I consider Bohmian mechanics as quite superior to Copenhagen QM, and containing the roots of further improvements. but, as it is, it is too ugly, it breaks too many nice symmetries...
Yup, there are definitely some issues that one can raise against Bohm. No doubt. But I think any reasonable person who really understands both Bohm and orthodox QM, cannot possibly think that orthodox QM is a better theory. I know you still probably prefer MWI, but at least we can agree that Bohm beats Copenhagen hands down.
Now what about all the rest of you Copenhagenish lurkers?