Bell Non Locality, Quantum Non Locality, Weak Locality, CDP

In summary: Actually, the correlation between your garlic crop and onion crop is not a counter-example to the locality condition, because the correlation is not between two distant variables. The water supply, represented by \lambda, is in fact a common cause of both the garlic and onion crops, so the locality condition holds.The claim is that if \lambda is a complete description of the common causal influences on a and b, then the probabilities will factor when conditioned on \lambda. It has to be complete for factorization to hold.
  • #1
morrobay
Gold Member
1,028
1,260
When there are EPR/Bell test inequality violations and no signal faster than light, the terms:
Bell Non Locality, Quantum Non Locality, Weak Locality and the Cluster Decomposition Principle:
Initial state of space like systems can be factorized.
Subsystems remain space like separated.
Then final state can be factorized..
With the following diagram how can the above terms be unified in one comprehensive definition and explanation
for Bell test violations ?
am8qop.jpg
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
morrobay said:
Initial state of space like systems can be factorized.

If this is the case, then the systems are not entangled and there will be no violation of the Bell inequalities. The QM prediction of violations of the Bell inequalities requires that the systems in question are entangled, which means the state of the system as a whole cannot be factorized.
 
  • #3
https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/cluster-decomposition-and-epr-correlations.409861/
I obtained that definition from post # 7 and thought it was in reference to EPR/Bell inequality violations for entangled particles.
And also that this factorization :
p (abIxy,λ) = p (aIx,λ) p (bIy ,λ) is used to derive the inequality : S = (ab) + (ab') + (a'b) - (a'b') ≤ 2
for entangled particles.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
morrobay said:
https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/cluster-decomposition-and-epr-correlations.409861/
I obtained that definition from post # 7 and thought it was in reference to EPR/Bell inequality violations for entangled particles.
And also that this factorization :
p (abIxy,λ) = p (aIx,λ) p (bIy ,λ) is used to derive the inequality : S = (ab) + (ab') + (a'b) - (a'b') ≤ 2
for entangled particles.

Well, that's the heart of Bell's disproof of local hidden variables: Every local hidden variables theory can be "factorized", but an entangled quantum state cannot be. Therefore, entangled quantum states cannot be explained by local hidden variables.
 
  • Like
Likes PeterDonis and vanhees71
  • #5
stevendaryl said:
Well, that's the heart of Bell's disproof of local hidden variables: Every local hidden variables theory can be "factorized", but an entangled quantum state cannot be. Therefore, entangled quantum states cannot be explained by local hidden variables.

Please, where are the errors in the following?

Fact 1: Under the product rule for probabilities (here, wrt EPRB), the following formulation can never be false: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|xy,λ,a). (A)
Explanation: This factorisation is based on these facts: the inclusion of irrelevant conditionals in a probability function is irrelevant; irrelevant conditionals are best eliminated by experimental facts (not by relying on erroneous opinions, hypotheses, etc).

Fact 2: Bell-test experiments confirm the necessity of x and "a" in p(b|xy,λ,a) .
Explanation: "a" and "b" are correlated by the common hidden-variable λ and the angle (x,y) between x and y.

Fact 3: Bell-test experiments confirm that the correlation is law-like.
Explanation: Under EPRB, the law in (A) is: p(b|xy,λ,a) = sin2 ##\tfrac{1}{2}##(x,y). (B)

Fact 4: Many physicists insist that: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ). (C)
Explanation: (C) is called "Bell's locality hypothesis".

Fact 5: There is no justification for thinking that separated local events cannot be correlated as in (A).
Explanation: My garlic crop is correlated with my separate onion crop; the correlated hidden-variable is the separate but correlated underground water-supplies.

Fact 6: Since λ is Bell's random hidden-variable: p(a|x,λ) = p(b|y,λ) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}.## (D)
So under "Bell's locality hypothesis" (C), we must have this permanent error: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ) = ##\tfrac{1}{4}.## (E)
Explanation: (C) is an erroneous hypothesis in that it overlooks the validity of (A) under local-realism when outputs are correlated by the combination of correlated hidden-variables λ and test-settings x and y are correlated by the angle (x,y) between them.

Thanks; N88
 
  • #6
N88 said:
Please, where are the errors in the following?

Fact 1: Under the product rule for probabilities (here, wrt EPRB), the following formulation can never be false: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|xy,λ,a). (A)
Explanation: This factorisation is based on these facts: the inclusion of irrelevant conditionals in a probability function is irrelevant; irrelevant conditionals are best eliminated by experimental facts (not by relying on erroneous opinions, hypotheses, etc).

Fact 2: Bell-test experiments confirm the necessity of x and "a" in p(b|xy,λ,a) .
Explanation: "a" and "b" are correlated by the common hidden-variable λ and the angle (x,y) between x and y.

Fact 3: Bell-test experiments confirm that the correlation is law-like.
Explanation: Under EPRB, the law in (A) is: p(b|xy,λ,a) = sin2 ##\tfrac{1}{2}##(x,y). (B)

Fact 4: Many physicists insist that: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ). (C)
Explanation: (C) is called "Bell's locality hypothesis".

Fact 5: There is no justification for thinking that separated local events cannot be correlated as in (A).
Explanation: My garlic crop is correlated with my separate onion crop; the correlated hidden-variable is the separate but correlated underground water-supplies.

Fact 6: Since λ is Bell's random hidden-variable: p(a|x,λ) = p(b|y,λ) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}.## (D)
So under "Bell's locality hypothesis" (C), we must have this permanent error: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ) = ##\tfrac{1}{4}.## (E)
Explanation: (C) is an erroneous hypothesis in that it overlooks the validity of (A) under local-realism when outputs are correlated by the combination of correlated hidden-variables λ and test-settings x and y are correlated by the angle (x,y) between them.

Thanks; N88

Well, outside of quantum mechanics, there are no counter-examples to the locality condition [itex]P(ab|x,y,\lambda) = P(a|x,\lambda) P(b|y, \lambda)[/itex]. That is, outside of QM, whenever two distant variables are correlated, it is because there is a common cause to each, and they are correlated through that common cause. Of course, assumption (C) is "erroneous"---QM is not locally realistic. Bell's theorem clarifies the way in which it differs from a locally realistic theory.

The correlation between your garlic crop and onion crop is not a counter-example. In that case, [itex]\lambda[/itex] represents the water supply, in common to both.
 
Last edited:
  • #7
stevendaryl said:
Well, outside of quantum mechanics, there are no examples of the locality condition [itex]P(ab|x,y,\lambda) = P(a|x,\lambda) P(b|y, \lambda)[/itex]. That is, outside of QM, whenever two distant variables are correlated, it is because there is a common cause to each, and they are correlated through that common cause. Of course, assumption (C) is "erroneous"---QM is not locally realistic. Bell's theorem clarifies the way in which it differs from a locally realistic theory.

The correlation between your garlic crop and onion crop is not a counter-example. In that case, [itex]\lambda[/itex] represents the water supply, in common to both.

The claim is that if [itex]\lambda[/itex] is a complete description of the common causal influences on [itex]a[/itex] and [itex]b[/itex], then the probabilities will factor when conditioned on [itex]\lambda[/itex]. It has to be complete for factorization to work.
 
  • #8
stevendaryl said:
outside of quantum mechanics, there are no examples of the locality condition

I think you mean that outside of QM there are no examples of violations of the locality condition, correct? QM violates it, but we don't know of any other theory that does.
 
  • Like
Likes stevendaryl
  • #9
stevendaryl said:
Well, outside of quantum mechanics, there are no examples of the locality condition [itex]P(ab|x,y,\lambda) = P(a|x,\lambda) P(b|y, \lambda)[/itex]. That is, outside of QM, whenever two distant variables are correlated, it is because there is a common cause to each, and they are correlated through that common cause. Of course, assumption (C) is "erroneous"---QM is not locally realistic. Bell's theorem clarifies the way in which it differs from a locally realistic theory.

The correlation between your garlic crop and onion crop is not a counter-example. In that case, [itex]\lambda[/itex] represents the water supply, in common to both.
I thought the water-supply, being common to both crops, was an illustrative analogy: equivalent to [itex]\lambda[/itex] being common to both of Bell's factors. No?
 
  • #10
N88 said:
I thought the water-supply, being common to both crops, was an illustrative analogy: equivalent to [itex]\lambda[/itex] being common to both of Bell's factors. No?

Sorry, I think I misunderstood your example. I thought you were arguing that C (the assumption of factorizability) was wrong, and that your example showed it.
 
Last edited:
  • #11
stevendaryl said:
Well, outside of quantum mechanics, there are no counter-examples to the locality condition [itex]P(ab|x,y,\lambda) = P(a|x,\lambda) P(b|y, \lambda)[/itex]. That is, outside of QM, whenever two distant variables are correlated, it is because there is a common cause to each, and they are correlated through that common cause.
No, in classical theory it is as well possible that it is the locality condition which fails.

Suspected criminals A and B make the same claims about what has happened at the crime scene. Is this because that really happened, and they have told the truth, or because A has succeeded to tell his friend B about the questions, and his answer?
 
  • #12
Denis said:
Suspected criminals A and B make the same claims about what has happened at the crime scene. Is this because that really happened, and they have told the truth, or because A has succeeded to tell his friend B about the questions, and his answer?

Neither of these possibilities violate locality. They just postulate different local interactions (at the crime scene, vs. at some other location where A tells B things).
 
  • #13
PeterDonis said:
Neither of these possibilities violate locality. They just postulate different local interactions (at the crime scene, vs. at some other location where A tells B things).
The point was that it violates P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ). With λ being what they have above known before the interrogations, x and y being the questions asked by the interrogators, and a and b their answers.
Of course, the information transfer in the analogy is not violating Einstein causality, but it violates the law of the state, with the police doing everything to prevent it, so it is also a hidden information transfer. And the guys will do everything to hide it. (If they use smuggled mobiles, the communication may be even faster than sound.)

And the aim of this hidden communication is, exactly, to suggest the police to apply the EPR criterion of reality: Once the interrogation of A allowed to correctly predict what B would answer, without influencing B's interrogation in any way, the answer should correspond to some element of reality.
 
  • #14
Denis said:
The point was that it violates P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ). With λ being what they have above known before the interrogations

But the only way for the factorizability condition to be violated here is if ##\lambda## does not include information from the actual crime scene. But that's not how ##\lambda## is supposed to be defined. ##\lambda## is supposed to include all information that could have gotten to both measurements by local means--in relativistic terms, it should include all information that is in the intersection of the past light cones of the two measurement events. That has to include information from the actual crime scene.

With ##\lambda## defined to include information from the actual crime scene, then the factorizability condition can't be violated, since all of the correlations between A's and B's answers can be explained by their common knowledge of what happened at the crime scene. Whether that common knowledge comes from both of them being present at the crime scene, or A communicating it to B afterwards, doesn't matter for factorizability.

Denis said:
the aim of this hidden communication is, exactly, to suggest the police to apply the EPR criterion of reality

Which is violated by quantum mechanics, but not by your scenario. Your scenario does not violate locality; as you admit in the above quote, it shows why the EPR criterion is a good criterion for any scenario that does not involve quantum mechanics. In other words, it shows why classical physics does not violate locality.
 
  • #15
stevendaryl said:
Sorry, I think I misunderstood your example. I thought you were arguing that C (the assumption of factorizability) was wrong, and that your example showed it.

Thanks SD. We need to be careful here because, as I see it, you have responded to my position in two ways and neither is correct (as I understand them). So I trust I'm being sufficiently careful in the 4 points that follow:

1: Re your above reply, I AM arguing that (C) is wrong; ie, experimentally false! And I'm also arguing that my example shows it.

That is, Fact 4 is a fact: Many physicists insist [that "Bell's local realism" can be represented by]: p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ). (C)
Explanation: (C) is called "Bell's locality hypothesis".

But (C) = p(ab|xy,λ) = p(a|x,λ)p(b|y,λ) is false by observation: so "Bell's local realism" or "Bell's locality hypothesis" is immediately false under EPRB. That is, we know that that "a" and "b" will be correlated (logically dependent) : ie, we know the particles are pairwise correlated and we know the detector settings are correlated --- by a function of the angle (x,y). But (C) is the expression for logical-independence! Hence wrong here -- by observation alone.

2: Further, your original reply was this: "Yes, and your water supply example does not violate the factorizability condition." I disagree. My garlic and onion outputs are also logically dependent because of the correlated water supply; ie, two great crops when the water supply is well maintained; two poor crops when the water supply is neglected.

So my water supply example, with its correlated crops, DOES violate the factorizability condition: which is "Bell's locality hypothesis".

3: Regarding Fact 3: Bell-test experiments confirm that the correlation is law-like.
Explanation: Under EPRB, the law in (A) is: p(b=1)|xy,λ,a=1) = sin2##\tfrac{1}{2}##(x,y). (B)

So, even if our knowledge of λ were complete, our related prediction must still be (B); otherwise it would be experimentally falsified.

4. But, further, I do not understand why anyone might believe that we could ever know "hidden-variables" like Bell's λ completely. [Moreover, I am able to derive the correct experimental results without such knowledge and without nonlocality.] So the fundamental tenet of Bell's (C) -- ie, know λ completely -- can never be satisfied. And QM does not require such: for, again in my view, QM is so well-founded that we are able to encode incomplete-information re "hidden-variables" in probability relations AND derive the correct experimental outcomes.

In conclusion: somewhere in the above there must be a "fact" that we disagree about; maybe one that I am confused about.

HTH. Thanks again, N88
 
Last edited:
  • #16
N88 said:
My garlic and onion outputs are also logically dependent because of the correlated water supply

The water supply is part of ##\lambda##, and ##\lambda## appears in both factors in the factorizability condition. So a correlation due to ##\lambda## can hold without the factorizability condition being violated.

To put it in terms of your garlic and onion crops, if we factor out the common cause, the water supply (##\lambda##), there is no residual correlation between the two crops: the garlic crop (##a##) depends only on factors specific to how you grew garlic (##x##), and the onion crop (##b##) depends only on factors specific to how you grew onions (##y##). That is what the factorizability condition expresses, and it will be true for your garlic and onion case. In other words, that case obeys the Bell locality condition.

In QM experiments on entangled particles, however, the above will not be the case: even after you have factored out the common cause (##\lambda##), you still have correlations--the results on the ##a## side of the experiment do not depend solely on ##x##, and the results on the ##b## side of the experiment do not depend solely on ##y##. It's as if, even after factoring out the effect of the water supply (and any other common causes), somehow changing the way you grew garlic changed the yield of your onion crop. That does not happen anywhere outside of QM experiments on entangled particles--those are the only experiments anyone has ever done that violate the Bell locality condition.
 
  • #17
PeterDonis said:
The water supply is part of ##\lambda##, and ##\lambda## appears in both factors in the factorizability condition. So a correlation due to ##\lambda## can hold without the factorizability condition being violated.

To put it in terms of your garlic and onion crops, if we factor out the common cause, the water supply (##\lambda##), there is no residual correlation between the two crops: the garlic crop (##a##) depends only on factors specific to how you grew garlic (##x##), and the onion crop (##b##) depends only on factors specific to how you grew onions (##y##). That is what the factorizability condition expresses, and it will be true for your garlic and onion case. In other words, that case obeys the Bell locality condition.

In QM experiments on entangled particles, however, the above will not be the case: even after you have factored out the common cause (##\lambda##), you still have correlations--the results on the ##a## side of the experiment do not depend solely on ##x##, and the results on the ##b## side of the experiment do not depend solely on ##y##. It's as if, even after factoring out the effect of the water supply (and any other common causes), somehow changing the way you grew garlic changed the yield of your onion crop. That does not happen anywhere outside of QM experiments on entangled particles--those are the only experiments anyone has ever done that violate the Bell locality condition.

It's not clear to me why you "factor out" the common cause?

Let me be clear: the garlic [G] and onion [O] example is in no way meant to reproduce EPRB correlations. But it is meant to be a counterpoint to your following statement (a counterpoint that can be experimentally validated):

  • "To put it in terms of your garlic and onion crops, if we factor out the common cause, the water supply (##\lambda##), there is no residual correlation between the two crops:"

I've cut off the underground water supply (so the test conditions are now X) and still the separated crops are correlated; ie, under X, I now get a good crop of each [G+, O+] half the time, or a poor crop of each [G-, O-] half the time, with no crossovers. So:

P(G+|X) = P(O+|X) = P(G-|X) = P(O-|X) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}##.

P(G+O+|X) = P(G+|X)P(O+|XG+) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}## ## \neq## P(G+|X)P(O+|X).

Given such a clear difference, I take it that our differences must arise from my misunderstanding something?
 
  • #18
N88 said:
I've cut off the underground water supply (so the test conditions are now X) and still the separated crops are correlated

How? Translating this back into Bell's notation, we have eliminated ##\lambda## (the water supply), so the factorizability condition is ##p(ab|xy) = p(a|x) p(b|y)##. If this condition is violated, it means that each crop's yield depends not only on how you grow that crop, but how you grow the other crop. How can that be?

N88 said:
I've cut off the underground water supply (so the test conditions are now X)

No, they aren't. See below.

N88 said:
I take it that our differences must arise from my misunderstanding something?

I think you are misunderstanding Bell's notation. ##x##, in his notation, would correspond to the way you grow your garlic crop: by definition, it only contains factors that are local to the garlic crop. Similarly, ##y## only contains factors that are local to the onion crop. That means that, by hypothesis, and using your binary notation for good (+) or poor (-) crops, we would have

$$
P(O^+|X) = P(O^-|X) = P(G^+|Y) = P(G^-|Y) = \frac{1}{2}
$$

But we would not have ##P(G^+|X) = P(G^-|X)##, unless you are an incompetent garlic grower, and we would not have ##P(O^+|Y) = P(O^-|Y)##, unless you are an incompetent onion grower. In fact, we would expect ##P(G^+|X) > P(G^-|X)## and ##P(O^+|Y) > P(O^-|Y)##, since you are adapting your growth techniques to each crop individually.
 
  • #19
N88 said:
It's not clear to me why you "factor out" the common cause?
I've cut off the underground water supply (so the test conditions are now X) and still the separated crops are correlated; ie, under X, I now get a good crop of each [G+, O+] half the time, or a poor crop of each [G-, O-] half the time, with no crossovers. So:

P(G+|X) = P(O+|X) = P(G-|X) = P(O-|X) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}##.

P(G+O+|X) = P(G+|X)P(O+|XG+) = ##\tfrac{1}{2}## ## \neq## P(G+|X)P(O+|X).

Given such a clear difference, I take it that our differences must arise from my misunderstanding something?

If even after controlling for water supply, there is a correlation between your garlic crop and your onion crop, then that usually means that there is some other common causal influence other than water supply.
 
  • #20
PeterDonis said:
How? Translating this back into Bell's notation, we have eliminated ##\lambda## (the water supply), so the factorizability condition is ##p(ab|xy) = p(a|x) p(b|y)##. If this condition is violated, it means that each crop's yield depends not only on how you grow that crop, but how you grow the other crop. How can that be?

You appear to be confusing logical-implication with causation?? There is no causal influence between the crops; the crop correlations arise from the correlation of the separate local growing conditions (soil, sunlight, rainfall, plough-settings). The outcome correlations in EPRB arise in a similar way; eg, via the correlation of the independent and freely chosen detector settings x and y as a function of their angular difference (x,y).

PeterDonis said:
I think you are misunderstanding Bell's notation. ##x##, in his notation, would correspond to the way you grow your garlic crop: by definition, it only contains factors that are local to the garlic crop. Similarly, ##y## only contains factors that are local to the onion crop. That means that, by hypothesis, and using your binary notation for good (+) or poor (-) crops, we would have

$$
P(O^+|X) = P(O^-|X) = P(G^+|Y) = P(G^-|Y) = \frac{1}{2}
$$

But we would not have ##P(G^+|X) = P(G^-|X)##, unless you are an incompetent garlic grower, and we would not have ##P(O^+|Y) = P(O^-|Y)##, unless you are an incompetent onion grower. In fact, we would expect ##P(G^+|X) > P(G^-|X)## and ##P(O^+|Y) > P(O^-|Y)##, since you are adapting your growth techniques to each crop individually.

With 5000 acres of garlic and 6000 acres of onions, the crops are very much dependent on the weather! Our competence allows us to make good profits from both good and bad crops!

So, to more closely match the Bell-formulation, let's use
$$P(O^+|X) = P(O^-|X) = P(G^+|Y) = P(G^-|Y) = \frac{1}{2}. (J)$$
Then we find agriculturally that
$$
P(O^+G^+|XY) = P(O^+|X) P(G^+|XYO^+) = \frac{1}{2} \neq P(O^+|X)P(G^+|Y). (K)
$$
So now we have the local farming conditions X and Y separated like the x and y in Bell's locality hypothesis. And the farming conditions X and Y are correlated via a function of the associated growing conditions: just like Bell's detector settings x and y are correlated via a function of the associated settings.
 
  • #21
stevendaryl said:
If even after controlling for water supply, there is a correlation between your garlic crop and your onion crop, then that usually means that there is some other common causal influence other than water supply.
Indeed, its called the weather (mostly). Remember, I only removed the underground water-supply. And that was done reluctantly: for reasons that I have yet to understand (but see post above this one). There is apparently some reason to remove λ from Bell's formulation for comparison purposes, but that reasoning is currently beyond me.
 
  • #22
N88 said:
You appear to be confusing logical-implication with causation?? There is no causal influence between the crops; the crop correlations arise from the correlation of the separate local growing conditions (soil, sunlight, rainfall, plough-settings). The outcome correlations in EPRB arise in a similar way; eg, via the correlation of the independent and freely chosen detector settings x and y as a function of their angular difference (x,y).

So the probability of getting a good garlic crop is a function of lots of variables: soil, sunlight, rain, etc. Similarly for an onion crop. Then it's false to say that water supply is the only common causal influence on the two crops. Bell's factorizability condition is only expected to hold if the hidden variable [itex]\lambda[/itex] includes all relevant common causal influences.
 
  • #23
N88 said:
Indeed, its called the weather (mostly).

Then what that means is that [itex]\lambda[/itex] must include both water supply AND weather. Bell's factorizability condition only holds when ALL common causal influences are held constant.
 
  • #24
N88 said:
Indeed, its called the weather (mostly). Remember, I only removed the underground water-supply. And that was done reluctantly: for reasons that I have yet to understand (but see post above this one). There is apparently some reason to remove λ from Bell's formulation for comparison purposes, but that reasoning is currently beyond me.

For simplicity, let's assume that there are two states for the water supply, "good" and "bad. And there are two possible types of weather, "good" and "bad. Then there are four possible values of [itex]\lambda[/itex]:
  1. [itex]\lambda_{++}[/itex]: good water supply and good weather
  2. [itex]\lambda_{+-}[/itex] good water supply and bad weather
  3. [itex]\lambda_{-+}[/itex] bad water supply and good weather
  4. [itex]\lambda_{--}[/itex] bad water supply and bad weather
If water supply and weather are the only variables that are relevant, then

[itex]P(G^+, O^+|\lambda_{++}) = P(G^+|\lambda_{++}) P(O^+ | \lambda_{++})[/itex]
(and similarly for all other values of [itex]\lambda[/itex]).

If you don't control for weather and only control for water supply, then the probabilities will not factor. If you've controlled for every common causal influence, then the probabilities will factor.
 
  • #25
N88 said:
You appear to be confusing logical-implication with causation?

No, I'm just saying that you are confused about how your scenario matches up with Bell's notation and formulas.

N88 said:
the crop correlations arise from the correlation of the separate local growing conditions (soil, sunlight, rainfall, plough-settings)

In other words, the water supply is not the only common factor between the crops, despite what you said earlier. Ok, fine. Then all of these things that correlate between the growing conditions--soil, sunlight, rainfall, plough settings--are all included in ##\lambda##. They aren't included in ##x## and ##y##. That's how Bell defined those variables. If you are using different definitions from his, of course you're going to come up with different formulas. But if you want to compare with Bell's formulas, you need to use his definitions.

N88 said:
With 5000 acres of garlic and 6000 acres of onions, the crops are very much dependent on the weather!

Ok, then weather goes in ##\lambda## as well.

N88 said:
So now we have the local farming conditions X and Y separated like the x and y in Bell's locality hypothesis

No, you don't. See below.

N88 said:
the farming conditions X and Y are correlated

This violates Bell's definitions; by definition, Bell's ##x## and ##y## are uncorrelated.

N88 said:
just like Bell's detector settings x and y are correlated via a function of the associated settings

What "function of the associated settings" are you talking about?
 
  • #26
N88 said:
There is apparently some reason to remove λ from Bell's formulation for comparison purposes

No, only to illustrate what Bell meant by ##\lambda##. See the recent responses from stevendaryl and me.
 
  • #27
PeterDonis said:
But the only way for the factorizability condition to be violated here is if ##\lambda## does not include information from the actual crime scene.
No. It includes everything what above A and B know. If above have been there, that means, it includes all information from the crime scene.

But it does not contain the answer A has invented only during the interrogation to hide what they above have done in reality.
PeterDonis said:
With ##\lambda## defined to include information from the actual crime scene, then the factorizability condition can't be violated, since all of the correlations between A's and B's answers can be explained by their common knowledge of what happened at the crime scene.
Also correlations between lies about what actually happened, lies which have not been planned immediately at the crime scene, simply because above have been unable to know all what the police has been able to find out? Say, the following dialog:

Police: You have said you have left the place late in the afternoon. Please, more details, because you have been seen there at 19:00. When have you left the place?
A: We have left the place 19:30.
Police: Are you sure?
A: Yes, we wanted to see the soccer game which started 20:15 in TV. We have talked about this, I remember, its time to go I have said, else we will miss the begin of the game.
--
Police: You have said you have left the place late in the afternoon. Please, more details, because you have been seen there at 19:00. When have you left the place?
B: We have left the place 19:30.
Police: Are you sure?
B: Yes, we wanted to see the soccer game which started 20:15 in TV. We have talked about this, I remember, its time to go A has said, else we will miss the begin of the game.

Knowledge of the crime scene gives them memories how they have killed C 22:30, and an agreement between them to claim that they have left the place in the late afternoon, because they have not recognized that they have been seen there as late as 19:00, only at 15:00.
PeterDonis said:
Whether that common knowledge comes from both of them being present at the crime scene, or A communicating it to B afterwards, doesn't matter for factorizability.
It matters, because A's memories of the police interrogation are not part of ##\lambda##, thus, not accessible to B if factorizability holds.
PeterDonis said:
Which is violated by quantum mechanics, but not by your scenario. Your scenario does not violate locality; as you admit in the above quote, it shows why the EPR criterion is a good criterion for any scenario that does not involve quantum mechanics. In other words, it shows why classical physics does not violate locality.
No, the EPR criterion is not violated by the dBB interpretation of QM, and, therefore, not by QM. Because in the dBB interpretation of QM EPR holds, but is simply inapplicable, because (as described by the guiding equation) the measurement at A, if done before B, causally influences the outcome measured at B later.
 
  • #28
Denis said:
It includes everything what above A and B know. If above have been there, that means, it includes all information from the crime scene.

Yes, I agree; that's what I was saying in my previous post. And also, if ##\lambda## includes all that information, the factorizability condition will not be violated in your example.

Denis said:
it does not contain the answer A has invented only during the interrogation to hide what they above have done in reality

If A communicates that information to B before the interrogation, then ##\lambda## does include it. And if A does not communicate that information to B before the interrogation, then there will be no correlation between A's and B's answers based on that information alone, which means the factorizability condition will not be violated.

What you appear to be missing is that, if A invents an answer during the interrogation based on information he remembers from the crime scene, and B was also at the crime scene, then A's invention is using information that is in ##\lambda##, so the factorizability condition still holds.

What would violate the factorizability condition is if A invented some answer during the interrogation based solely on, say, the color of his interrogator's eyes, and B invented some answer during his interrogation based solely on, say, the pattern of marks on the wall of his interrogation room, and yet there were still correlations between those particular answers of A and B. But you are not claiming such a thing would happen (and of course it wouldn't in a real world interrogation).

Denis said:
A's memories of the police interrogation are not part of λ

Yes, that's correct (since we are assuming that A and B cannot communicate during the interrogation itself). And that means, as above, that there will be no correlation between A's and B's responses based on A's memories of the interrogation alone, so the factorizability condition will not be violated.

But once again, this requires that A invents an answer purely based on his memories of the interrogation, without using any information remembered from the crime scene (or anything else in ##\lambda##, such as prior communications with B). That's not what you described. What you described is A inventing answers based partly on his memories of the interrogation, and partly on his memories of the crime scene. That means A is using information in ##\lambda##, so his answers being correlated with B's, since B is also using information in ##\lambda##, does not violate the factorizability condition.

Denis said:
in the dBB interpretation of QM EPR holds, but is simply inapplicable, because (as described by the guiding equation) the measurement at A, if done before B, causally influences the outcome measured at B later

This causal influence is nonlocal--it violates Bell's locality condition, which is one of the premises required to derive Bell's inequality. So of course the dBB interpretation predicts violations of Bell's inequalities, just like any other interpretation of QM. This is not "EPR holds, but is simply inapplicable". This a straightforward "EPR is violated" (more precisely, Bell's inequalities are violated), just like any other interpretation of QM.
 
  • #29
PeterDonis said:
What you appear to be missing is that, if A invents an answer during the interrogation based on information he remembers from the crime scene, and B was also at the crime scene, then A's invention is using information that is in ##\lambda##, so the factorizability condition still holds.
Only if A's invention is completely defined by what has really happened on the crime scence. The case when A and B have already at the crime scene prepared their excuse. Which is what my version has deliberately excluded - they were not aware that they have been seen at 19:00, thus, have not prepared a version for this event. A had to invent something new.
PeterDonis said:
What would violate the factorizability condition is if A invented some answer during the interrogation based solely on, say, the color of his interrogator's eyes, and B invented some answer during his interrogation based solely on, say, the pattern of marks on the wall of his interrogation room, and yet there were still correlations between those particular answers of A and B. But you are not claiming such a thing would happen (and of course it wouldn't in a real world interrogation).
Indeed. But there is the other possibility that A told B via an illegal mobile phone connection about his interrogation, and what he has invented.
PeterDonis said:
Yes, that's correct (since we are assuming that A and B cannot communicate during the interrogation itself). And that means, as above, that there will be no correlation between A's and B's responses based on A's memories of the interrogation alone, so the factorizability condition will not be violated.
But the factorizability condition is violated. Because it predicts no correlation between the inventions, based on ##\lambda## alone, but what we observe is a large, 100%, correlation.
PeterDonis said:
But once again, this requires that A invents an answer purely based on his memories of the interrogation, without using any information remembered from the crime scene (or anything else in ##\lambda##, such as prior communications with B).
No, there is no such requirement. He can use what he wants from his memories in ##\lambda##. The only thing which matters is that he has to invent something new.
PeterDonis said:
That's not what you described. What you described is A inventing answers based partly on his memories of the interrogation, and partly on his memories of the crime scene. That means A is using information in ##\lambda##, so his answers being correlated with B's, since B is also using information in ##\lambda##, does not violate the factorizability condition.
There is no such restriction. The example shows that we observe 100% correlation of the answers (and given that it contains a lot of bits, this is already good enough statistics). It can be easily explained if we have the information channel, so that P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|a,y,λ) is all we need. But P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ) does not hold, once a is the result of some invention, which may depend on x (the questions, and something influencing his free decision) as well as on λ. Nothing in these formulas introduces a necessity of some independence of whatever on λ. The difference between the two cases is that P(b|a,y,λ) can depend on what A has answered.

It is the cheated police officer who believes that, given that no hidden information channel exists, P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ) holds. And that this allows to conclude that by receiving A's answer a he has really, with 100% certainty, and without in any way influencing B's following interrogation, been able to predict the outcome of B's interrogation. And that, therefore, B's answer was predefined by λ. Not invented in some way somehow using λ, not. Predefined by λ.
PeterDonis said:
This causal influence is nonlocal--it violates Bell's locality condition, which is one of the premises required to derive Bell's inequality. So of course the dBB interpretation predicts violations of Bell's inequalities, just like any other interpretation of QM. This is not "EPR holds, but is simply inapplicable". This a straightforward "EPR is violated" (more precisely, Bell's inequalities are violated), just like any other interpretation of QM.
Sorry, no. What is violated is - you name it - the locality condition, not realism, not the EPR criterion. Bell's inequalities are not "more precisely" the EPR criterion, but something completely different. Namely a conclusion, which holds only if we apply EPR as well as locality (to get the "predict in no way disturbing" part of the EPR criterion).

In BM, the measurement at A disturbs the measurement at B. In my example, the interrogation of A disturbs the interrogation of B, because A tells B about what happened there and influences his answer. So, in above cases the EPR criterion, which contains the "in no way disturbing" as a condition, is simply not applicable.
 
  • #31
Denis said:
Which is what my version has deliberately excluded - they were not aware that they have been seen at 19:00, thus, have not prepared a version for this event. A had to invent something new.

Denis said:
the factorizability condition is violated. Because it predicts no correlation between the inventions, based on ##\lambda## alone, but what we observe is a large, 100%, correlation.

Then what explains this large, 100% correlation? I assume you are not claiming that A and B are entangled quantum particles and that the interrogators are running EPR experiments on them. So what mechanism are you postulating that explains A's and B's correlated inventions? And why do you think it is consistent with the laws of physics?

In other words, it looks to me like you are saying that the factorizability condition can be violated in a non-QM setting, based on a made up scenario that could never actually happen. Am I reading you correctly?
Denis said:
In my example, the interrogation of A disturbs the interrogation of B, because A tells B about what happened there and influences his answer

I don't get it. I thought you said that A and B did not communicate (except for both being at the crime scene). So how can A tell B what happened in A's interrogation?

If A does tell B about his interrogation, then everything that happened in A's interrogation is part of ##\lambda##, so the factorizability condition is not violated.

You are either very confused or you are changing your scenario at your whim.
 
  • #32
PeterDonis said:
Then what explains this large, 100% correlation?
The hidden communication channel. Namely, A uses the smuggled phone to tell B about the surprise (they have been seen at 19.00) and what he has invented as the reaction. B has understood and acted appropriately. Clearly, a smuggled mobile phone connection between two incarcerated suspects violates laws, but only human laws, not physical laws.

PeterDonis said:
In other words, it looks to me like you are saying that the factorizability condition can be violated in a non-QM setting, based on a made up scenario that could never actually happen. Am I reading you correctly?
No, such things happen all the time. It is the reason why the police tries to prevent communication between suspects in the same crime. It is the reason why these suspects try to communicate, and try to hide the fact of their communication. The suspects want a 100% correlation between their claims, in a way that the police does not know about their communication. Because this suggests the police to apply the EPR principle, and to believe that the correlated claims correspond to reality, instead of being inventions to hide reality.
PeterDonis said:
I don't get it. I thought you said that A and B did not communicate (except for both being at the crime scene). So how can A tell B what happened in A's interrogation?
? I wrote in #13:
Of course, the information transfer in the analogy is not violating Einstein causality, but it violates the law of the state, with the police doing everything to prevent it, so it is also a hidden information transfer. And the guys will do everything to hide it. (If they use smuggled mobiles, the communication may be even faster than sound.)

And the aim of this hidden communication is, exactly, to suggest the police to apply the EPR criterion of reality: Once the interrogation of A allowed to correctly predict what B would answer, without influencing B's interrogation in any way, the answer should correspond to some element of reality.
PeterDonis said:
If A does tell B about his interrogation, then everything that happened in A's interrogation is part of ##\lambda##, so the factorizability condition is not violated.
No. ##\lambda## is what is predefined, what is fixed before the two "measurements" in form of police interrogations. What is transferred is the measurement result of the interrogation of A, that means, a.
PeterDonis said:
You are either very confused or you are changing your scenario at your whim.
Sorry, but I see the confusion on your side.

Here the consistent (quote me if you find some inconsistency) scenario:

##\lambda## the shared memories of A and B about their crime, and their initial version to hide it which failed.
x,y the questions of the interrogators
a,b the answers given by A and B.
we observe 100% correlation. Which is easily explained by the hidden communication.
The police does not know about the hidden communication, thus, thinks that P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ), thus, thinks, using EPR, that the shared excuse has an element of reality, was predefined, was part of their shared memories ##\lambda##. And therefore erroneously concludes, that the excuse is reality.
But the excuse was no reality, it was invented by A during the interrogation and send, violating human law, to B. P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|y,λ) does not hold, instead P(ab|x,y,λ)=P(a|x,λ)P(b|a,y,λ) holds.
 
  • #33
Griffiths writes in https://arxiv.org/abs/1512.01443:
However the derivation of the CHSH version of a Bell inequality, which is Eq. (1) in [1], has as one of its assumptions that Sx, Sz, and other components of spin can be replaced by classical, which is to say commuting, quantities, which have a joint probability distribution, directly contrary, as Fine pointed out, to the principles of quantum mechanics.
This is, again, a case of a very old point made by Bell in Bertlmann's socks and the nature of reality:
It is important to note that to the limited degree to which determinism plays a role in the EPR argument, it is not assumed but inferred. ... It is remarkably difficult to get this point across, that determinism is not a presupposition of the analysis.
It is inferred, using as the EPR principle of reality, as Einstein causality, to prove that the measurement at A really does not disturb the measurement at B.
 
  • #34
Denis said:
Griffiths writes in https://arxiv.org/abs/1512.01443:

This is, again, a case of a very old point made by Bell in Bertlmann's socks and the nature of reality:

It is inferred, using as the EPR principle of reality, as Einstein causality, to prove that the measurement at A really does not disturb the measurement at B.
The EPR principle cannot be used to infer this. Bob's detector angle is random and thus Alice cannot predict with certainty what Bob's outcome is. This is possible only in the case of fixed detector angles and in that case, a local hidden variable explanation is possible with no problems. The fact that the detector angles must be chosen randomly and independently prevents the application of the EPR principle. It would be possible, if the spins along all directions could be measured simultaneously, but as Griffithis points out, this is in direct conflict with the principles of QM.

If you want to apply the EPR principle, you must presuppose that the spins along all angles are simultaneously well-defined.
 
  • #35
Denis said:
The hidden communication channel. Namely, A uses the smuggled phone to tell B about the surprise (they have been seen at 19.00) and what he has invented as the reaction. B has understood and acted appropriately

Ok, then all the information in that conversation is part of ##\lambda##, and the factorizability condition is not violated.

Denis said:
such things happen all the time

People talk on cell phones all the time, sure. But talking on cell phones does not and cannot violate the Bell inequalities. If you are seriously claiming that it can, then you have a serious misunderstanding of the physics involved.

Denis said:
##\lambda## is what is predefined, what is fixed before the two "measurements" in form of police interrogations

That might be your definition, but it's not Bell's definition. Bell's definition is that ##\lambda## includes all information that is available at both measurement events. It doesn't matter how it gets there.

One feature of your scenario that is different from the standard EPR experiment is that your "measurement" events (the interrogations) are timelike separated, not spacelike separated. That means that ##\lambda## can include information that happens after one interrogation but before the other, such as the information A tells B during the cell phone call. As long as the information is available at both interrogations, it goes in ##\lambda##.

If the interrogations were in fact spacelike separated, then you would be correct that ##\lambda## would only include information that happened prior to both interrogations. But if the two interrogations were spacelike separated, A would not be able to use a smuggled cell phone to call B and tell him what happened in his interrogation.

Denis said:
(quote me if you find some inconsistency)

Your definition of ##\lambda## is wrong. See above.
 

Similar threads

Replies
2
Views
957
Replies
12
Views
1K
Replies
50
Views
4K
Replies
1
Views
824
Replies
3
Views
824
Replies
0
Views
752
Replies
4
Views
1K
Replies
93
Views
5K
Replies
6
Views
2K
  • Quantum Physics
3
Replies
87
Views
5K
Back
Top