Gödel’s theorem: larger than proof?

In summary, Gödel's theorem proves that there is a certain self-indicating proposition that is true but non-demonstrable within a certain formulated axiomatic system.
  • #1
stefanow
9
1
It's been a decade or so since I've read Nagel & Newman's presentation of Gödel’s famous proof of incompleteness and although not a mathematician or logician myself I couldn’t help but laugh facing an ingenious logical process bound to prove a banality like “I’m lying - it’s true!”. Gödel’s proof is a masterpiece of mathematical and logical demonstration, but I seriously doubt the metaphysical/platonic implications that many people see in it. It’s a formal refutation of formalism, nothing more, nothing less, a mathematic form of Russell’s paradox or liar’s paradox. Gödel didn’t prove that there are certain true but non demonstrable propositions within a certain axiomatic system, but that there is one certain self-indicating proposition like “this proposition is not demonstrable” which is at once non demonstrable but nevertheless true, and he did that by using a powerful version of diagonal method combined with metamathematical (verbal) assumptions in one or two critical points of his demonstration. I haven’t heard of Gödel or anyone else who finally succeeded in demonstrating the same result with non-self-indicating propositions (like, say, Goldbach’s conjecture), which would be extremely interesting and frustrating ?:) by the way.

So Gödel showed that there is a certain kind of proposition that is non-demonstrable, but at the same time true within a certain formulated axiomatic system. Obviously (hmm..:rolleyes:) such a claim has no meaning with real propositions (propositions that indicate something outside themselves), so Gödel tried it with one self-indicating proposition, which by the way is not a proposition in the common sense and therefore neither true or false as far as our languange game is concerned. It is like saying that something is real but does not exist: the only “something” that corresponds to such a description is nothing. I think that the whole misunderstanding of the significance of Gödel’s proofs derives from his metamathematical use of the word “true” in a context where such a use is nonsensical. Gödel himself used to believe that his proof was something more than a commentary “on formally undecidable propositions of Principia Mathematica and related systems”, so his next logical step was a mathematic proof of the existence of God..
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Self-reference appears not to be essential and the self referential statements are really only self-referential in concept (that is, outside of the language you are expressing them in).

http://www.math.mcgill.ca/rags/JAC/124/self.html

If only I had time, I would use this as an opportunity to learn this stuff more thoroughly, but unfortunately, I probably don't.
 
  • #3
stefanow said:
I haven’t heard of Gödel or anyone else who finally succeeded in demonstrating the same result with non-self-indicating propositions (like, say, Goldbach’s conjecture), which would be extremely interesting and frustrating ?:) by the way.

Goodstein's theorem is the easiest example for a non-mathematician.
 
  • #4
Gödel showed that the Gödel sentence G is true but not provable within formal arithmetic, provided formal arithmetic is consistent, using that G itself can be interpreted as "G is not provable within formal arithmetic",

But G can be reformulated to say that a certain diofantine equation (a polynomial equation in one or several natural number variables with natural number coefficients ) E has no solutions. If E is provable within formal arithmetic, then the proof itself can be used to construct a solution to E.
So Gödel's Theorem has consequences also for "ordinary" arithmetic, in this case diofantine equations.

Also, we have results such as Goodstein's theorem, which pwsnafu mentioned.
 
  • #5
Godel sentence is self-referential, while the claim of the Goodstein's theorem is not self-referential (or is it?).
My question is: Is there a rigorous way to prove that a sentence (or a set of sentences) is self-referential, or is self-referentiallity a property that can be seen only intuitively?

EDIT:
Perhaps an even better formulation of this question is the following. Can self-referentiality of a sentence in a given axiomatic theory be detected within the theory, without looking at it from a meta-theory?
 
Last edited:
  • #6
I think that the self-referential character of G is a metamathematical trait necessary for one in order to be able to apply truth value to G. Otherwise the proposition would be just undecidable (as is proven in the case of Goodstein’s Theorem by Paris-Kirby or the Continuum Hypothesis by Paul Cohen etc.) i.e. neither true nor false within the system’s limitations. Russell had also used self-reference in order to debase Frege’s system and so did Gödel in order to debase Russell’s. I wonder if one could apply some form of Russell's paradox in Gödel’s construction in a manner of “if Gödel’s proof is complete, then excludes itself from its incompleteness claims and thus renders itself incomplete, but this very incompleteness renders it true..o0)”, eventhough Gödel’s proof seems to have been tailored in order to use contradiction for increasing its strength. My memory on the subject could use some refreshment anyway..
 
Last edited:
  • #7
I think the problem is how we can define "self referential" in a stringent way...
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #8
http://www.imm.dtu.dk/~tobo/essay.pdf
This may give an idea of the various forms of self-reference. Note that “Gödel himself had a footnote in his 1931 article… saying that any paradox of self-reference could be used to prove the Incompleteness Theorem”.
 
  • Like
Likes Demystifier
  • #9
Anyway I'd say that the general form of a malicious self-referential sentence could be f(x), only if x=f(x), but would this clear things up?
 
Last edited:

1. What is Gödel's theorem and why is it important in mathematics?

Gödel's theorem, also known as the incompleteness theorem, is a fundamental result in mathematical logic that states any consistent axiomatic system is either incomplete or inconsistent. This means that there will always be true mathematical statements that cannot be proven within a given set of axioms. It is important because it challenges the idea of a complete and consistent set of axioms as the foundation of mathematics.

2. Who is Kurt Gödel and how did he discover this theorem?

Kurt Gödel was an Austrian mathematician and logician who made significant contributions to mathematical logic, the foundations of mathematics, and philosophy of mathematics. He discovered the incompleteness theorem in 1931 while working at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, New Jersey.

3. Can you give an example of a mathematical statement that cannot be proven using Gödel's theorem?

One example is the Continuum Hypothesis, which states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. This statement cannot be proven or disproven using the axioms of set theory, as shown by Gödel's theorem.

4. How does Gödel's theorem relate to other areas of science?

Gödel's theorem has implications in various fields, such as computer science, artificial intelligence, and philosophy. In computer science, it has been used to show the limitations of formal systems and the impossibility of creating a computer program that can prove all true mathematical statements. In philosophy, it has led to discussions about the nature of truth, proof, and the foundations of mathematics.

5. Is Gödel's theorem widely accepted in the scientific community?

Yes, Gödel's theorem is widely accepted and has been extensively studied and verified by mathematicians and logicians. It has been cited as one of the most important and influential results in mathematical logic and has sparked numerous debates and discussions among scientists and philosophers.

Similar threads

  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
16
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
3
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
7
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
4
Views
1K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
4
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
2
Replies
40
Views
6K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
14
Views
2K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
1
Views
3K
  • Set Theory, Logic, Probability, Statistics
Replies
10
Views
2K
Replies
14
Views
2K
Back
Top