Why does time dilation only affect one of the twins?

In summary: B is going to travel so that his clock will appear to tick fast (by comparison) when he is near A and slow when he is far away.
  • #1
ersa17
13
2
I am more confused by the theory of relativity as I start thinking about it. I have a question and it might sound silly but please, correct me if I am wrong.
Suppose, A and B are twins where A is at the Earth, and B is moving on a spacecraft at a speed near to the speed of light. In this scenario, since there is a relative motion between two, time moves slower for the other observer with respect to own frame(i.e. For A, time slows down for B and vice-versa). But the twin paradox says that the twin who makes a trip with high speed and returns back to the Earth seems younger than the twin who is at the Earth. If A and B both see time slowing for each other, why is that only B is younger? Since B sees that time is slowing down for A, shouldn't A be the one who is younger(in B's frame of reference)?
Also, does the direction of speed have any effect on the time dilation(i.e. if moving towards or away from the observer)?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
See this Insight. The main thing you are missing is the relativity of simultaneity (see my signature). B is not an inertial observer and changes rest frames mid-way. In each of the two different rest frames for B (outbound and inbound, respectively), A is indeed time dilated. However, simultaneity in the outbound frame is not the same as simultaneity in the inbound frame, making you miss a large part of A's world line if you just try to blindly apply time dilation.

ersa17 said:
Also, does the direction of speed have any effect on the time dilation(i.e. if moving towards or away from the observer)?
No.
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17, Ibix and vanhees71
  • #3
ersa17 said:
Since B sees that time is slowing down for A, shouldn't A be the one who is younger(in B's frame of reference)?
B’s frame of reference is non-inertial, so the rules for inertial frames do not apply. Things look very different in non inertial frames
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17 and Ibix
  • #4
ersa17 said:
But the twin paradox says that the twin who makes a trip with high speed and returns back to the Earth seems younger than the twin who is at the Earth.
Not quite. "High speed" is never a meaningful phrase unless you specify soeed with respect to something. The twin paradox actually says that the twin who moves non-inertially will be (not seem, actually be) younger than the twin who moves inertially.
ersa17 said:
If A and B both see time slowing for each other
It's not that simple. They don't see the other's clock tick slowly directly. They will see the other's clock appear to tick fast or slow due to the changing light speed delay from the changing distance. Only when they correct for that will they calculate that the other's clock is ticking slowly. This is a point that often isn't made clearly.

The problem is that the calculations that lead to "the other guy's clock is ticking slow" assume that you are both moving inertially, so do not apply to the twin paradox where one of you isn't. You can naively apply the calculation to the outbound and inbound legs of the journey separately but, as Orodruin says, you need to look up the relativity of simultaneity in order to join the results together correctly.
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17
  • #5
ersa17 said:
Why does time dilation affects only one of the twins?
It doesn't. Time dilation is symmetrical and an observational effect. You are confusing it with differential aging, which is NOT symmetrical and is a real effect, not an observational effect. The traveling twin takes a different path through space-time so even though his clock ticks away at one second per second, just as does the clock of his Earthbound twin, his clock gets fewer tics because of the different path through spacetime, thus he ends up younger.
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17 and Ibix
  • #6
Now I believe that I have somewhat understood it. Because of the different worldline, they're traveling in and t ≠ t', even though both the observers see the other observer's time slowing, B is still younger than A. If t = t' then this would have contradicted(or hadn't been possible).
 
  • #8
I want to expand on what Ibix said about actual appearances, and discuss what they'll see and not what they compute:
Ibix said:
It's not that simple. They don't see the other's clock tick slowly directly. They will see the other's clock appear to tick fast or slow due to the changing light speed delay from the changing distance.
ersa17 said:
Because of the different worldline, they're traveling in and t ≠ t', even though both the observers see the other observer's time slowing, B is still younger than A.
So about what they actually see, suppose there is a rod of length 1.732 light hours and A is stationed at one end of it, and B is going to travel at 0.866c to the other end and come back. A should age 4 hours during this and B just 2, but I want to describe it in terms of what they see when they watch each other's clocks, in order to show the complete symmetry between the two.
Relativistic dilation factor (gamma) at that speed is 2. Doppler effect is much stronger, so while receding, each will see the other's clock run at about 0.268 the normal rate, and a clock approaching at that speed will appear to run about 3.732 the normal rate.

So B sets out. In his frame, B is stationary and the fast moving rod length-contracts to 0.866 light hours, and it takes the contracted rod one hour to pass by him at that speed, and another hour to pass by in the other direction. Total duration of 2 hours. In the first hour, A's clock appears to log 0.268 hours, and during B's second hour, A's approaching clock appears to log 3.732 hours, for a total of 4 hours .

In A's frame, only B moves. It takes B two hours to go the length of the 1.732 light-hour rod before turning around, and it takes 1.732 hours for the light from the distant turnaround event to reach him, so B's clock will appear to run at 0.268 for 3.732 of A's hours at which point the B clock will appear to read exactly one hour. For the next 0.268 hours A will see B returning with a clock running at 3.732 which accumulates one more hour on B's clock for a total of 2 when they are again in each other's presence.

I did that to show that what they see is entirely symmetrical. Both will see the other clock running at the same slow or fast rate depending on if they're receding or approaching, but due to the asymmetry of their actions, they see these rates for different amounts of time
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17
  • #9
For what it's worth, when I first puzzled over the twins paradox, I found it helped to think about the about the problem without non-inertial frames. It highlights that the reason for what appears to be non-symmetrical time dilation is actually a change of frames, as stated in #2 above.

Here's a quick description of the inertial version:
  • Spaceship B, moving at a constant velocity, passes adjacent to A.
  • At that moment, both A and B set their clock to 0.
  • B continues on, eventually meeting C, who is traveling at a constant velocity toward A.
  • At the moment B and C are adjacent, C sets his clock to match B's.
  • When C passes by A, they compare times.
  • C's clock time will always read less than A's.
It's not necessary that B's and C's velocities match.
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17 and PeroK
  • #10
To drive home that the non-inertial traveler is not equivalent to the inertial twin,
I think it's useful to consider the traveler with an asymmetric trip (with numbers chosen to allow calculations with fractions).

While this diagram for inertial twin OPZ
can be thought of as "a splicing together
of the diagrams for OP (using simultaneity according to OP)
and for PZ (using simultaneity according to OP)",
the same can't be said for OQZ.

1590421196985.png
1590421408726.png


In accord with what @Orodruin and @Dale said, the non-inertial traveler OQZ
has a very different looking "[attempted] spacetime diagram". A portion of OPZ is missing in OQZ's diagram.
  • a portion of OPZ's worldline is missing and OPZ is discontinuous.
    In fact, event P and other events in the white region are missing.
    The attempted spacetime diagram is incomplete... events are missing.
    (This doesn't happen for inertial observers.)
  • Event X and other events in the green region appear twice.
    (This doesn't happen for inertial observers.)
No Lorentz transformation will straighten out the kink at Q.

The takeaway message is
"Being able-to-be-at-rest" [itex] \neq [/itex] "Being inertial".
 
  • Like
Likes ersa17
  • #11
robphy said:
To drive home that the non-inertial traveler is not equivalent to the inertial twin,
I think it's useful to consider the traveler with an asymmetric trip (with numbers chosen to allow calculations with fractions).

This looks like an artificial example, one that assumes instantaneous acceleration. This is unphysical.

If you add a short period of acceleration, the moving observer's frame changes with time. At any instant, there is no discontinuity and X has a single set of coordinates.

If you allow for instantaneous acceleration, then even a symmetric trip will have missing events and events with multiple coordinates. I don't think the asymmetry is necessary to make that point.

I suspect none of this is going to help the OP as it may require a foundation of knowledge he may not have (if one can make sense of your diagrams, one probably doesn't need help with the twins paradox).
 
  • #12
Freixas said:
This looks like an artificial example, one that assumes instantaneous acceleration. This is unphysical.
That critique applies to any piecewise-inertial motion, including the standard twin paradox/clock effect in special relativity and piecewise-constantVelocity motion in Galilean kinematics.
 
  • #13
Freixas said:
If you add a short period of acceleration, the moving observer's frame changes with time. At any instant, there is no discontinuity and X has a single set of coordinates.
If by this you mean to patch together the instantaneous inertial rest frames of the accelerating twin, this is not correct. The process inevitably assigns multiple coordinates to single events on the outside of the corner in the worldline as depicted on a Minkowski diagram.
 
  • Like
Likes Orodruin
  • #14
robphy said:
That critique applies to any piecewise-inertial motion, including the standard twin paradox/clock effect in special relativity and piecewise-constantVelocity motion in Galilean kinematics.

The twins paradox is vritually unchanged if you allow for a very quick (but not instantaneous) acceleration--and all the unphysical stuff goes away. I always think of it as: "we're not going to look super-closely at what happens at turn-around". If you focus on this and insist on the turn-around being instantaneous, you create a lot of artificial warts.

I proposed an alternate version of the twins paradox in which there is no acceleration back at #9 that also removes a lot of these problems. And the velocities do not need to be symmetrical.
 
  • #15
Ibix said:
If by this you mean to patch together the instantaneous inertial rest frames of the accelerating twin, this is not correct. The process inevitably assigns multiple coordinates to single events on the outside of the corner in the worldline as depicted on a Minkowski diagram.

I'll go out on a limb and claim that, for the moving observer, there is no single instant in which the process assigns multiple coordinates to a single event. At different instants, an event will have different coordinates, but never simultaneously for the moving observer (unless you allow for instantaneous acceleration).

But perhaps you can show me what you mean with a diagram. I can't picture it.
 
  • #16
Freixas said:
But perhaps you can show me what you mean with a diagram. I can't picture it.
Draw a curved worldline on a Minkowski diagram. Draw a line perpendicular to that line at some event (in the Minkowski sense of perpendicular), and that line is the locus of events sharing a t-coordinate value using your methodology. Now draw another perpendicular line at another event on the worldline. That line is also the locus of events sharing a t-coordinate, but a different value from the first line.

Unless the velocity of the worldline is equal at the two events from which you drew perpendiculars, those lines are not parallel. Thus they intersect at some event - and you have assigned two different t-coordinates to this event. For the special case of constant acceleration this event is the intersection of the Rindler horizon and anti-horizon.

For illustrations see figure 1 (instantaneous turnaround) and 2 (smooth turnaround) in Dolby and Gull.
 
Last edited:
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #17
Freixas said:
I'll go out on a limb and claim that, for the moving observer, there is no single instant in which the process assigns multiple coordinates to a single event.
You can define a coordinate system where the non-inertial twin is at rest, but this coordinate system is not going to be an inertial frame. If you want to use this, you need to dig a lot deeper than describing things in terms of inertial frames.
 
  • Like
Likes Ibix
  • #18
Ibix said:
Draw a curved worldline on a Minkowski diagram. Draw a line perpendicular to that line at some event (in the Minkowski sense of perpendicular), and that line is the locus of events sharing a t-coordinate value using your methodology. Now draw another perpendicular line at another event on the worldline. That line is also the locus of events sharing a t-coordinate, but a different value from the first line.

Sure, that's obvious. But those are two different points in time for the observer whose worldline you are drawing tangents to. There is no single instant for that observer at which an event has two coordinates.

On the other hand, if you allow for instantaneous acceleration, there is one instant in which the observer would have two valid and different sets of coordinates for some event.

In any case, I feel I have introduced a discussion that threatens to hijack the OP's thread and I'd rather not go further down that path.

Relevant to the OP are my thoughts that one can view the problem using only inertial frames and one can view the problem with a very short and dramatic velocity change at the turn-around point.
 
  • Skeptical
Likes Dale and weirdoguy
  • #19
Freixas said:
There is no single instant for that observer at which an event has two coordinates.
Why raise this issue?

The point concerning my diagram is that the "attempted spacetime diagram" is not a complete map of spacetime and is not obtained as a one-to-one map from the spacetime diagram for an inertial observer.

I made no claim concerning "a single instant... at which an event has two coordinates."

I claimed that there are events, like event X, that have two sets of coordinates.
Said another way, the same event X (like the particular intersection of two worldlines) occurs at different times according the non-inertial observer.
 
  • Like
Likes Dale
  • #20
Freixas said:
There is no single instant for that observer at which an event has two coordinates.

On the other hand, if you allow for instantaneous acceleration, there is one instant in which the observer would have two valid and different sets of coordinates for some event.
This is a misconception and confuses observers with inertial frames.

Freixas said:
Relevant to the OP are my thoughts that one can view the problem using only inertial frames and one can view the problem with a very short and dramatic velocity change at the turn-around point.
Your misconceptions only serve the purpose of confusing the OP. The only relevant thing to this problem in reality is piecewise smooth curves and the geometry of Minkowski space. Whether the turnaround is smooth or not is not that relevant.

Even in the case of continuous acceleration the entire process can be described using a single inertial frame, two inertial frames, three inertial frames, or whatever coordinates you want to impose. The physics will remain the same though.
 
  • Like
Likes Ibix, vanhees71 and PeterDonis
  • #21
The twin paradox is only invented to confuse students ;-). It's easily resolved when just expressing the relevant quantities in a manifestly covariant form and the conjectore that a moving proper clock shows proper time,
$$\tau=\int_{\lambda_1}^{\lambda_2} \mathrm{d} \lambda \sqrt{g_{\mu \nu} \dot{x}^{\mu} \dot{x}^{\nu}},$$
where ##x^{\mu}(\lambda)## is the parametrization of the time-like worldline of the clock. In this form it's completely independent of the choice of space-time coordinates and the parametrization. You can calculate it in any frame of reference (inertial or not), and it's even valid in general relativity with gravitation (or spacetime curvature) present.

That this conjecture is correct has been experimentally demonstrated in many high-precision experiments (for both situations that gravitation is necessary to be taken into account or not).
 
  • #22
robphy said:
I claimed that there are events, like event X, that have two sets of coordinates.

That shouldn't be a big surprise with two different frames of reference. With non-instantaneous acceleration X has even infinite different sets of coordinates. Yes, this is just an artefact resulting from the use of inertial rest frames for a non-inertial observer. But there is nothing wong with it.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #23
DrStupid said:
That shouldn't be a big surprise with two different frames of reference. With non-instantaneous acceleration X has even infinite different sets of coordinates. Yes, this is just an artefact resulting from the use of inertial rest frames for a non-inertial observer. But there is nothing wong with it.

It is this feature (yes, which is to be expected, but only if one looks hard enough)
that I use to distinguish a non-inertial observer from an inertial one.
That was the point of my initial posting in this thread.
Straightening out the non-inertial worldline (which is implied by "doing time-dilation calculations in the traveler-leg frames") is not enough
to justify an attempted equivalence of a non-inertial observer with an inertial one.
One has to transform [map] the spacetime as well.

"Being able-to-be-at-rest" ≠ "Being inertial".
 
Last edited:
  • #24
Freixas said:
I'll go out on a limb and claim that, for the moving observer, there is no single instant in which the process assigns multiple coordinates to a single event.

You are wrong. The moving observer's lines of constant time, according to your definition, will inevitably cross at some distance "below" him (i.e., in the direction opposite to the direction in which he is accelerating), which means his coordinate chart will assign multiple values of his ##t## coordinate to the same event. This is a well-known limitation of the method you are describing.
 
  • Like
Likes Freixas and vanhees71
  • #25
PeterDonis said:
You are wrong. The moving observer's lines of constant time, according to your definition, will inevitably cross at some distance "below" him (i.e., in the direction opposite to the direction in which he is accelerating), which means his coordinate chart will assign multiple values of his ##t## coordinate to the same event. This is a well-known limitation of the method you are describing.

Thanks, Peter. I'm not sure why, but I never got notified of your reply and I only drop into this group occasionally (oddly, I just received a notification for a new thread that I had never seen or interacted with--weird).

We'll take it as given that I'm wrong. Could you help me see where I went wrong? Here's how I visualize the problem:

Clipboard01.jpg


The units are light years (x) and years (t). The constant acceleration for the moving observer is .01 Earth gravities. The cyan axes show the Instantaneous Moving Frame (IMF) at rest time 20 years. For the moving observer, it appears to me that every event has a single coordinate at this instant in time. In addition, all events have coordinates--there are no events for which a coordinate cannot be calculated.

There is nothing special about this point in time, so I generalized this to any instant and made the claim that you point out as being wrong.

Lines of constant time, to the moving observer, would be lines parallel to his x' axis. Parallel lines being what they are, I can't see how they cross at some distance "below" the observer.

Perhaps there is something wrong with the diagram. Here's how I drew it: The t' axis's angle is calculated as tangent to the moving observer's world line. I have formulas that tell me the instantaneous velocity at any point of the moving observer's world line. Once I know the velocity, the units for t' and x' can be calculated. This determines the origin of the t' axis. The velocity also determines the angle of the x' axis.
 
  • #26
What you've drawn in cyan is the instantaneous inertial rest frame of an object on the red worldline. That's fine. And you can draw the instantaneous inertial rest frame of the object at any time. However each of these cover all of spacetime. If you want to "stitch them together" into one coordinate system you need some rule to describe which bit of spacetime you are going to cover with which frame. The naive way of doing it leads to the frames all overlapping at the focus of the hyperbola, which means that the observer applies multiple coordinates to one event. Non-naive ways of doing it don't really fit the notion of "the perspective of the accelerating observer".
 
  • Like
Likes Freixas and PeterDonis
  • #27
Freixas said:
I'm not sure why, but I never got notified of your reply
This typically happens if you left the browser window open after your last reply and someone else replies. The forum software auto-updates your page and concludes you've read the new post, even if you never noticed the page update. You do get an alert, but it's instantly marked read. It's a most annoying behaviour.
 
  • Like
Likes Freixas
  • #28
Freixas said:
We'll take it as given that I'm wrong
I don’t think that your statement was wrong. It was irrelevant. The restriction “no single instant” is a restriction that renders the rest of your comment irrelevant.

A coordinate system is a smooth and invertible mapping between an open region in the manifold and an open region in R4. By restricting your comment to a single instant your region under consideration is not open and so gives you no information on the validity of the coordinate system
 
  • Like
Likes Ibix
  • #29
Ibix said:
What you've drawn in cyan is the instantaneous inertial rest frame of an object on the red worldline. That's fine. And you can draw the instantaneous inertial rest frame of the object at any time. However each of these cover all of spacetime. If you want to "stitch them together" into one coordinate system you need some rule to describe which bit of spacetime you are going to cover with which frame. The naive way of doing it leads to the frames all overlapping at the focus of the hyperbola, which means that the observer applies multiple coordinates to one event. Non-naive ways of doing it don't really fit the notion of "the perspective of the accelerating observer".

Thanks, Ibix!

It never occurred to me that one would want to "stitch together" the various IMFs. But I can see that if I were to try to switch the two observers in my diagram, I would want some single coordinate system. (There appears to be an alternative approach on the Minkowski Spacetime Diagram Wikipedia page [see "Spacetime diagram of an accelerating observer in special relativity"] which makes more sense to me: you fix the accelerating observer at (x, t) = (0,0) and animate the changing coordinate system relative to the observer at each point in time.)

Let's go back to post #10. If there are multiple ways one might stitch together all the IMFs into a single coordinate system, is the method used by robphy the "approved" method? When he claimed that some events have multiple coordinates and some have none, is this claim an artifact of an arbitrary choice of stitching (i.e. I could choose some other stitching method in which his claims would be incorrect) or is this the method all physicists would use?

Let me try to simplify by re-using an old diagram I had lying around for the twins paradox:

twin-paradox.jpg


This example assumes a single instantaneous acceleration change, so there are just two frames to consider. If we just overlay the two frames over each other I'm assuming this is the "naive" method), every event has two coordinates and no event has missing coordinates. Is there a commonly accepted method of creating a single coordinate system for these two frames?
 
  • #30
No. There is no standard method for forming a non inertial frame. That is part of the problem.

My preferred approach is radar coordinates. This avoids the overlaps and gaps of the naive approach, and it is the only convention I know that respects the second postulate.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71
  • #31
Dale said:
No. There is no standard method for forming a non inertial frame. That is part of the problem.

My preferred approach is radar coordinates. This avoids the overlaps and gaps of the naive approach, and it is the only convention I know thrust respects the second postulate.

Thanks, Dale.

Perhaps you can help clarify post #10 for me. It appears to me to propose a mapping and then lists some problems that the mapping reveals. Are the problems universal (missing worldlines and events, events appearing twice) or are these more a reflection of the choice of mapping?

While I would love to see your radar version of the twins paradox diagram I posted, I know that's asking a lot. I looked up radar coordinates, but it would be really helpful to see the diagram that I posted converted to your preferred approach by someone who actually knows what he is doing.
 
  • #32
Freixas said:
Are the problems universal (missing worldlines and events, events appearing twice) or are these more a reflection of the choice of mapping?
Those are a pathology of the "naive" approach to constructing a non-inertial frame.

Freixas said:
While I would love to see your radar version of the twins paradox diagram I posted, I know that's asking a lot. I looked up radar coordinates, but it would be really helpful to see the diagram that I posted converted to your preferred approach by someone who actually knows what he is doing.
See https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0104077 figure 9 in particular.

Note that in radar coordinates the traveling twin's world line in the home twin's frame (figure 1) is not the mirror image of the home twin's worldline in the traveling twin's frame (figure 9). That is one clear asymmetry between the twins. If you used a different method for constructing the traveling twin's frame then you would get a violation of the second postulate which would be another clear asymmetry.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Freixas
  • #33
Dale said:
Those are a pathology of the "naive" approach to constructing a non-inertial frame.

Thanks. I felt that the observations made in post #10 were artificial, but didn't have the knowledge needed to phrase my objection properly.

Dale said:
See https://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/0104077 figure 9 in particular.

This paper is familiar; I remember trying to understand it some years ago when you referenced it in a different thread. Maybe it will make more sense now.

Appreciate the help from everyone.
 
  • Like
Likes vanhees71 and Dale

1. Why does time dilation only affect one of the twins?

Time dilation is a phenomenon predicted by Einstein's theory of relativity, which states that the passage of time is relative and can be affected by factors such as velocity and gravity. In the case of the twin paradox, where one twin travels at high speeds while the other stays on Earth, the twin who travels experiences time dilation due to their high velocity, while the twin who stays on Earth does not. This is because their relative velocities are different, causing time to pass at different rates for each twin.

2. How does time dilation affect the aging process?

Time dilation can affect the aging process by causing time to pass at a slower rate for an object or person in motion compared to one at rest. This means that the twin who travels at high speeds will age slower than the twin who stays on Earth, resulting in a noticeable age difference when they are reunited. However, the overall effects of time dilation on aging are only significant at extremely high velocities, such as those near the speed of light.

3. Can time dilation be observed in everyday life?

Yes, time dilation can be observed in everyday life, although the effects are usually too small to be noticeable. For example, GPS satellites orbiting the Earth experience time dilation due to their high speeds, and this must be taken into account when calculating their positions. Similarly, astronauts on the International Space Station experience time dilation due to their high orbital velocity.

4. Why does time dilation only occur at high speeds?

Time dilation only occurs at high speeds because it is a consequence of the special theory of relativity, which only applies to objects moving at a significant fraction of the speed of light. At everyday speeds, the effects of time dilation are too small to be significant. However, as an object approaches the speed of light, its relative velocity increases, causing time dilation to become more pronounced.

5. Can time dilation be reversed?

No, time dilation cannot be reversed. Once an object has experienced time dilation due to its high velocity, there is no way to reverse or undo the effects. This is because time dilation is a fundamental aspect of the fabric of spacetime, and changing it would require altering the laws of physics. However, the effects of time dilation can be compensated for by adjusting other factors, such as the rate of a clock, to account for the difference in the passage of time.

Similar threads

  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
9
Views
255
  • Special and General Relativity
4
Replies
115
Views
5K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
20
Views
2K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
5
Views
650
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
4
Views
901
  • Special and General Relativity
3
Replies
70
Views
4K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
21
Views
505
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
25
Views
1K
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
16
Views
665
  • Special and General Relativity
Replies
25
Views
665
Back
Top