Millennial said:
No, "solving for x" as you know it forms just a little bit of math. Your criticism of the Riemann Hypothesis is also wrong. We can find zeroes of the Riemann zeta function relatively easily, especially with the computers of our age. The problem is that where those zeroes actually lie. After all, we cannot compute infinitely many zeros with a computer, so one needs a proof to conclude all zeros lie on the critical line.
Even if you do think this is solving for X (which you shouldn't), the methods of solving are still much different. You will change your mind if you reach the level in which you can understand the Riemann Hypothesis and what it actually means.
Was that for me? I wasn't able to tell if you're responding to what I wrote. If so, I'll be happy to explain. RH is the classic "find x" problem. Of course it's at a much higher level of mathematical sophistication than finding the solution of 2x = 5 in the integers (or proving no solution exists); but it's precisely the same in terms of structure.
Let's examine the structure of "Find an integer x such that 2x = 5, or prove no such exists."
We have a predicate P. In this case, P (x) is "x is an integer and 2x = 5."
We are asked to find any and all x that satisfy P, or else prove that no such x can exist.
An exhaustive computer search proves fruitless. 2*1 = 2, 2*2 = 4, 2*3 = 6, 2*(-180) = -360, ... hmmm, this won't work. I need some
theory.
I consult a local mathematician. (A local mathematician is someone who appears to be a mathematician within some neighborhood, but who may or may not be a mathematician when viewed from a global perspective. A lot like many of the denizens of online math forums!) She walks me through some elementary number theory and some elementary ring theory, then points out that on the left, if x is an integer, then 2x must be an element of the ideal generated by 2, denoted <2>. But 5 is not an element of this ideal, because 5 = 2(2) + 1 and 1 is not an element of <2>.
I am enlightened. We have used theory to show that no such integer x exists satisfying 2x = 5.
Now I start wondering about RH. Again we have a predicate P(x), which in this case is "x is a nontrivial zero of the zeta function and the real part of x is not 1/2".
Of course P is a fairly complicated predicate, and it would take some time to boil it down to a form that would satisfy a logician's definition of a predicate. But it can be done. We have a theory that says so :-)
Now we are challenged to find x in the complex numbers that satisfies P, or else show that no such x can exist.
In other words, RH is far more mathematically sophisticated than 2x = 5. For one thing, nobody's offering a million dollars for a solution of the famous 2x = 5 problem. But the
form is identical. RH is a classic "find x" problem. You have a predicate and you're asked to find the value(s) that satisfy P, or else show that no such x can exist.
In fact, many math problems have this structure. Take the famous classification of finite, simple groups. In this case, x is a classification. A classification in this context is a collection of groups such that every finite simple group is isomorphic to exactly one member of the collection. If we were sufficiently motivated, we could write down a predicate that encapsulates the meaning of "classification." Again, we have a classical "find x" problem.
It's surprising just how many deep mathematical problems have the same structure: "Find all x satisfying predicate P, or prove that no such exists."
If you are building a theory, finding x does not typically come into play. But whenever you are
solving a problem, "finding x" is typically the exact form of the problem. We're looking for elements of some set that satisfy a predicate.
And as I pointed out, exhaustive computer search is no more effective in solving 2x = 5 than it is in solving RH; so the fact that a given problem requires theory is no objection at all.