Are clicks proof of single photons?

  • Thread starter Thread starter A. Neumaier
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Photons Proof
  • #51
A. Neumaier said:
[..]
So. if one knows that one produced single photons or atoms at a time, as localized wave packets, it is appropriate to talk about particles. In that case, the wave arriving and the particle arriving are synonymous.

But their fate as particles after passing a slit more narrow than their wavelength (or a beam splitter and similar devices) becomes dubious since the slit delocalizes the field to an expanding spherical wave. Now this wave arrives at a far away detector at all places simultaneously, while the detector responds randomly at one place. Thus the particle view and the wave view diverge, and only the latter is a reasonable (i.e., semiclassical) explanation of what happens. [..]

Now here you lump photons and atoms together in a single description, and this is what I have an issue with (due to my intuition, which may be right, or wrong).
For I have no problem to imagine that a photon isn't really a particle, so that it doesn't need to be localised; that fits rather well with "classical" concepts and anyway, nobody has ever really seen a photon and you can't hold a bunch of photons in your hand.

But it's different with atoms: you can hold them in your hand and count them with a microscope. Surely you do not suggest that atoms can be split or destroyed by slits, or do you? It would for me be a revolutionary way of splitting the atom!
Please clarify.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #52
meopemuk said:
And it appears that this epic battle still rages on. Fascinating!
Yes. And the future might perhaps view our discussion here as one of the last few rearguard actions of the particle faction.
meopemuk said:
Do I understand you correctly? This means that M&W arguments cannot explain detection of single-photon states (which can be called "quantum light" as opposed to multi-photon "classical light")? Then we are in agreement.
The M&W arguments in Chapter 9 do not try to explain detection of single-photon states. It is not even possible to state in the model used in Chapter 9 what a single-photon state should be (except in the wave packet approximation described below).

M&W treat the full QED case in Chapter 14, where they show that for coherent states, one gets exactly the results from Chapter 9. For other states, they find deviations from the Poisson distribution and differences in the distribution of the time between two clicks.

The result is very far from your postulated idealized 1-1 correspondence between photons and clicks (which is wishful thinking without an experimental basis). They get (after some approximations - the formulas are not valid for sufficiently long times) the formula (14.8-16) for the probability of getting n clicks in a time interval of length T, given an m-photon Fock state in which only a single momentum mode is occupied. For n>m, this is zero.
meopemuk said:
For example, I can shoot a single neutron at a piece of proper material (I hope you wouldn't deny that a single-neutron state can be predictably prepared.)
Well, how would you do it reliably?
meopemuk said:
The neutron gets absorbed by only one nucleus.
The problem is that it gets absorbed by at most one nucleus. And you don't know whether or not it does.
meopemuk said:
This nucleus goes to an excited state, which decays later by emitting just one gamma quantum. I don't know nuclear physics so well, but I guess that such a sequence of events can be arranged.
According to conventional wisdom, the resulting gamma quant is emitted in a random direction. And you don't know whether it is in the direction of your detector unless you record it there!
meopemuk said:
If the lifetime of the nucleus is 10 hours I can wait for 10 hours, no problem.
The decay happens at an unpredictable random time. After 10 hours, the probability of emission is only a factor of 1/e.
meopemuk said:
If you don't like the idea of the source receding at high velocity, then I can place my radioactive nucleus on a rotating platform.
Well, with the rotating platform, it won't be easier to hit the target detector!
meopemuk said:
Or I can place it in a strong gravitational potential, so that the frequency (energy) of the emitted photon is red-shifted.
The potential would have to be so strong that it swallows all your recording equipment!
meopemuk said:
There are various realistic ways to achieve the goal.
So far, your proposals didn't sound even remotely realistic.
meopemuk said:
But M&W Chapter 9 does not guarantee the emission of only one electron. I don't see such a guarantee there.
They don't since under their assumptions (coherent input light) there is a small but nonzero probability for emitting more than one electron in an arbitrarily short time interval. And their results are very well in agreement with experiment! Thus the requested guarantee would not conform to experimental reality.
meopemuk said:
Besides, the energy conservation argument doesn't work. In their model the oscillating classical potential serves basically as an unlimited reservoir of energy.
Yes, but they treat a coherent state, not a single photon. A coherent state produces an unlimited number of photons if you wait long enough. (This is why you can't represent it in Fock space.)

But if only a single photon arrives (as you tried to arrange), there is a definite total energy. In the classical setting the single photon appears as a modulated wave packet, with nonzero energy density only for the time it took your nucleus to decay, and an integral that matches the 1-photon energy hbar times omega. Then the energy conservation argument works. (Their analysis generalizes since they split the time
anyway into many small time intervals, where the intensity can be considered constant. only the integration would be different, and hence the probability distribution.)
 
  • #53
meopemuk said:
My only disagreement is that this model cannot explain the "1 photon = 1 click" rule. I insist that 1-photon states can be, in principle, prepared, and that this rule can be verified experimentally.
Please cite a paper that verified this rule.

As I mentioned in my just finished post, the QED result (which agrees with experiment) is different from what your rule claims.
 
  • #54
meopemuk said:
I disagree. The most basic calculation in QED is the calculation of the Compton scattering cross-section. It assumes explicitly the initial state consisting of *exactly* one photon and *exactly* one electron. So, the photon number has a very precise meaning there.
Only in the tree approximation. If you compute radiative corrections you get infrared divergences due to an unlimited number of soft photons. Phys. Rev. 85, 231–244 (1952).

And if you look at how Compton scattering is experimentally verified, you see that they use not 1-photon states but ordinary laser light, which form coherent states
(or even ordinary light, which is a mixture of coherent states).
 
  • #55
harrylin said:
But it's different with atoms: you can hold them in your hand and count them with a microscope. Surely you do not suggest that atoms can be split or destroyed by slits, or do you? It would for me be a revolutionary way of splitting the atom!
Please clarify.

Surely, atoms cannot be split by the slits. Each atom exists as one localized entity each time we look at it. Then you may say that in order to interfere on the double-slit setup the atom must go through both slits simultaneously. How these two views can co-exist?

My answer is that when the atom is "passing through slits" we are not actually looking at the atom. The conclusion about "passing simultaneously through both slits" is not a result of direct measurement but a result of some logical reasoning. But logical speculations have a lesser value than direct experimental observations. So, it would be a safer bet to stick to atoms as single indivisible localized entities, which are seen in experiments.

If you ask me: "but what about atoms passing through slits"? My answer would be "I don't know". In science I am not obliged to answer questions, whose answers cannot be directly verified by experiment. "But what about atoms passing through slits"? is exactly this type of question. There is no shame if I answer simply "I don't know". Yes, I can introduce atom wave function and calculate the probability density and predict the shape of the interference picture (i.e., the final outcome of the experiment). But this does not mean that I *know* what atoms are doing while passing through the slits.

By the way, the same reasoning should be applied to photons. Each time we actually observe individual photons with sufficiently high resolution (using photographic plates, photo-multipliers, CCD devices, etc) we see them as separate countable undivisible particles. So, it is a safer bet to assume that this is exactly what the photons are. The wave properties appear in situations when no actual observations are made (e.g., when a photon passes through two slits). So, just as in the case of atoms above, we can describe these wave properties by an abstract wave function, which interferes with itself, collapses, and does various nasty (but not troubling) things while we are not looking.

Eugene.
 
  • #56
harrylin said:
Now here you lump photons and atoms together in a single description, and this is what I have an issue with (due to my intuition, which may be right, or wrong).
They are all described by wave equations, though different ones due to their different masses and spins. But they behave quite similarly.
harrylin said:
For I have no problem to imagine that a photon isn't really a particle, so that it doesn't need to be localised; that fits rather well with "classical" concepts and anyway, nobody has ever really seen a photon and you can't hold a bunch of photons in your hand.
In quantum field theory, a photon is as much or as little a particle as an electron, depending on your precise definition of a particle.

You can see a photon as a flash in your eyes, whereas you cannot see an atom.
harrylin said:
But it's different with atoms: you can hold them in your hand and count them with a microscope.
You can hold a crystal in your hands but not an atom.

If you look at an atom under an field emission microscope or a similar high resolution device, you see a continuous surface whose bulges are interpreted as atoms. This is just what one would expect from a field! A macroscopic body with many macroscopic bulges is indeed not viewed as being composed of macroscopic balls (''atoms'') but as a matter field described by elasticity theory.
harrylin said:
Surely you do not suggest that atoms can be split or destroyed by slits, or do you?
No. The atom field splits at the slits and unites afterwards again, just like a water wave or any other wave.

In an atom interferometer, you have a diluted atom field in the form of a high-frequency beam, which moves through the splits like any other field, and expands behind the slits as a superposition of two spherical waves. Then it reaches the screen and causes some detectors to fire, with probability rates proportional to the incident field energy. This is precisely the same as what happens with the photon field; except that the internal degrees of freedom of atoms and photons are different. (But these are not relevant in a standard double slit experiment)
 
  • #57
A. Neumaier said:
Well, how would you do it reliably?

The problem is that it gets absorbed by at most one nucleus. And you don't know whether or not it does.

According to conventional wisdom, the resulting gamma quant is emitted in a random direction. And you don't know whether it is in the direction of your detector unless you record it there!

The decay happens at an unpredictable random time. After 10 hours, the probability of emission is only a factor of 1/e.

Well, with the rotating platform, it won't be easier to hit the target detector!

The potential would have to be so strong that it swallows all your recording equipment!

So far, your proposals didn't sound even remotely realistic.

These are all technical issues. Let's leave them to experimentalists.


A. Neumaier said:
But if only a single photon arrives (as you tried to arrange), there is a definite total energy. In the classical setting the single photon appears as a modulated wave packet, with nonzero energy density only for the time it took your nucleus to decay, and an integral that matches the 1-photon energy hbar times omega. Then the energy conservation argument works. (Their analysis generalizes since they split the time
anyway into many small time intervals, where the intensity can be considered constant. only the integration would be different, and hence the probability distribution.)

Can we then agree that single photon states can be prepared, at least in principle? I don't see how you can disagree, because a 1-photon sector is present even in QED. Since we are talking about non-interacting freely propagating light here, you cannot use arguments about non-Fock spaces.

So, we take this one-photon state and let it pass through a double slit setup and let it fall on a CCD detector. According to you, after passing the slits the photon's electromagnetic wave diverges, so that it covers the whole detector area. You also say that there is a non-zero probability that more than one pixel will catch a signal. Is this what you're saying?

On the other hand, my claim is that no more than one pixel will "click". Photon is a particle that cannot be split in smaller pieces.

I don't know experiments performed exactly in this way, but I'll try to look for them. Only one of us can be correct. Hopefully, we can resolve this contradiction peacefully, without engaging in rearguard skirmishes.

Eugene.
 
  • #58
A. Neumaier said:
In an atom interferometer, you have a diluted atom field in the form of a high-frequency beam, which moves through the splits like any other field, and expands behind the slits as a superposition of two spherical waves. Then it reaches the screen and causes some detectors to fire, with probability rates proportional to the incident field energy. This is precisely the same as what happens with the photon field; except that the internal degrees of freedom of atoms and photons are different. (But these are not relevant in a standard double slit experiment)

Instead of using detectors, which respond to the "field energy", I can simply allow the atoms to be deposited on the screen/substrate. So that over time thicker atomic layers grow in regions of constructive interference and there is less stuff deposited in the regions of descructive interference. How would you then deny that each atom passed through the slits landed at a very specific point on the substrate? So, atoms behave exactly as individual particles. The only thing that behaves continuously in this case is the probability density for each atom to land at a specific point. This probability density is obtained from the regular one-particle quantum mechanical wave function. There is no need to invoke fields, either classical or quantum.

Eugene.
 
  • #59
meopemuk said:
Can we then agree that single photon states can be prepared, at least in principle?
The standard field interpretation of QED doesn't depend on this. The states commonly prepared by Nature or by physicists are far from single photon states. Usually they are coherent states or squeezed states, or entangled tensor products of such states.

The best I know is that it is possible to create mixtures of superpositions of the vacuum state and 1-photon states in the sense of my lecture http://arnold-neumaier.at/ms/lightslides.pdf
meopemuk said:
So, we take this one-photon state and let it pass through a double slit setup and let it fall on a CCD detector. According to you, after passing the slits the photon's electromagnetic wave diverges, so that it covers the whole detector area. You also say that there is a non-zero probability that more than one pixel will catch a signal. Is this what you're saying?
No. Given a mixture of superpositions of the vacuum state and 1-photon states, there is a nonzero probability for recording some event, while the probability for more than one event is exactly zero. This can be deduced from the estimate in M&W (14.8-16).
meopemuk said:
On the other hand, my claim is that no more than one pixel will "click".
Here we agree.
meopemuk said:
Photon is a particle that cannot be split in smaller pieces.
This is irrelevant. It is neither needed to derive the probability statement, nor does it follow from it.
 
  • #60
meopemuk said:
Instead of using detectors, which respond to the "field energy", I can simply allow the atoms to be deposited on the screen/substrate. So that over time thicker atomic layers grow in regions of constructive interference and there is less stuff deposited in the regions of destructive interference. How would you then deny that each atom passed through the slits landed at a very specific point on the substrate?
I deny this on the basis of several facts:
1. The interpretation rules are inconsistent with the atomic nature of the atom:
An atom is indivisible (at the energies of the experiment) and can therefore go only through one of the slits. Assuming it went through the left or the right slit, the atoms' arrival pattern would (according to the same arguments you give for your interference pattern) have to be different from what is observed. Contradiction.
2. One cannot say how each atom arrived at a constructive interference spot rather than at a destructive interference spot. The atom comes from the source, is nonexistent (or in a state of limbo where it has no physical property at all) during a period of time corresponding to the flight of time to the screen, and then miraculously is called into existence by the detector, consistent with an interference pattern of which neither the atom nor the detector knows the slightest thing. This is far too miraculous a story to believe, though this fairy tale has been told umpteen times since the old Copenhagen times. The emperor wears no clothes, but nobody dares to say so.

The quantum field view has none of these problems.
meopemuk said:
So, atoms behave exactly as individual particles.
They would need a Bohmian guiding field in order to behave like that. I reject this for the reasons given in post #42.
 
  • #61
meopemuk said:
On the other hand, my claim is that no more than one pixel will "click".

A. Neumaier said:
Here we agree.


Ok, so possibly we are not so far apart as I thought. The difference is only in interpretation. I say that the pixel "clicks" because a photon has arrived there. You say that this was a result of a quantum field "magic".

Eugene.
 
  • #62
A. Neumaier said:
An atom is indivisible (at the energies of the experiment)

Yes.


A. Neumaier said:
...and can therefore go only through one of the slits.

I am not sure about that. I would prefer not to make any statements about situations in which the atom is not observed. Anyway, such statements cannot be verified experimentally, so they are beyond scientific discourse.

A. Neumaier said:
The atom [...] is nonexistent (or in a state of limbo where it has no physical property at all) during a period of time corresponding to the flight of time to the screen.

Again, in order to avoid contradictions, I prefer not to say anything about the state of the atom between preparation and observation events. I can assign a wave function to such a state, but this is just a mathematical device. Using the wave function I can say something meaningful (probabilities) about possible observations. However, I cannot say anything useful about the non-observed state.

A. Neumaier said:
The quantum field view has none of these problems.

Please remind me what was the field theory explanation for the interference experiment with atomic deposition? In particular, how the atomic "field" collapses to a specific position on the substrate? Isn't it the same dreadful Copenhagen collapse?

I hope in this explanation you wouldn't invoke the quantum nature of the substrate as M&W did in their Chapter 9.

Eugene.
 
  • #63
meopemuk said:
I would prefer not to make any statements about situations in which the atom is not observed. Anyway, such statements cannot be verified experimentally, so they are beyond scientific discourse.
You narrow the scientific endeavor to a very tiny realm. According to your criteria, you would consider talk about the temperature or composition of the core of the Earth or the interior of the sun, about the time of impact of one of the big meteors in the far past, or about the functioning of the inside of your computer to be beyond scientific discourse. All these are not observed.
meopemuk said:
Again, in order to avoid contradictions, I prefer not to say anything about the state of the atom between preparation and observation events. I can assign a wave function to such a state, but this is just a mathematical device. Using the wave function I can say something meaningful (probabilities) about possible observations. However, I cannot say anything useful about the non-observed state.
Saying something about possible but unperformed observations should be beyond scientific discourse according to your criteria. How then can you call it meaningful? You cannot make any definite statement without running into contradictions. This is what I meant by saying ''The atom [...] is nonexistent (or in a state of limbo where it has no physical property at all) during a period of time corresponding to the flight of time to the screen.'' If the atom had some physical properties, one would be allowed to state and use them consistently.
meopemuk said:
Please remind me what was the field theory explanation for the interference experiment with atomic deposition? In particular, how the atomic "field" collapses to a specific position on the substrate? Isn't it the same dreadful Copenhagen collapse?

I hope in this explanation you wouldn't invoke the quantum nature of the substrate as M&W did in their Chapter 9.
It would be very strange if the quantum nature of the substrate were immaterial.

I have no explicit calculations for this, but judging from what I expect a calculation would reveal, the atomic field simply ends at the substrate, with a randomly growing density at the boundary, this time (because of a mass conservation law) due to the quantum nature of both the atomic field and the substrate. No collapse is needed for this, and everything happens locally, with nonlocal correlations but no nonlocal information transfer.
 
  • #64
A. Neumaier said:
You narrow the scientific endeavor to a very tiny realm. According to your criteria, you would consider talk about the temperature or composition of the core of the Earth or the interior of the sun, about the time of impact of one of the big meteors in the far past, or about the functioning of the inside of your computer to be beyond scientific discourse. All these are not observed.

Saying something about possible but unperformed observations should be beyond scientific discourse according to your criteria. How then can you call it meaningful? You cannot make any definite statement without running into contradictions. This is what I meant by saying ''The atom [...] is nonexistent (or in a state of limbo where it has no physical property at all) during a period of time corresponding to the flight of time to the screen.'' If the atom had some physical properties, one would be allowed to state and use them consistently.

I cannot talk about things, which I do not observe, but I am allowed to talk (predict) about results of future experiments. There is a subtle philosophical difference.

For example, in the original double-slit experiment I cannot say whether the photon (or electron, or whatever) passes through one slit or through two slits. Whichever answer I choose I will find myself in a logical contradiction. So, I decide to answer simply "I don't know". And you cannot blame for that, because you cannot find the truth experimentally without totally changing the experimental setup, so that the original question does not make sense anymore.

However, I *can* predict that if we modify the double-slit setup by adding particle detectors near each slit, then this new experiment will find that the photon is passing through one slit only. But experimental conditions have changed, so this result tells me nothing about the single-slit or double-slit passage in the original setup.

Talking about non-observable things can be OK if we are dealing with purely classical effects, where Z follows from Y and Y follows from X without any quantum probabilities involved. Most of observations in physics belong to this class. For example, from temperature X in the middle of the sun follows temperature Y on the surface of the sun. And from temperature Y on the surface of the sun follows photon spectrum Z observed on earth. So, by measuring the photon spectrum on Earth I can follow this cause-effect relationship backwards and recreate the value of the parameter X. Of course, this is a gross simplification and many other parameters are involved. However, the important thing is that all these parameters are in unambiguous (non-quantum) cause-effect relationships with each other.

The same with the meteorite. By looking at the crater I can roll back the classical cause-effect relationship chain and say what was the meteorite's mass, velocity, when the impact has occurred, etc.

In the quantum case this roll back is not possible. If I see that a photon landed at the point Z on the screen I cannot recreate the cause-effect chain and say whether the photon passed through the left slit or through the right slit. Quantum processes have inherent unexplainable probability, which does not allow me to make definite statements about things that have not been observed.

A. Neumaier said:
It would be very strange if the quantum nature of the substrate were immaterial.

Do you then expect that the shape of the interference picture would depend on the chemical composition of the sustrate? Of course, I assume that the substrate is chemically neutral, that atoms cannot migrate on the surface, etc. As far as I know, all interference patterns (with photons, electrons, atoms, etc.) have the same form, which depend only on the geometry of the two slits and the momentum of projectiles. There is absolutely no dependence on the chemical composition of the diaphragm and the screen/substrate. If your model predicts such dependence, then it can be verified experimentally.

A. Neumaier said:
I have no explicit calculations for this, but judging from what I expect a calculation would reveal, the atomic field simply ends at the substrate, with a randomly growing density at the boundary, this time (because of a mass conservation law) due to the quantum nature of both the atomic field and the substrate. No collapse is needed for this, and everything happens locally, with nonlocal correlations but no nonlocal information transfer.

I don't really get it. We've fired just one atom. According to you, the situation is described by a continuous field, which is spread over the entire substrate surface. Nevertheless, the atom lands at one fixed location. How exactly this location is chosen? Which physical mechanism has chosen this particular location?

Eugene.
 
Last edited:
  • #65
A. Neumaier said:
No. I see the sufficiency of standard quantum mechanics. Bohmian mechanics adds nothing to understand the photoelectric effect:

There is no Bohmian mechanics version of photon absorption consistent with Maxwell's equation, though models for Bohmian photons with a Maxwell pilot wave exist: http://arxiv.org/pdf/0907.2667

But even if this were improved, I don't see any reason for postulating unobservable Bohmian ghost particles with nonlocal instantaneous influences over galactic spacetime regions, just in order to explain seeing the light of stars.

Fair enough. I'm hoping that the next couple of years will start to rectify the lack of usable mechanics, though what emerges may not be at all Bohmian. Thanks for the references, I'll read them as soon as time permits.
 
  • #66
A. Neumaier said:
No. Even according to a hypothetical Hamiltonian multiparticle theory accounting for photodetection, one could ''find'' a photon in this way only when it no longer exists! The very act of attempting to observe a photon kills it!

Therefore, one cannot use observations to prove the existence of photons! They are ghosts conjured by Einstein and Dirac! Whereas in quantum field theory, one just has states of the electromagnetic field, and the number of photons in a given region is a
non-observable.

One CAN in fact measure single photons without destroying them, as is done in the experiments in the group of Serge Haroche.

See e.g. http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v455/n7212/abs/nature07288.html"

In their experiments they detect photons in a QND type way, where repeated measurement of the same photon is possible. With this they can detect the differences between photons in coherent states and in pure Fock states.
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #67
meopemuk said:
I cannot talk about things, which I do not observe, but I am allowed to talk (predict) about results of future experiments. There is a subtle philosophical difference.
We are talking most of the time about things we do not observe. We trust that all the transistors in the VLSI chips of our computers behave in a particular way predicted by quantum mechanics, although we hardly ever check it. We _could_ check it (thereby destroying the chip = changing the experimental setup), but we never do it. Even at the manufacturer, one only checks the consistency of some peripheral test results with the predictions.
meopemuk said:
For example, in the original double-slit experiment I cannot say whether the photon (or electron, or whatever) passes through one slit or through two slits. Whichever answer I choose I will find myself in a logical contradiction.
That's the problem with the particle picture. You buy it at the cost of a very strange picture of reality that takes years of brain washing to get used to. The field picture doesn't have these difficulties.
meopemuk said:
So, I decide to answer simply "I don't know". And you cannot blame for that, because you cannot find the truth experimentally without totally changing the experimental setup, so that the original question does not make sense anymore.
I blame you for that because you cannot find the truth experimentally about the trnsistors in your computer without totally changing the experimental setup, but the original question still makes sense, and we know!

Why should one quantum system be different than the other? How many particles does a quantum system need to have to be able to be blamed for pretending not to be knowable?
meopemuk said:
by measuring the photon spectrum on Earth I can follow this cause-effect relationship backwards[...]
In the quantum case this roll back is not possible. [...] Quantum processes have inherent unexplainable probability, which does not allow me to make definite statements about things that have not been observed.
So you sacrifice the cause-effect relationship on the level at a single quantum particle, but you claim that such a relationship exists on the level of N quantum particles where N is the number of particles in the sun? At which value of N do you switch between the two modes?

Moreover, what you say is restricted to the quantum particle view. In a quantum field view, the causal uncertainty is not bigger than classically, involving the inherent unexplainable probability of predicting or retrodicting a chaotic system.
meopemuk said:
Do you then expect that the shape of the interference picture would depend on the chemical composition of the sustrate? Of course, I assume that the substrate is chemically neutral, that atoms cannot migrate on the surface, etc. As far as I know, all interference patterns (with photons, electrons, atoms, etc.) have the same form, which depend only on the geometry of the two slits and the momentum of projectiles. There is absolutely no dependence on the chemical composition of the diaphragm and the screen/substrate.
Under the conditions you stated, QFT probably predicts absolutely no dependence on the chemical composition of the diaphragm and the screen/substrate - just as it doesn't predict any such dependence on the nature of a photodetection device, where M&W did the calculations.
meopemuk said:
I don't really get it. We've fired just one atom. According to you, the situation is described by a continuous field, which is spread over the entire substrate surface. Nevertheless, the atom lands at one fixed location. How exactly this location is chosen? Which physical mechanism has chosen this particular location?
Considered as a microscopic system, the detector is a highly chaotic dynamical system. Therefore, the individual binding sites for the atomic field behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident atom field, just as the outer electrons in a photodetector behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident electromagnetic field. The response rate is proportional to the incident energy. Once one of the qubits fires, it uses up the whole energy and matter of the atom field, and the choice has been made. No other qubit can fire, by a most likely existing analogue of M&W's formula (14.8-16).

In quantum field theory, causality is therefore as well-behaved as in any classical stochastic process.
 
  • #68
A. Neumaier said:
So you sacrifice the cause-effect relationship on the level at a single quantum particle, but you claim that such a relationship exists on the level of N quantum particles where N is the number of particles in the sun? At which value of N do you switch between the two modes?

Yes, the transition between the random quantum regime and the predictable classical regime occurs gradually as N grows. There is no unique threshold value. Some systems show quantum behavior even for very large N. The usual examples are superconductors and superfluid helium.

A. Neumaier said:
Considered as a microscopic system, the detector is a highly chaotic dynamical system. Therefore, the individual binding sites for the atomic field behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident atom field, just as the outer electrons in a photodetector behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident electromagnetic field. The response rate is proportional to the incident energy. Once one of the qubits fires, it uses up the whole energy and matter of the atom field, and the choice has been made. No other qubit can fire, by a most likely existing analogue of M&W's formula (14.8-16).

In quantum field theory, causality is therefore as well-behaved as in any classical stochastic process.

I see. So, you are a follower of Einstein's "God does not play dice" camp. So, you are saying that quantum uncertainties result from classical "hidden variables"? So, if we could entangle all these stochastic chaotic classical processes, we would be able to predict the exact location of the atom deposition or pixel firing in each case. Is it right?

On the other hand, your position is not pure as you mix classical fields and quantum mechanics in your version of quantum field theory. I find it inconsistent. I think you should either deny quantum uncertainty and go all the way with classical hidden variables or accept fundamental unpredictability of nature and then work with Hilbert spaces, wave functions, and all that machinery of quantum mechanics.

Eugene.
 
  • #69
meopemuk said:
[..]
On the other hand, your position is not pure as you mix classical fields and quantum mechanics in your version of quantum field theory. I find it inconsistent. I think you should either deny quantum uncertainty and go all the way with classical hidden variables or accept fundamental unpredictability of nature and then work with Hilbert spaces, wave functions, and all that machinery of quantum mechanics.
Eugene.

Isn't QM a theory that predicts output observables based on input observables? If so, it can make no claim about unmeasurable things like "fundamental unpredictability of nature". It cannot make such philosophical claims. Instead, it can make claims about our limits of prediction of observables, and the machinery of QM serves for quantifying such claims.
 
  • #70
harrylin said:
Isn't QM a theory that predicts output observables based on input observables?

No, QM is not that kind of theory. Even if you know your input observables as well as possible QM allows you to predict the output observables only probabilistically.

It is impossible to prepare the initial states of your particles, so that after passing the double-slit setup all of them will land at the same point on the screen. QM cannot tell you where each individual particle will land. QM can only tell you the probability distribution. The exact landing points is a matter of chance. QM does not explain this random behavior of nature. No other theory can explain this.

Eugene.
 
  • #71
meopemuk said:
No, QM is not that kind of theory. Even if you know your input observables as well as possible QM allows you to predict the output observables only probabilistically.
That is what I would call a yes, although you said "no". Or do you claim that probability theory makes no predictions about the results of throwing dice?
[..] QM does not explain this random behavior of nature. [..]
Exactly.
No other theory can explain this.
That claim is not a postulate of QM, or is it?
 
  • #72
harrylin said:
Or do you claim that probability theory makes no predictions about the results of throwing dice?

The probability theory predicts that in 50% of cases you'll see head up and in 50% of cases you'll see tail up. Similarly, QM predicts that a polarized photon will pass through the filter in 50% of cases and not pass in other 50% of cases. If you call this "prediction of output observables based on input observables", then yes, we agree.

The important thing is that both theories cannot tell you what will be the outcome in each individual case. So, there are some aspects of nature, which are totally unpredictable. That was my point.

Eugene.
 
  • #73
meopemuk said:
Please remind me what was the field theory explanation for the interference experiment
with atomic deposition? In particular, how the atomic "field" collapses to a specific position
on the substrate? Isn't it the same dreadful Copenhagen collapse?

I hope in this explanation you [Arnold] wouldn't invoke the quantum nature of the
substrate as M&W did in their Chapter 9.

I don't see anything fundamentally wrong with a similar calculation as in M&W ch9.

For the benefit of other readers, I'll quickly review sections 9.2 and 9.3 of Mandel & Wolf:

M&W work in the interaction picture, with the Schroedinger equation

<br /> \partial_t \; |\psi(t)\rangle<br /> ~=~ \frac{1}{i\hbar} \, \hat{H}_I(t) \, |\psi(t)\rangle<br /> ~~~~~~~~(9.2-1)<br />

where |\psi(t)\rangle is the state of an electron in the detector,
and \hat{H}_I(t) is the interaction part of the Hamiltonian.
For such a quantized detector interacting with a classical EM field, the latter is

<br /> \hat{H}_I(t) ~=~ - \frac{e}{m}\, \hat{p}_i(t) \hat{A}^i(r,t) ~.<br /> ~~~~~~~~(9.2-3)<br />

where \hat{p}_i(t) is the electron momentum,
\hat{A}_i(r,t) is the (classical, c-number) EM vector potential,
and the electron is initially in a tightly bound state at position r.

By standard techniques, equation (9.2-1) is formally integrated
iteratively (as usual for Volterra-type integral equations) to obtain:

<br /> |\psi(t)\rangle ~=~ |\psi(t_0)\rangle<br /> ~+~ \frac{1}{i\hbar} \int_{t_0}^t dt_1 \hat{H}_I(t_1) \, |\psi(t_0)\rangle<br /> ~+~ \mbox{(higher order terms in } \hat{H}_I) \dots<br /> ~~~~~~~~(9.2-8)<br />

In the situation being considered, truncation of the higher order terms
is acceptable. The transition probability from an initial state
|\psi(t_0)\rangle to some new state \Phi at time t
which is orthogonal to |\psi(t_0)\rangle is then approximately:

<br /> \left| \mbox{Transition probability} \right|<br /> ~=~ \left| \langle \Phi | \psi(t)\rangle \right|^2<br /> ~=~ \frac{1}{\hbar^2} \left| \int_{t_0}^t dt_1<br /> \langle \Phi | \hat{H}_I(t_1) |\psi(t_0)\rangle \right|^2<br /> ~~~~~~~~(9.2-9)<br />

Since we're working in the interaction picture, and the EM field is
a c-number here, the interaction part of the Hamiltonian at t_1
can be expressed in terms of an arbitrary initial time t_0 as

<br /> \hat{H}_I(t) ~=~ - \frac{e}{m} ~<br /> e^{i H_0 \Delta t/\hbar} \, \hat{p}_i(t_0) \,<br /> e^{-i H_0 \Delta t/\hbar} ~ \hat{A}^i(r,t) <br />

where \Delta t := t_1 - t_0.

With an extra (analytic signal representation) assumption about the
incident EM field, this is sufficient information to evaluate formula
(9.2-9) above, giving the probability that a transition occurs (i.e., a
photoelectron is produced) within a small time interval \Delta t.

In summary, one calculates the probability from an initial product state
consisting of quantized bound electron and incident EM field to a final
state in which the electron has been excited into the conduction band
under the interaction \hat{H}_I(t).

The important point from the above is that similar computations
could be done for other kinds of interactions, involving some field
incident on a many-body plate, with other possibilities for the final
state(s). For atom deposition, we could consider an field of atom type
"I" incident upon a lattice of atoms of type "L", where the final state
consists of a new bound state between a "L" atom and an "I" atom.
All that matters for the purposes of this thread is that a different final
state be possible, resulting from an interaction. Though the numbers
may differ, we still get the result that there's a certain finite transition
probability for an atom deposition at any particular point in a finite time.

The only difference from the photodetection case is that we must
think of the incident atom beam as a field, not a collection of
particles.

In any case, more accurate results are given by also quantizing the incident
field (c.f. M&W ch14) -- we still get atoms being deposited at random
places according to a transition probability per unit time.

Minimal QM (without the extra baggage of a "collapse" interpretation)
thus seems quite adequate.
 
Last edited:
  • #74
strangerep said:
Minimal QM (without the extra baggage of a "collapse" interpretation)
thus seems quite adequate.

strangerep,

what do you mean by "Minimal QM (without the extra baggage of a "collapse" interpretation)"? QM cannot be formulated without a collapse in some form. Once you started talking about Hilbert spaces and superpositions of states you have tacitly assumed the presence of a collapse.

The weirdness of the M&W model is that it places the collapse in an unusual place. Namely, in their model the collapse occurs when the photoelectron jumps to a continuous spectrum state. The probability of this jump is described by a square of a certain time-dependent wave function. This is exactly what is called "collapse" in quantum mechanics.

In the usual treatment of the double-slit experiment (see Feynman) the projectile is treated with a QM wave function. This treatment gives a full explanation of the shape of the interference picture and of the collapse effect. There is no need to build a quantum-mechanical model of the screen.

Eugene.
 
  • #75
meopemuk said:
what do you mean by "Minimal QM (without the extra baggage of a "collapse" interpretation)"?
I mean QM with an absolutely minimal amount of interpretation layered on top.
In particular, I have in mind the statistical interpretation as described by
Ballentine in his textbook and papers.

QM cannot be formulated without a collapse in some form. Once you started talking
about Hilbert spaces and superpositions of states you have tacitly assumed the
presence of a collapse.

Ballentine's statistical interpretation shows that this is not correct.

The weirdness of the M&W model is that it places the collapse in an unusual place. Namely, in their model the collapse occurs when the photoelectron jumps to a continuous spectrum state. The probability of this jump is described by a square of a certain time-dependent wave function. This is exactly what is called "collapse" in quantum mechanics.

I no longer see a need to talk about collapse at all, but only probability distributions.

Although the notion of collapse makes some semi-heuristic treatments of
certain situations easier to "explain", it comes at the cost of undesirable
features/paradoxes such as Schroedinger's cat.

In the usual treatment of the double-slit experiment (see Feynman) the projectile is
treated with a QM wave function. This treatment gives a full explanation of
the shape of the interference picture and of the collapse effect. There is no
need to build a quantum-mechanical model of the screen.

If one does utilize a simple quantum-mechanical model of the screen,
one no longer needs to postulate a collapse effect in order to account
for the observed phenomena.
 
Last edited:
  • #76
strangerep said:
I no longer see a need to talk about collapse at all, but only probability distributions.

Perhaps I am using a non-standard terminology, but for me "probability distribution" and "collapse" is the same thing. When you are talking about an ensemble you can say "probability distribution". When you are talking about individual event there is a "collapse". I didn't read Ballentine lately, but, as far as I remember, he didn't contradict this view.

strangerep said:
Although the notion of collapse makes some semi-heuristic treatments of
certain situations easier to "explain", it comes at the cost of undesirable
features/paradoxes such as Schroedinger's cat.

If you follow my advice not to make statements about non-observable quantum things, then Schroedinger's cat will not pose any paradox.


strangerep said:
If one does utilize a simple quantum-mechanical model of the screen,
one no longer needs to postulate a collapse effect in order to account
for the observed phenomena.

When M&W considered the quantum mechanical model of the screen they simply shifted the boundary between the quantum system and the measuring apparatus. Previously (e.g., in Feynman's approach), the screen played the role of the measuring apparatus. Now this role is played by the detector, which counts emitted photo-electrons. So, the collapse is still there, though not mentioned by name. The collapse occurs when the electron detector clicks.

Somewhere along the way M&W forgot that the incident photon should also have a quantum description. They've substituted photon's wave function with a classical field, which mimics quantum interference properties. This is OK as a rough approximation for the full quantum mechanical description of this experiment.

Eugene.
 
  • #77
meopemuk said:
The weirdness of the M&W model is that it places the collapse in an unusual place. Namely, in their model the collapse occurs when the photoelectron jumps to a continuous spectrum state.
There is nothing weird about the M&W setting. It is the _standard_ view in quantum optics. They place the collapse precisely where it belongs: Since it only happens in a measurement, it must be due to the interaction with the measurement device.
meopemuk said:
The probability of this jump is described by a square of a certain time-dependent wave function. This is exactly what is called "collapse" in quantum mechanics.
M&W assume that an electron is actually ejected according to the probabilities computed by the QM formulas. This is assumed in any interpretation of quantum mechanics, including the most weird ones. In particular also by no-collapse interpretations such as MWI or consistent histories.
meopemuk said:
In the usual treatment of the double-slit experiment (see Feynman) the projectile is treated with a QM wave function. This treatment gives a full explanation of the shape of the interference picture and of the collapse effect. There is no need to build a quantum-mechanical model of the screen.
meopemuk said:
The quantum mechanical model is needed to explain the photoelectric effect. It explains why a photographic plate acts as a measurement device while a candle light doesn't.

While the usual treatment explains nothing but simply _postulates_ that hitting the screen produces an event.
 
  • #78
strangerep said:
\hat{p}_i(t) is the electron momentum,
\hat{A}_i(r,t) is the (classical, c-number) EM vector potential,
and the case of an incident quantum field would be very similar, having here the vector potential operator. To a first approximation, this can be replaced by its expectation value, which is why the treatment as a classical field is often adequate. For a nonclassical incident field, one gets minor corrections; qualitatively nothing changes but quantitatively one has the usual O(hbar) differences.
strangerep said:
In summary, one calculates the probability from an initial product state
consisting of quantized bound electron and incident EM field to a final
state in which the electron has been excited into the conduction band
under the interaction \hat{H}_I(t).

The important point from the above is that similar computations
could be done for other kinds of interactions, involving some field
incident on a many-body plate, with other possibilities for the final
state(s). For atom deposition, we could consider an field of atom type
"I" incident upon a lattice of atoms of type "L", where the final state
consists of a new bound state between a "L" atom and an "I" atom.
All that matters for the purposes of this thread is that a different final
state be possible, resulting from an interaction. Though the numbers
may differ, we still get the result that there's a certain finite transition
probability for an atom deposition at any particular point in a finite time.

The only difference from the photodetection case is that we must
think of the incident atom beam as a field, not a collection of
particles.

In any case, more accurate results are given by also quantizing the incident
field (c.f. M&W ch14) -- we still get atoms being deposited at random
places according to a transition probability per unit time.

Minimal QM (without the extra baggage of a "collapse" interpretation)
thus seems quite adequate.
Yes. Thanks for the labor of writing out things explicitly!
 
  • #79
meopemuk said:
The probability theory predicts that in 50% of cases you'll see head up and in 50% of cases you'll see tail up. Similarly, QM predicts that a polarized photon will pass through the filter in 50% of cases and not pass in other 50% of cases. If you call this "prediction of output observables based on input observables", then yes, we agree.

The important thing is that both theories cannot tell you what will be the outcome in each individual case. So, there are some aspects of nature, which are totally unpredictable. That was my point.
And you call both collapse. You are the first person I heard about who postulates the collapse of coins upon throwing them.
 
  • #80
meopemuk said:
Yes, the transition between the random quantum regime and the predictable classical regime occurs gradually as N grows.
How should this come about in your interpretation? For N=1 you can say nothing without measuring it. But N times nothing is still nothing. How do you explain that you can gradually say more and more, until when N reached the size of the pointer of a measuring apparatus you can say definitely which position it has?
meopemuk said:
There is no unique threshold value. Some systems show quantum behavior even for very large N. The usual examples are superconductors and superfluid helium.
Ah. So you want to say we can't predict anything about superconductors and superfluid helium unless we have measured it? But these are used in industrial practice, where people have to rely on things working very predictably even without constantly measuring them!
meopemuk said:
A. Neumaier said:
Considered as a microscopic system, the detector is a highly chaotic dynamical system. Therefore, the individual binding sites for the atomic field behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident atom field, just as the outer electrons in a photodetector behave like random qubits responding to the intensity of the incident electromagnetic field. The response rate is proportional to the incident energy. Once one of the qubits fires, it uses up the whole energy and matter of the atom field, and the choice has been made. No other qubit can fire, by a most likely existing analogue of M&W's formula (14.8-16).

In quantum field theory, causality is therefore as well-behaved as in any classical stochastic process.
I see. So, you are a follower of Einstein's "God does not play dice" camp. So, you are saying that quantum uncertainties result from classical "hidden variables"?
If you read again what you quoted, you'll see no reference to hidden variables.
The quantum dynamics of the detector becomes, in the approximation of a system of qubits coupled to a semiclassical background formed by the remainder of the photographic plate, a quantum-classical system where the classical part is described by a chaotic
dynamics or - with less resolution - by a stochastic process. (Already few-particle quantum systems become chaotic in such a semiclassical description.)


meopemuk said:
So, if we could entangle all these stochastic chaotic classical processes, we would be able to predict the exact location of the atom deposition or pixel firing in each case. Is it right?
No, since already the classical model involves approximations, and even tiny errors in the model preclude deterministic predictions for a chaotic process.
meopemuk said:
On the other hand, your position is not pure as you mix classical fields and quantum mechanics in your version of quantum field theory. I find it inconsistent.
Classical fields are only for convenience, since they let one see better what is going on.
As mentioned in a previous post, quantum corrections are small and do not change the classical picture drastically. As long as the field expectation dominates the field fluctuations, one can safely ignore the quantum aspects.
 
  • #81
A. Neumaier said:
The quantum mechanical model is needed to explain the photoelectric effect. It explains why a photographic plate acts as a measurement device while a candle light doesn't.

While the usual treatment explains nothing but simply _postulates_ that hitting the screen produces an event.

Yes, the usual (Feynman) treatment is interested in demonstrating quantum properties of the photon. So, the boundary between the quantum system and the measuring apparatus is drawn in such a way that the photon is on the quantum side and is represented by a wave function. The photographic plate is on the "apparatus" side of the boundary. We are basically assuming that the photographic plate serves as an ideal measuring device for position. So, in our quantum 1-photon theory we represent this ideal measuring device by the position *operator*. (Let us not argue now about the absence of a rigorous photon position operator. I could use electron projectiles in my example to avoid your criticism.) Please note that I am not saying (as many other authors do) that the measuring apparatus is a classical object. In this theory the measuring apparatus has a quantum description, but not in terms of a wave function, but in terms of an Hermitian operator of observable -- in this case the observable of position.

This treatment coupled with the collapse postulate allows us to reproduce all significant features of the single-photon interference: the randomness of photon hits and the accumulation of these hits along the constructive interference spots.


Now, you can say that you are not satisfied with the above idealized treatment of the photographic plate, and you want to include the plate in the quantum-mechanical part of the description. Fine, you are definitely allowed to do that. But this doesn't save you from the necessity to use the collapse postulate. You've simply defined the quantum part of the world differently and thus moved the boundary between the quantum system and the measuring apparatus to a different place. Now, your quantum system includes both the incident photon and the photographic plate with all its atoms. This part of the world is described by a wave function. The measuring apparatus in this case could be a detector catching emitted photo-electrons or your eye's retina that registers sunlight reflected from the photographic plate. Just as before, the collapse occurs at the "boundary" between the physical system and the measuring apparatus. This new measuring apparatus is described by a Hermitian operator.

My point is that no matter how exact you want your quantum description to be, you must always have a boundary between the quantum physical system and the measuring apparatus. There is always a collapse happening at this boundary. This separation of the world in two distinct parts is reflected in the formalism of quantum mechanics quite naturally: the quantum system is described by a state vector or a wave function; the measuring apparatus is described by a Hermitian operator of some observable. You need both these mathematical components in order to have a complete quantum-mechanical theory. It it not possible to describe the whole world by one wave function.

Eugene.
 
  • #82
A. Neumaier said:
And you call both collapse. You are the first person I heard about who postulates the collapse of coins upon throwing them.

You've probably misunderstood. harrylin said that QM predict output observables based on input observables. I disagreed by saying that QM prediction is only probabilistic. In this sense, QM is not doing a better job at predictions than classical probability theory with coins. There is one important difference, though. When we through a coin, we can in principle predict the result (head or tail) with 100% certainty. This is very difficult, but possible within classical mechanics. On the other hand, when we let a photon to pass through a polarizer filter, there is absolutely no way to predict the outcome. This is one important difference between quantum and classical probabilities.

I've never said that classical coin experiences any kind of collapse.

Eugene.
 
  • #83
A. Neumaier said:
No, since already the classical model involves approximations, and even tiny errors in the model preclude deterministic predictions for a chaotic process.

Could you please be more clear? Are you saying that there exists a distinct classical trajectory behind each (seemingly random) quantum event? So, you are saying that this trajectory involves many degrees of freedom, is chaotic, stochastic, etc. and for this reason we cannot make deterministic predictions. However, if we (humans) had unlimited power to control the errors, to observe and calculate things, then we would be able, in principle, to disentangle this seemingly chaotic process and to predict with 100% certainty the place of photon's landing in the double-slit experiment. Is this what you're actually saying, or I am misinterpreting your words?

Eugene.
 
  • #84
A. Neumaier said:
...no-collapse interpretations such as MWI or consistent histories.

We disagree about the meaning of "collapse" in quantum mechanics. I would say that MWI and consistent histories need the same collapse as Copenhagen. These models simply hide the fact that they use the collapse. For example, in MWI the collapse occurs when we choose the "right" universe randomly.

In general, every time we use word "probability" we mean "collapse". The collapse does not happen in classical mechanics, because everything is predictable there and probabilities reduce to either 1 (yes) or 0 (no). If sometimes we use classical probabilities, like in coin tossing, we are simply lazy and don't want to bother to specify all necessary conditions exactly.

So, there can be only two legitimate interpretations of quantum mechanics. One is the "hidden variable" interpretation, which basically says that QM is just a branch of classical mechanics, where everything is deterministic and predictable. No probabilities involved and no collapse. The other interpretation is that quantum events are truly random. Then the collapse is needed. There is no third way.

Eugene.
 
  • #85
Just a question. Let's say that I radiate some form of energy into a group of many people. Sometimes, casually, one of those persons feels "excited" because of that energy and jumps for some seconds. Where is the "collapse"?
 
  • #86
lightarrow said:
Just a question. Let's say that I radiate some form of energy into a group of many people. Sometimes, casually, one of those persons feels "excited" because of that energy and jumps for some seconds. Where is the "collapse"?

Lightarrow... do we meet again? Are you the man I knew from the Naked Scientists?

To answer your question, if it was possible for some quantity of energy to be tranferred, rather than simply radiated into the body of another person, then collapses may occur if there are decoherences in the stucture of the other person. These simple decoherences are collapse-like state systems.

It's a bit of an odd question, but if you are the man I remember, then it's not a great surprise :)
 
  • #87
meopemuk said:
Now, your quantum system includes both the incident photon and the photographic plate with all its atoms. This part of the world is described by a wave function. The measuring apparatus in this case
is the photomultiplier or the chemical reaction. Both are dissipative processes that proceed locally, and essentially classically, and need because of the large number of particles involved no special treatment beyond the statistical interpretation (without the explicit collapse).

Of course, you could call any statistical element ''collapse'', but this is not the standard way of using the term. If you use your personal terminology, the only result is that nobody understand you anymore.
 
  • #88
meopemuk said:
When we through a coin, we can in principle predict the result (head or tail) with 100% certainty.
No, we cannot, since throwing a coin is a chaotic process, especially when it first lands on the edge. You need an accuracy for the intial data that one is never able to collect.
Not even in principle can a (classical or quantum) object collect enough information about a coin to exactly determine its state. And already tiny uncertainties magnify immensely.
 
  • #89
meopemuk said:
Could you please be more clear? Are you saying that there exists a distinct classical trajectory behind each (seemingly random) quantum event?
No, but that there is an approximate classical description behind each quantum system, and the latter is chaotic, and sufficient to describe the behavior of a photomultiplier or the approach to chemical equilibrium. Nobody models these in a full quantum mechnaical model, since it is a huge waste of effort.
meopemuk said:
However, if we (humans) had unlimited power to control the errors, to observe and calculate things
I am interested in explaining the world as it is, not a magic version of it.
 
  • #90
meopemuk said:
We disagree about the meaning of "collapse" in quantum mechanics.
I know. I am using the standard meaning, while you mix it up with the simpler version of Born's rule, which makes no statement about what happens to the state in a measurement.
meopemuk said:
I would say that MWI and consistent histories need the same collapse as Copenhagen. These models simply hide the fact that they use the collapse.
They claim they don't. That's all I meant when citing them. I agree that they don't succeed in that, but this is a different matter.

In any case, you can't redefine the meaning of the word collapse. It means no more and no less than that one pretends to know after a measurement that the system is in an eigenstate corresponding to the measured eigenvalue.

But this is completely irrelevant for being able to read a pointer on an instrument telling that there was a nonzero current produced by the photomultiplier. This process is so macroscopic that it is universally described in terms of thermodynamics - one gets an expectation value rather than an eigenvalue!

Moreover, the collapse is provably wrong in case a single photon is measured by a photodetector. It is after the measurement not in a position eigenstate but it has no state anymore!
 
  • #91
lightarrow said:
Just a question. Let's say that I radiate some form of energy into a group of many people. Sometimes, casually, one of those persons feels "excited" because of that energy and jumps for some seconds. Where is the "collapse"?

This is actually a good analogy of the photoelectron emission process as described in Chapter 9 of Mandel & Wolf. The collapse (in my non-standard terminology) happens when a person feels excited for no good reason. If there is no deterministic explanation of this excitation, then we have an unpredictable truly random effect, which I call collapse.

Before the collapse the state of this person could be described by probability, i.e., the chance to be excited is X, the chance to be not excited is 1-X. After the excitation has materialized this probability distribution has collapsed to a certain state.

Eugene.
 
  • #92
A. Neumaier said:
Of course, you could call any statistical element ''collapse'', but this is not the standard way of using the term. If you use your personal terminology, the only result is that nobody understand you anymore.

I use the word "collapse" every time when a probability distribution (i.e., incomplete knowledge) is converted to an actual event (complete knowledge).

I wouldn't use the word collapse in the case of coin tossing, because the coin movement is described by classical mechanics, which is capable of predicting the outcome with 100% certainty if the initial state if fully specified. Yes, this is difficult to do in the case of a coin or turbulence or other seemingly untractable "chaotic" classical systems. But "difficult" or "impractical" does not mean "impossible". So, in my understanding, there is no probability associated with classical coin tossing or turbulence. So, there is no collapse.

Quantum mechanical systems are fundamentally different from the tossed coin. When electron passes through a single-slit or a double-slit there is absolutely no way to predict where it will land. This is a truly unpredictable system. Before actual landing on the screen the electron is described by a probability density (square of the wave function) which collapses after the observation is made.

Eugene.
 
  • #93
meopemuk said:
I use the word "collapse" every time when a probability distribution (i.e., incomplete knowledge) is converted to an actual event (complete knowledge).
Compare this with the conventional mainstream meaning:
''wave function collapse (also called collapse of the state vector or reduction of the wave packet) is the phenomenon in which a wave function—initially in a superposition of several different possible eigenstates—appears to reduce to a single one of those states after interaction with an observer. '' http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wavefunction_collapse
meopemuk said:
I wouldn't use the word collapse in the case of coin tossing, because the coin movement is described by classical mechanics, which is capable of predicting the outcome with 100% certainty if the initial state if fully specified. But "difficult" or "impractical" does not mean "impossible". So, in my understanding, there is no probability associated with classical coin tossing or turbulence. So, there is no collapse.
But your definition that ''a probability distribution (i.e., incomplete knowledge) is converted to an actual event (complete knowledge)'' fully applies in practice. So your definition of collapse seems inconsistent.
 
  • #94
QuantumClue said:
Lightarrow... do we meet again? Are you the man I knew from the Naked Scientists?
Hello QuantumClue!

To answer your question, if it was possible for some quantity of energy to be tranferred, rather than simply radiated into the body of another person, then collapses may occur if there are decoherences in the stucture of the other person. These simple decoherences are collapse-like state systems.
I used that metaphor to express the idea that a quantum description is not needed for that effect.

It's a bit of an odd question, but if you are the man I remember, then it's not a great surprise :)
But quantum physics is odder, isnt'it? :smile:
 
  • #95
A. Neumaier said:
But your definition that ''a probability distribution (i.e., incomplete knowledge) is converted to an actual event (complete knowledge)'' fully applies in practice. So your definition of collapse seems inconsistent.

I don't think our knowledge is incomplete when we are tossing a coin. Yes, it is incomplete in practice, because we are too lazy to specify all initial conditions exactly and to perform all necessary calculations.

On the other hand, when we are sending a polarized photon through a filter, the result is unpredictable. No matter how careful we are in preparing their state, the photons will behave unpredictably.

This is why coin tossing can be described (in principle, but possibly not in practice) by classical mechanics, and in order to describe photons or electrons we need quantum mechanics.

If you don't want to recognize this difference between classical and quantum mechanics, then you represent the "hidden variables" interpretation camp.

Eugene.
 
  • #96
meopemuk said:
So, there can be only two legitimate interpretations of quantum mechanics. One is the "hidden variable" interpretation, which basically says that QM is just a branch of classical mechanics, where everything is deterministic and predictable. No probabilities involved and no collapse. The other interpretation is that quantum events are truly random. Then the collapse is needed. There is no third way.

Isn't that perspective a bit too limiting? One should be allowed the option of approaching every problem with the aim of finding at least one "hidden variable". Sometimes, maybe often, those variables will be so sensitively balanced that chaotic conditions pertain to the result. But in searching and possibly finding such a variable one might ultimately find some other characteristic that isn't deterministic. In other words, we recognize the difference between deterministic-predictive variables, deterministic-chaotic variables producing effectively unpredictable results and fully non-deterministic variables where anyone situation may may be composed of variables of each type.
 
Last edited:
  • #97
meopemuk said:
I don't think our knowledge is incomplete when we are tossing a coin. Yes, it is incomplete in practice, because we are too lazy to specify all initial conditions exactly and to perform all necessary calculations.
No, because it is impossible. We cannot even specify single real numbers to infinite precision (and rounding them to a rational creates already enough uncertainty to make chaos apply after a very short time.
meopemuk said:
On the other hand, when we are sending a polarized photon through a filter, the result is unpredictable. No matter how careful we are in preparing their state, the photons will behave unpredictably.
This is unpredictable only in a particle picture. In a field picture, polarization is very easy to understand. The qubit was understood classically almost 50 years before Planck discovered the first hint to quantum mechanics - see slides 6-15 of my lecture http://arnold-neumaier.at/ms/optslides.pdf

The only reason why the Schroedinger equation wasn't found by Stokes in 1852 was that there was no incentive to do so...
meopemuk said:
This is why coin tossing can be described (in principle, but possibly not in practice) by classical mechanics, and in order to describe photons or electrons we need quantum mechanics.
Of course we need quantum mechanics to describe photons and electrons and dice.
A die is a quantum mechanical object - but it behaves approximately classically to such an extent that we hardly ever regard it as a quantum object. But a correct account of its falling behavior would require that.

On the other hand, we don't need a collapse to predict the laws of elasticity and classical motion of a die from a quantum mechanical basis. We only need Ehrenfest's theorem.
 
Last edited:
  • #98
meopemuk said:
[..] If you don't want to recognize this difference between classical and quantum mechanics, then you represent the "hidden variables" interpretation camp.

Eugene.

Why do you want to push people in "camps" that they may not have joined?
 
  • #99
A. Neumaier said:
..You could as well claim that the fact that a shower emits tiny rays of water is proof that water is composed of discrete rays...The corrections obtained by using QED instead of the classical external field are very tiny and can be neglected...
Then, how on Earth can the tiny dots be interpreted as an indication that light is a flow of discrete particles rather than a continuous wave? The external field used to generate the pattern _is_ a continuous wave, as one can trivially verify by inspecting the model...This is enough to make the conclusion invalid that the tiny dots must be regarded as proof of a discrete particle structure of the incident radiation...These discussions revealed to me that real-life photons are something very different from what superficial discussions seemed to suggest.
That was from #14. Still not clear just how the QFT and classical EM pictures differ. In some places you speak of 'more or less localised' photon states, elsewhere that 'the wave spreads out beyond the slit' etc. Unless there are two or more distinctly different models of what constitutes a photon/photon state in QFT, I am assuming localization is simply the result of wave interference as for instance in an antenna array or multi-mode cavity resonator. Wrong? Consider a specific case. An excited atom in vacuo undergoes spontaneous decay into ground state, emitting a field quanta (avoiding the 'p' word). Classically, the emission might be described as a weighted ensemble of multipole fields that propagates as a spherical pulse with superposed multipole angular distributions. At large r the field gets very tenuous but never becomes 'granular'. To what extent is the QFT picture different?
 
  • #100
Q-reeus said:
That was from #14. Still not clear just how the QFT and classical EM pictures differ. In some places you speak of 'more or less localised' photon states, elsewhere that 'the wave spreads out beyond the slit' etc. Unless there are two or more distinctly different models of what constitutes a photon/photon state in QFT,
The quantum field is described by a state, defining expectation values of the field operators. By the Ehrenfest theorem http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ehrenfest_theorem , these expectations correspond exactly to the classical e/m field, independent of the photon content of the state. Measurements respond to this field and/or to the associated coherence fields, given by the expectations of certain bilinear expressions in the fields - among them is the energy density of the field. To see the nonclassical character of a quantum field, one needs to make correlation experiments that exhibit the deviating statistical properties.

The notion of photon is commonly used with two different meanings:
1. as a localized wave packet of approximate frequency omega and approximate total (integrated over time) energy omega*hbar, in some cases generated by a single atomic event;
2. as synonymous to a 1-photon state. The latter are in 1-1 correspondence with classical solutions of the Maxwell equations, but they are Fock states with very nonclassical properties.
This explains why the classical and the quantum field descriptions are quite similar, even when talking about single photons.
Q-reeus said:
I am assuming localization is simply the result of wave interference as for instance in an antenna array or multi-mode cavity resonator. Wrong?
Interference creates the pattern. Localization is associated with the fact that a single, localized electron responds (according to a process whose rate is proportional to the intensity pattern).
Q-reeus said:
Consider a specific case. An excited atom in vacuo undergoes spontaneous decay into ground state, emitting a field quanta (avoiding the 'p' word). Classically, the emission might be described as a weighted ensemble of multipole fields that propagates as a spherical pulse with superposed multipole angular distributions. At large r the field gets very tenuous but never becomes 'granular'. To what extent is the QFT picture different?
The field expectation values are precisely what the classical picture suggests.

The quantum nature is reflected by the knowledge that in this particular situation (far from easy to produce experimentally to good accuracy and with high efficiency) the quantum field state is a 1-photon state. This is usually completely inconsequential, but can make a significant difference in special correlation experiments.
 

Similar threads

Replies
21
Views
2K
Replies
1
Views
996
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
15
Views
4K
Replies
19
Views
3K
Replies
4
Views
1K
Back
Top