Almost Certain = 1? Why Reject Surreal Numbers?

  • Thread starter Thread starter lolgarithms
  • Start date Start date
AI Thread Summary
The discussion centers on the definition of "almost certain" in probability theory, equating it to a probability of exactly 1. It argues that while surreal numbers and infinitesimals might seem appealing, they complicate the established framework of probability, which relies on measure functions defined within the interval [0,1]. The probability of selecting a rational number from a continuous interval is shown to be 0, leading to the conclusion that the probability of selecting an irrational number is 1. This aligns with the measure theory perspective, where an event is considered almost certain if its complement has a measure of zero. The conversation emphasizes the importance of adhering to conventional probability definitions to maintain clarity and consistency.
lolgarithms
Messages
120
Reaction score
0
Why is "almost certain" := EXACTLY 1? Shouldn't it be 1 minus an infinitesimal (reciprocal of an infinite cardinal) for a dense space? (Why aren't surreal numbers acceptable?)
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Because the reciprocal of a cardinal has no meaning here...

The probability of an event A occurring is defined by a measure function, which essentially is a way of measuring the area that A occupies with respect to W. The measure function is defined to take a real value between [0,1], you could pick other measure functions but then you're not following the definition of a probability.

One standard example is if you have the interval [0,1] and you pick a number at random, what is the probability that you pick a rational number?

We define the probability of picking a number inside of an interval (a,b) as b-a (and as [0,1] has length 1 we see this defines a probability). Then since the rationals are countable, we can list them q_1, q_2,... and around q_i we can construct an interval of length \frac{e}{2^n} for any e>0. Then adding up all the lengths of the intervals gives us at least the probability that we pick a number inside one of those intervals (if there's overlap, then we overestimated, but that's OK). We have geometric series, so this comes out to a total probability of e. But e was arbitrary, so the probability of picking a rational number < e for all e>0, so it must be zero. Hence the probability of picking an irrational number is 1.

So while it is possible that you pick a rational number, the probability is 0. A possible interpretation in practical terms is that even if you keep picking numbers at random, your chance of picking a rational number never increases, whereas if the probability was anything other than 0, your chance of eventually picking one would increase to 1 as you make more picks

As an aside, notice that Q is dense in R but the probability was 0, not 1. Knowing a set is dense doesn't tell you anything about its probability
 
Colloquially, "almost" can mean "with great (but non unity) probability", as in: "the probability that he will be late for the meeting is almost 100%".

So I will assume that you mean "almost" in the mathematical sense here, which involves measure theory. Let X be the set of possible outcomes of an experiment, and we define a measure μ on X such that μ(X) = 1. Now we can define events as subsets A of X (note that there is implicitly a sigma algebra floating around here which I am not mentioning) and the probability of event A is then μ(A). Then by definition, we can say that A is almost certain to happen, when the probability that A is not going to happen is zero. That is, if the complement is a null set: μ(AC) = 0.

Example. What is the probability that if we pick a random number from [0, 1], it will be irrational? Well, in most applications you would tacitly assume that [0, 1] is equipped with Lebesgue measure λ. Well, the set of rational numbers is a null set for this measure: λ(Q) = 0. So the probability we're interested in is λ(QC) = 1 - λ(Q) = 1.

This definition makes sense, although it may be a little counter-intuitive at first. As you suggest, the most logical way to overcome this would be to work with infinitesimal numbers, but then we have to give up the idea that we can express probabilities as a percentage between 0 and 100 (i.e. a probability measure is a map from the sigma algebra to the interval [0, 1]).
 
I was reading documentation about the soundness and completeness of logic formal systems. Consider the following $$\vdash_S \phi$$ where ##S## is the proof-system making part the formal system and ##\phi## is a wff (well formed formula) of the formal language. Note the blank on left of the turnstile symbol ##\vdash_S##, as far as I can tell it actually represents the empty set. So what does it mean ? I guess it actually means ##\phi## is a theorem of the formal system, i.e. there is a...
Back
Top