Is information lost in wavefunction collapse?

In summary: Yes, there is a specific spin measurement that you would observe if you were in a closed environment with the SG.
  • #36
atyy said:
Carroll states that MWI has serious issues

But he also says, as you quote, that it is "way ahead of any proposed alternative".

atyy said:
If even supporters of MWI still think there are major problems with MWI, then it cannot be considered textbook physics.

By this reasoning, no interpretation of QM can be considered "textbook physics". Is that your position?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #37
atyy said:
The usual approach, eg, AdS/CFT to try to solve the paradox would also solve it for Copenhagen.

Unless "everything is always unitary" is consistent with what you mean by "Copenhagen", I don't see how this could be true. And if "everything is always unitary" is consistent with what you mean by "Copenhagen", then I am very confused as to what you mean by "Copenhagen".
 
  • #38
atyy said:
If even supporters of MWI still think there are major problems with MWI, then it cannot be considered textbook physics.
All interpretations have major issues - that's why we can spend so much time arguing about them, and also why pointing out the issues cannot settle these arguments.

It would be a bad thing if this thread were to degenerate into another form of "your interpretation is uglier than mine".
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #39
What is the technical definition for "information" in the context of this thread?
 
  • #40
I had a similar question months ago, (https://www.physicsforums.com/threads/where-does-the-energy-go.930637/)Even though it wasn't mentioned in the thread, if you take the collapse interpretation to be true, I believe you are essentially saying that your information (states) are not coupled to the environment until a measurement is taken place. So no information is loss even in the Copenhagen interpretation because as far the environment knows, there was really only one option?

If your information is coupled to the environment, then in theory, you would be able to measure the energy output of each state via some gravitational wave (I think Davies worked out some hand-wavy calculations in the 60/70s, i'll send references for anyone interested)... but maybe that's not for this thread :).

There are so many ifs when dealing with which is why...

Stephen Tashi said:
What is the technical definition for "information" in the context of this thread?

I think to make any movement in a thread like this, this is the right way to go. Otherwise we will all just talk around each other using ambiguous words. Math triumphs. As far as I'm aware, information in QM is referred to as states! But what states are we considering? An energy operator is different than a position operator, and then some other people started talking about bits! If we start talking about bits, then there is already a reason how THAT information loss is handled! If we start to think as information as bits, then why not just invoke Launder's principle and call it a day?

Just to clarify, as far as I'm aware Launder's principle might not apply to quantum systems, but I'm not an expert in quantum computing nor computing in general!
 
  • #41
PeterDonis said:
Unless "everything is always unitary" is consistent with what you mean by "Copenhagen", I don't see how this could be true. And if "everything is always unitary" is consistent with what you mean by "Copenhagen", then I am very confused as to what you mean by "Copenhagen".

Well it depends on what one means by "everything". For the information paradox, there is a reasonable definition of everything. In Copenhagen, everything is unitary between measurements.
 
  • #42
PeterDonis said:
By this reasoning, no interpretation of QM can be considered "textbook physics". Is that your position?

Yes, except for Copenhagen or whatever one wishes to call what is in the textbooks.
 
  • #43
Nugatory said:
It would be a bad thing if this thread were to degenerate into another form of "your interpretation is uglier than mine".

It has nothing to do with ugliness, but correctness. It is not correct, in a thread which mentions standard QM, and makes sense within standard QM, to tell the OP that his question doesn't make sense, by bringing in speculative approaches to the measurement problem as if it is settled physics - here I use speculative in the sense that string theory is speculative and not settled physics (although I do think it is the leading approach to quantum gravity).
 
  • #44
Nugatory said:
It would be a bad thing if this thread were to degenerate into another form of "your interpretation is uglier than mine".

To add to my comment above, the OP is not a question about interpretations. Bringing in interpretations as Peter Donis did is irrelevant to the OP. The point is that the non-unitary evolution of collapse, and that of the information paradox are not related as I tried to say in post #20, and as Demystifier says clearly in post #30.
 
  • #45
Demystifier said:
Even though collapse and apparent disappearance of information by black hole evaporation both violate unitarity, those two processes are not directly related. They violate unitarity in very different ways.
In a collapse, a pure state evolves (jumps) into another pure state.
By black hole evaporation, a pure state evolves into a mixed state.

I'm not sure I understand the distinction you are making. The way I understand "mixed state" in quantum mechanics, there are two different sources of mixed states:
  1. If you don't know what the state of a system is, then you can represent it as a mixed state, where the probabilities reflect your subjective uncertainty about what the pure state is.
  2. A pure state involving two subsystems (the system of interest and the environment, say) can be treated as a mixed state of just one of the subsystems, by a kind of averaging over the system that you're not interested in.
When people say that a black hole turns a pure state into a mixed state, I'm not exactly sure what notion of "mixed state" is meant. But if it is #1, then it seems to me equivalent to a measurement collapsing the wave function, but you don't know what the measurement result was.
 
  • #46
atyy said:
To add to my comment above, the OP is not a question about interpretations. Bringing in interpretations as Peter Donis did is irrelevant to the OP. The point is that the non-unitary evolution of collapse, and that of the information paradox are not related as I tried to say in post #20, and as Demystifier says clearly in post #30.

I agree with the point you and @Demystifier make that these two things (collapse vs. BH information paradox) are different. Are you saying that that, in itself, is a sufficient answer to the question in the OP? If so, I would like the OP to say whether he agrees with that.
 
  • #47
atyy said:
It is not correct, in a thread which mentions standard QM, and makes sense within standard QM, to tell the OP that his question doesn't make sense, by bringing in speculative approaches to the measurement problem as if it is settled physics

But in "standard QM", the OP's question can't be answered, because standard QM allows both kinds of interpretations: interpretations in which information is not lost in "wave function collapse" (because "collapse" is not a real process but just a calculational rule, no real non-unitary processes ever happen--for example, the MWI), and interpretations in which information is lost in collapse, because collapse is a real, non-unitary process.
 
  • Like
Likes bhobba
  • #48
atyy said:
it depends on what one means by "everything"

Yes, which is exactly why the answer to the OP's question must be interpretation dependent: some interpretations, like the MWI, mean by "everything" literally everything--nothing non-unitary ever happens, anywhere in the universe. Whereas other interpretations only interpret "everything" to mean "everything between measurements" (and some go on to claim that during a measurement, an actual non-unitary process, wave function collapse, happens, while others are agnostic about this).
 
  • #49
stevendaryl said:
I'm not sure I understand the distinction you are making. The way I understand "mixed state" in quantum mechanics, there are two different sources of mixed states:
  1. If you don't know what the state of a system is, then you can represent it as a mixed state, where the probabilities reflect your subjective uncertainty about what the pure state is.
  2. A pure state involving two subsystems (the system of interest and the environment, say) can be treated as a mixed state of just one of the subsystems, by a kind of averaging over the system that you're not interested in.
When people say that a black hole turns a pure state into a mixed state, I'm not exactly sure what notion of "mixed state" is meant. But if it is #1, then it seems to me equivalent to a measurement collapsing the wave function, but you don't know what the measurement result was.
It is neither #1 nor #2. It is

3. Initially you have a pure state involving two entangled subsystems, one inside the black hole and the other outside of the black hole. So initially it corresponds to your 2. But then the inside subsystem gets destroyed in the black hole singularity, so what remains is only the outside subsystem, which is in a mixed state but no longer entangled with anything.
 
  • #50
Demystifier said:
It is neither #1 nor #2. It is

3. Initially you have a pure state involving two entangled subsystems, one inside the black hole and the other outside of the black hole. So initially it corresponds to your 2. But then the inside subsystem gets destroyed in the black hole singularity, so what remains is only the outside subsystem, which is in a mixed state but no longer entangled with anything.

Thanks. So that really is something new.

So the idea is that you create an EPR pair---an electron and positron with entangled anticorrelated spins. You throw the positron into a black hole, which then vanishes in a puff of Hawking radiation. Now, you still have the electron, but the electron by itself was not in a pure state, it was in an entangled state. So how do you describe it now that its entangled partner no longer exists? A mixed state.

Now that I say it out loud, it occurs to me that in the case of spin entanglement, you might still have the electron entangled, rather than in mixed state. When the positron falls into the black hole, it imparts a tiny bit of angular moment to the black hole. When the black hole evaporates, that angular momentum is distributed among the particles produced by the Hawking radiation. So in that particular case, it seems that the electron's spin would be entangled with the resulting Hawking radiation. So I think to really illustrate the information loss, you would need some property of a pair of particles that is nonconserved?
 
  • #51
atyy said:
All the major textbooks use Copenhagen. Standard QM is the Copenhagen interpretation.

Agreed, but standard here just means a standard presentation in Physics education.

atyy said:
Yes, except for Copenhagen or whatever one wishes to call what is in the textbooks.

Sure, but the presence in textbooks is a stronger case for a consensus regarding what to teach students, it may not represent a consensus regarding a preference for truth or correctness.

It's an imperfect analogy, but one might argue that Newtonian mechanics is the "right" version of mechanics, because it is found in many more introductory textbooks (and therefore more textbooks, since most texts are introductory.) However, it is completely equivalent to Lagrangian mechanics and Hamiltonian mechanics. The consensus to teach Newtonian mechanics first (which I believe is correct) is based more on its usefulness with the math skills of most students in these classes rather than some sense that it is more correct than Lagrangian or Hamiltonian.

I would not make any more from the lack of alternate QM interpretations in the textbooks than I'd make from the piles and piles of Physics texts that ignore Lagrangian and Hamiltonian mechanics.
 
  • Like
Likes DrClaude and martinbn
  • #52
stevendaryl said:
Thanks. So that really is something new.

So the idea is that you create an EPR pair---an electron and positron with entangled anticorrelated spins. You throw the positron into a black hole, which then vanishes in a puff of Hawking radiation. Now, you still have the electron, but the electron by itself was not in a pure state, it was in an entangled state. So how do you describe it now that its entangled partner no longer exists? A mixed state.

Now that I say it out loud, it occurs to me that in the case of spin entanglement, you might still have the electron entangled, rather than in mixed state. When the positron falls into the black hole, it imparts a tiny bit of angular moment to the black hole. When the black hole evaporates, that angular momentum is distributed among the particles produced by the Hawking radiation. So in that particular case, it seems that the electron's spin would be entangled with the resulting Hawking radiation.
That's correct.

stevendaryl said:
So I think to really illustrate the information loss, you would need some property of a pair of particles that is nonconserved?
No. Instead of angular momentum, consider e.g. lepton number which is supposed to be conserved. If you have electron with positive lepton number outside and positron with negative lepton number inside, the total lepton number is zero. However, the lepton number cannot be seen in the external properties of geometry of the black hole (this is the so called no-hair theorem). When the black hole finally evaporates, the negative lepton number in the inside disappears. Hence the black hole evaporation violates the lepton number conservation, which otherwise is conserved.
 
  • #53
Demystifier said:
No. Instead of angular momentum, consider e.g. lepton number which is supposed to be conserved

I would say that quantities such as lepton number or baryon number are not actually conserved. It just happens to be that there are no interactions that cause it to change. :wink:

I of course didn't understand it, but t'Hooft gave an argument a long time ago to the effect that baryon number is not conserved in the standard model. So proton decay, for example, is a prediction of the standard model, even though no finite number of Feynman diagrams can show it. It's a nonperturbative effect. I'm pretty sure that he didn't consider black holes. (This prediction does not contradict the experimental evidence that protons don't decay, because t'Hooft's mechanism is way too weak to produce a detectable number of proton decay events. It's many orders of magnitude smaller than the number of decays predicted by various GUT theories.)
 
  • #54
stevendaryl said:
I would say that quantities such as lepton number or baryon number are not actually conserved. It just happens to be that there are no interactions that cause it to change. :wink:

I of course didn't understand it, but t'Hooft gave an argument a long time ago to the effect that baryon number is not conserved in the standard model. So proton decay, for example, is a prediction of the standard model, even though no finite number of Feynman diagrams can show it. It's a nonperturbative effect. I'm pretty sure that he didn't consider black holes. (This prediction does not contradict the experimental evidence that protons don't decay, because t'Hooft's mechanism is way too weak to produce a detectable number of proton decay events. It's many orders of magnitude smaller than the number of decays predicted by various GUT theories.)

It is stated here (http://inspirehep.net/record/16152/files/v16-n1-p23.pdf) that decays by t'Hooft's mechanism are ##10^{-77}## less common than predicted decays by GUT theories.
 
  • #55
stevendaryl said:
I would say that quantities such as lepton number or baryon number are not actually conserved. It just happens to be that there are no interactions that cause it to change. :wink:

I of course didn't understand it, but t'Hooft gave an argument a long time ago to the effect that baryon number is not conserved in the standard model. So proton decay, for example, is a prediction of the standard model, even though no finite number of Feynman diagrams can show it. It's a nonperturbative effect. I'm pretty sure that he didn't consider black holes. (This prediction does not contradict the experimental evidence that protons don't decay, because t'Hooft's mechanism is way too weak to produce a detectable number of proton decay events. It's many orders of magnitude smaller than the number of decays predicted by various GUT theories.)
Even in GUT theories one has a conservation of a difference between baryon and lepton number B-L, but black hole evaporation violates it too.
 
  • #56
PeterDonis said:
I agree with the point you and @Demystifier make that these two things (collapse vs. BH information paradox) are different. Are you saying that that, in itself, is a sufficient answer to the question in the OP? If so, I would like the OP to say whether he agrees with that.

Yes, I do mean that those two things are sufficient for answering the OP (or at least for correcting the use of the black hole information paradox as motivation for the question in the OP). There is no need to bring in interpretations of QM.

There is the additional question of whether information is lost in collapse. This needs to be defined a bit better (eg. as stevendaryl has discussed at various points in this thread, but one can use standard QM, which includes collapse).
 
  • #57
PeterDonis said:
But in "standard QM", the OP's question can't be answered, because standard QM allows both kinds of interpretations: interpretations in which information is not lost in "wave function collapse" (because "collapse" is not a real process but just a calculational rule, no real non-unitary processes ever happen--for example, the MWI), and interpretations in which information is lost in collapse, because collapse is a real, non-unitary process.

stevendaryl's post #25 frames and answers this question in a way that is independent of the subtleties you mentioned. (As a side point, it is not really common to take collapse to be physical in Copenhagen. Physical collapse usually refers to alternative theories like GRW or CSL).
 
  • #58
Dr. Courtney said:
Sure, but the presence in textbooks is a stronger case for a consensus regarding what to teach students, it may not represent a consensus regarding a preference for truth or correctness.

It's an imperfect analogy, but one might argue that Newtonian mechanics is the "right" version of mechanics, because it is found in many more introductory textbooks (and therefore more textbooks, since most texts are introductory.) However, it is completely equivalent to Lagrangian mechanics and Hamiltonian mechanics. The consensus to teach Newtonian mechanics first (which I believe is correct) is based more on its usefulness with the math skills of most students in these classes rather than some sense that it is more correct than Lagrangian or Hamiltonian.

I would not make any more from the lack of alternate QM interpretations in the textbooks than I'd make from the piles and piles of Physics texts that ignore Lagrangian and Hamiltonian mechanics.

Yes, but the difference is that there are many advanced textbooks teaching the Lagrangain and Hamiltonian formalisms and their equivalence to Newtonian mechanics, and there is consensus in the community about these issues.

In the case of MWI, there are no advanced textbooks stating that MWI is standard QM - Cohen-Tannoudji, Sakurai and Weinberg are senior undergraduate level textboks, about the same level at which the Lagrangian and Hamiltonian formalisms are usually discussed. In fact, the research level discussions state problems MWI, even by people who are proponents of the approach. Stating unresolved physics as if it is standard is bad for beginners, because it is misleading false advertising, Stating unresolved physics as if it is standard is also bad for people who support the approach, because it means that we should stop research into these open questions, which ultimately means that the questions will never pass from being unresolved to resolved.
 
  • Like
Likes Mentz114
  • #59
atyy said:
it is not really common to take collapse to be physical in Copenhagen

If that is the case, then I don't think it's correct to describe the standard QM collapse as non-unitary.
 
  • #60
atyy said:
stevendaryl's post #25 frames and answers this question

No, it doesn't. The last sentence of that post highlights the issue: standard QM does not specify where the information has gone. But that doesn't mean the information is lost, or that it's not lost. It just means standard QM can't tell you whether it's lost or not.
 
  • #61
PeterDonis said:
No, it doesn't. The last sentence of that post highlights the issue: standard QM does not specify where the information has gone. But that doesn't mean the information is lost, or that it's not lost. It just means standard QM can't tell you whether it's lost or not.
Is this the same as saying the there is no observable (self-adjoint operator) in standard QM that can be attributed to that which has/has not been lost ?
 
Last edited:
  • #62
PeterDonis said:
If that is the case, then I don't think it's correct to describe the standard QM collapse as non-unitary.

PeterDonis said:
No, it doesn't. The last sentence of that post highlights the issue: standard QM does not specify where the information has gone. But that doesn't mean the information is lost, or that it's not lost. It just means standard QM can't tell you whether it's lost or not.

I understand where you are coming from, and the more general sense of "information" in plain English. However, "information loss" in the black hole information paradox is one of those physics jargon terms that can be misleading for the general public, like "work" in Newtonian Mechanics or "observer" in special relativity.

Th black hole information paradox is that reasonable postulates lead to a loss of unitarity incompatible with standard QM. The most common approaches (AdS/CFT) to solving the paradox have to do with quantum gravity, and nothing to do with the measurement problem, and aim to restore unitarity in the framework of standard QM.
 
  • #63
atyy said:
Standard QM has collapse - see the texts by Dirac, Landau and Lifshitz, Cohen-Tannoudji et al, Weinberg, Sakurai, Griffiths.

For many years THE standard text on QM was Dirac which I have a copy of. It has a few issues but not related to this. What standard QM is can be found on page 45 under the heading of - The General Physical Interpretation. His assumption is given an observable O and a state x the average of making the observation associated with O, E(O) is E(O) = <x|O|x> .

Now I did not go through the whole book to see if he uses the word collapse anywhere, but it is not in his general physical Interpretation. And the above is all you need to solve problems.

It is often thought Dirac was in the Copenhagen School of Neil's Bohr - but in actual fact he wasn't - although its hard to find evidence of it because for him math was the thing - interpretations were not much of an issue - and he was notoriously a man of few words. That said, from what he did write, he had a very subtle view of QM and physics in general - here he is arguing with Heisenberg about one of the tenants of Copenhagen - that the state is a complete description of the system and it has reached it's final form:
http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/1614/1/Open_or_Closed-preprint.pdf
'Dirac criticized the Copenhagen theorists for claiming that quantum theory had attained its final form. In a 1929 letter to Bohr he writes 'I am afraid I do not completely agree with your views. Although I believe that quantum mechanics has its limitations and will ultimately be replaced by something better, . . . I cannot see any reason for thinking that quantum mechanics has already reached the limit of its development. I think it will undergo a number of small changes.'

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #64
bhobba said:
For many years THE standard text on QM was Dirac which I have a copy of. It has a few issues but not related to this. What standard QM is can be found on page 45 under the heading of - The General Physical Interpretation. His assumption is given an observable O and a state x the average of making the observation associated with O, E(O) is E(O) = <x|O|x> .

Now I did not go through the whole book to see if he uses the word collapse anywhere, but it is not in his general physical Interpretation. And the above is all you need to solve problems.

It is often thought Dirac was in the Copenhagen School of Neil's Bohr - but in actual fact he wasn't - although its hard to find evidence of it because for him math was the thing - interpretations were not much of an issue - and he was notoriously a man of few words. That said, from what he did write, he had a very subtle view of QM and physics in general - here he is arguing with Heisenberg about one of the tenants of Copenhagen - that the state is a complete description of the system and it has reached it's final form:
http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/1614/1/Open_or_Closed-preprint.pdf
'Dirac criticized the Copenhagen theorists for claiming that quantum theory had attained its final form. In a 1929 letter to Bohr he writes 'I am afraid I do not completely agree with your views. Although I believe that quantum mechanics has its limitations and will ultimately be replaced by something better, . . . I cannot see any reason for thinking that quantum mechanics has already reached the limit of its development. I think it will undergo a number of small changes.'

Thanks
Bill

Dirac has collapse.
 
  • #65
atyy said:
Dirac has collapse.

I could be wrong - but I could not find it in his text - can you give the page number?

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #66
bhobba said:
I could be wrong - but I could not find it in his text - can you give the page number?

Thanks
Bill

In the 4th edition, it is on p36.
 
  • #67
atyy said:
In the 4th edition, it is on p36.

No - he says - the measurement causes the system to jump to an eigenstate after the measurement. And he also uses the physical continuity argument I have mentioned many times to derive it must jump ie be in that sate immediately AFTER the measurement. Nobody argues it is in the eigenstate immediately after the measurement - its the specific collapse postulate we are talking about. Collapse has a stronger meaning than this - it means unitary evolution is broken and it discontinuously changes the state - see page 330-331 of Schlosshauer's textbook I am always mentioning - Decoherence and the Quantum to Classical Transition. The fact is we do not know if it is discontinuous or not - we only know it is different AFTER the measurement. Whats going on during the measurement is unknown - it is an interpretation to say it's discontinuous.

In fact decoherence suggests it is not discontinuous - but we really do not know. MW would indeed say it is not discontinuous. In collapse theories like GRW is does indeed happen spontaneously and presumably discontinuously.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #68
bhobba said:
No - he says - the measurement causes the system to jump to an eigenstate after the measurement.

Those words are ambiguous---they could be given a "disturbance" interpretation, which doesn't seem like collapse:
  • If you try to measure the energy of a bound electron, the interaction between measuring device and electron will result in the electron being forced into an energy eigenstate.
However, if you have an entangled pair of particles (as with EPR), then measuring a property of one particle can seemingly cause the other particle to collapse into an eigenstate of whatever is being measured. The collapse of the distant particle can't be given a disturbance interpretation (without FTL influences).

So I don't think that Dirac's nuanced distinction between "collapse" and "measurement causing the system to jump to an eigenstate" really helps. If the latter is true, it sure seems to me that the former is, also.
 
  • #69
bhobba said:
No - he says - the measurement causes the system to jump to an eigenstate after the measurement. And he also uses the physical continuity argument I have mentioned many times to derive it must jump ie be in that sate immediately AFTER the measurement. Nobody argues it is in the eigenstate immediately after the measurement - its the specific collapse postulate we are talking about. Collapse has a stronger meaning than this - it means unitary evolution is broken and it discontinuously changes the state - see page 330-331 of Schlosshauer's textbook I am always mentioning - Decoherence and the Quantum to Classical Transition. The fact is we do not know if it is discontinuous or not - we only know it is different AFTER the measurement. Whats going on during the measurement is unknown - it is an interpretation to say it's discontinuous.

In fact decoherence suggests it is not discontinuous - but we really do not know. MW would indeed say it is not discontinuous. In collapse theories like GRW is does indeed happen spontaneously and presumably discontinuously.

Thanks
Bill

I disagree. Dirac does mean collapse.

As if there were any ambiguity, p108 further shows that this is what he meant.
 
Last edited:
  • #70
stevendaryl said:
Those words are ambiguous---they could be given a "disturbance" interpretation, which doesn't seem like collapse

You are falling for the same trap. What Dirac calls a jump is a simple deduction of the Born Rule. Collapse says more. In EPR we know its a correlation and like any 100% correlation as soon as you know one you know the other. In the classical envelope analogy does the other envelope suddenly collapse - of course not. The only difference in QM is it has different statistical properties - but something may or may not have discontinuously changed - we simply do not know. To be specific entanglement is broken - does that happen instantaneously - its the same as any observation - we do not know.

Thanks
Bill
 
<h2>1. What is wavefunction collapse?</h2><p>Wavefunction collapse is a concept in quantum mechanics where the wave-like behavior of a quantum system collapses into a definite state when it is observed or measured.</p><h2>2. Does information get lost during wavefunction collapse?</h2><p>This is a highly debated topic in the field of quantum mechanics. Some theories suggest that information is lost during wavefunction collapse, while others propose that the information is simply transferred to the observer or the environment.</p><h2>3. How does wavefunction collapse affect the uncertainty principle?</h2><p>The uncertainty principle states that it is impossible to know both the position and momentum of a particle with absolute certainty. Wavefunction collapse plays a role in this principle by determining the probability of a particle's position and momentum when it is observed.</p><h2>4. Can wavefunction collapse be reversed?</h2><p>There is currently no evidence to suggest that wavefunction collapse can be reversed. However, some theories propose that the wavefunction of a collapsed system can be reconstructed using advanced techniques such as quantum entanglement.</p><h2>5. How does wavefunction collapse impact our understanding of reality?</h2><p>Wavefunction collapse challenges our traditional understanding of reality, as it suggests that the act of observation can fundamentally alter the behavior of particles. This has led to various interpretations and debates in the field of quantum mechanics.</p>

1. What is wavefunction collapse?

Wavefunction collapse is a concept in quantum mechanics where the wave-like behavior of a quantum system collapses into a definite state when it is observed or measured.

2. Does information get lost during wavefunction collapse?

This is a highly debated topic in the field of quantum mechanics. Some theories suggest that information is lost during wavefunction collapse, while others propose that the information is simply transferred to the observer or the environment.

3. How does wavefunction collapse affect the uncertainty principle?

The uncertainty principle states that it is impossible to know both the position and momentum of a particle with absolute certainty. Wavefunction collapse plays a role in this principle by determining the probability of a particle's position and momentum when it is observed.

4. Can wavefunction collapse be reversed?

There is currently no evidence to suggest that wavefunction collapse can be reversed. However, some theories propose that the wavefunction of a collapsed system can be reconstructed using advanced techniques such as quantum entanglement.

5. How does wavefunction collapse impact our understanding of reality?

Wavefunction collapse challenges our traditional understanding of reality, as it suggests that the act of observation can fundamentally alter the behavior of particles. This has led to various interpretations and debates in the field of quantum mechanics.

Similar threads

Replies
16
Views
1K
Replies
16
Views
1K
Replies
8
Views
893
Replies
4
Views
954
Replies
15
Views
1K
  • Quantum Interpretations and Foundations
Replies
7
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
13
Views
2K
Replies
12
Views
2K
Replies
10
Views
2K
Replies
7
Views
2K
Back
Top