A-wal said:
Yes, that's what I'm saying.
You said light isn't subject to acceleration due to gravity. The fact that it bends shows that it is. So the fact that it bends does *not* support what you were saying. Do you read what you post?
A-wal said:
Relative to anything, including a hypothetical riverbed made up of hovering observers.
Which then has to cover the entire spacetime in order to support your claims. So for you to be correct, you must *assume* that such a riverbed exists and covers the entire spacetime, which is equivalent to *assuming* that nothing can reach the horizon. So you are assuming what you claim to be proving.
A-wal said:
What would happen if there was a hover just outside the horizon and they accelerated away very sharply when a free-faller was passing them at almost c? Would they then be moving faster than c relative to the free-faller? Of course they wouldn't.
Agreed; they would see the free-faller passing them at a speed a little *closer* to c than if they had just stayed hovering (I assume by "accelerated away very sharply" you mean "accelerated upward even more sharply than they would have to to maintain hovering just outside the horizon").
A-wal said:
The same thing would happen if you calculate a hover even closer to the horizon. You can get as close as you like, just as you can get as close as you want to c. You won't reach it.
With reference to the hoverers, you are correct; they will never see a free-faller passing them at c (or faster). But this does not prove that free-fallers can't pass the horizon; as I noted above, what the hoverers can and can't see is only relevant if the hoverers can cover the entire spacetime, and assuming that is equivalent to *assuming* that free-fallers can't reach the horizon. But you can't *assume* that; you're supposed to be *proving* it.
A-wal said:
You could use the proper time elapsed for the hoverer and match that in flat space-time to get the same answer when they cross.
I'm not sure I understand what you're suggesting here. It sounds like you're changing the conditions of the problem: you want to match the hoverer's/accelerator's proper time elapsed from "start", the time when the hoverer/accelerator and free-faller are mutually at rest, to the time when they cross, but that's not the same as matching the physical *distance* apart they are when they start out mutually at rest, which was the initial condition you specified before. Which is it?
A-wal said:
You were allowed a point-like object. If you work out the velocity at the horizon you'll see that it can't reach c, so it isn't the horizon.
I don't know what you mean by this. What "velocity at the horizon"? The velocity of the free-falling object relative to the outgoing light ray that's just at the horizon. That *is* c.
A-wal said:
The horizon moves back whenever you try to work out anything at the horizon.
I don't know what you mean by this either. The horizon is a fixed null surface in spacetime. It doesn't move.
A-wal said:
It moves back because length contraction and time dilation stop you from reaching it in exactly the same way they stop you from reaching c in flat space-time. You can say there's not enough 'distance shortening' to do that but there must be.
Why "must" there be? Just because you say so? Do you have any actual physical reason? Any actual argument (that doesn't rely on assuming what you're supposed to be proving)?
A-wal said:
I thought that if an object accelerates then it creates a Rindler horizon for an inertial observer because a light ray sent from them won't reach the accelerator until they stop accelerating, which is the equivalent to no object being able to the event horizon until the black hole's gone.
In other words, you still don't understand how a Rindler horizon works, despite claiming (many, many posts ago) that you were quite familiar with it and didn't need to have it explained to you; and you keep on making the same misstatement about it despite repeated corrections on my part.
I'll try once more, starting from scratch and spelling everything out. I'm sure a lot of this will seem "obvious" to you, but after hundreds of posts I can't assume anything about how you understand words relative to how I understand words. So I've got to dot all the i's and cross all the t's.
Consider a flat spacetime and a set of global inertial coordinates x, t on this spacetime (I'm using units in which c = 1, so x and t are in the same units). There are two families of observers in this spacetime. One family is of free-falling observers; each such observer is at rest (in the global inertial coordinate system) at some positive x-coordinate. The second family is of accelerating observers; each such observer starts out, at time t = 0, sitting at rest right next to one of the free-falling observers; but each accelerating observer accelerates with a proper acceleration (i.e., what's measured by his accelerometer) of c^2 / x, where x is the x-coordinate he is at at t = 0. Finally, there is a light ray that is emitted in the positive x-direction from x = 0 at time t = 0 (i.e., from the spacetime origin of the global inertial coordinates).
The following are all true:
(1) The light ray coincides with the Rindler horizon for *all* of the accelerating observers. This means that the light ray will never catch up to any of those observers; all of them will always be ahead of it (as long as they continue to accelerate at the given proper acceleration).
(2) Each of the free-falling observers passes the light ray (and therefore crosses the Rindler horizon) at a positive time t equal to his x-coordinate. Therefore, there are two regions in this spacetime: the region "outside" the horizon, which contains the starting points of all the observers at time t = 0, and the region "inside" the horizon, which is reached only by the free-falling observers, the accelerating observers never reach it (as long as they continue to accelerate). Therefore, the family of accelerating observers does *not* cover the same portion of the spacetime as the family of free-falling observers does; there is a portion (the region "inside" the horizon) that only the free-fallers cover.
(3) Once a free-falling observer crosses the Rindler horizon, there is no way for that observer to send any signal to the region of spacetime on the other side of the horizon (since such a signal would have to travel faster than light). That means no free-falling observer can send a signal to any of the accelerating observers after the free-falling observer has crossed the horizon. Which also means, of course, that no accelerating observer can "see" any free-falling observer after the free-falling observer has crossed the horizon. (All this applies as long as the accelerating observers continue to accelerate.)
(4) As a given free-falling observer passes each member of the family of accelerating observers, the velocity of the free-faller relative to the accelerating observers approaches c. However, it never reaches c, because there is no accelerating observer *at* the horizon; such an observer would have to move at c (since the horizon coincides with the path of a light ray), and no timelike observer can move at c. So no accelerating observer ever sees a freely falling observer pass him at c (or faster). Instead, from the point where each free-falling observer crosses the horizon, he simply stops passing accelerating observers (because there are no more for him to pass) and enters the region of spacetime that the accelerating observers don't cover.
The above is entirely in flat spacetime, it's entirely consistent with SR, and it clearly demonstrates several things: that free-falling observers *can* cross a Rindler horizon, that there *can* be an entire region of spacetime that accelerated observers can't "see" and which they don't cover, and that a free-falling observer not being able to send a light signal that can catch up with an accelerated observer is *not* equivalent to a free-falling observer not being able to cross the horizon.
I can already anticipate how you will reply to this post. You will say, "of course, that's how I've been saying a Rindler horizon works all along", and then proceed to claim that at least one of the three things I've demonstrated, which I listed in the previous paragraph, is false. If that's your inclination on reading the above, please think very carefully before posting a response. Don't even think about how the above translates into the spacetime surrounding a black hole, or what it implies or doesn't imply about a black hole horizon being reachable. Do you honestly believe, looking *just* at the flat spacetime scenario I've just described, as it stands, that anyone of the three things I listed in the previous paragraph is false? Because if so, I'm going to be hard pressed not to conclude that you and I can't have a sane discussion about this. It's one thing to be arguing about GR and how it applies to a black hole horizon. But if we can't even have a common understanding about how a simple scenario in SR works, I'm not sure what we *can* have a common understanding about.