Timelike tangent vectors in Zwiebach

  • Thread starter Thread starter Jimmy Snyder
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Tangent Vectors
Jimmy Snyder
Messages
1,122
Reaction score
22
On page 98 of Zwiebach's book "A First Course in String Theory", the following claim is made:

At each point on the worldsheet of a string there is both a spacelike and a timelike tangent vector.

Professor Zwiebach acknowledges that the statement needs to be softened as follows:

At each point on the worldsheet, except those points associated with the endpoints of an open string, there is both a spacelike and a timelike tangent vector. At the points associated with endpoints, there is both a spacelike and a null tangent vector.

I don't understand the proof that he gives. Can someone provide me with an alternative proof, or a clearer version of his proof? Or is the theorem perhaps untrue? Are there interior points with a null tangent vector, but no timelike tangent vector?
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Isn't this the same question you had on your thread String Question? why did you start a new one? Mentors don't like double posting, you know.
 
selfAdjoint,

Please read my response to your post in the previous thread.
 
Ah, OK. Then let me know if you understand the two paragraphs near the bottom of page 98:
The one beginning "To appreciate the need..."
and the one beginnig "The argument for the string...".

The first of these paragraphs supplies an argument ( a little less that a proof in all rigor, I suppose) for the existence of a timelike vector at each point of the worldline of a particle. The argument is by contradiction; he supposes the opposite of what he wants to prove and shows that leads to "an unphysical situation". This is from the contrapositive mode of logic; if not-A is false then A is true. Are we agreed on that first paragraph and on the way its argument proceeds?
 
jimmysnyder said:
On page 98 of Zwiebach's book "A First Course in String Theory", the following claim is made:

At each point on the worldsheet of a string there is both a spacelike and a timelike tangent vector.

Professor Zwiebach acknowledges that the statement needs to be softened as follows:

At each point on the worldsheet, except those points associated with the endpoints of an open string, there is both a spacelike and a timelike tangent vector. At the points associated with endpoints, there is both a spacelike and a null tangent vector.

I don't understand the proof that he gives. Can someone provide me with an alternative proof, or a clearer version of his proof? Or is the theorem perhaps untrue? Are there interior points with a null tangent vector, but no timelike tangent vector?

Hi Jimmy,

your question forced me to think much more about this whole issue and I think I understand much better what is going on (anyway, that's how I am feeling right now at midnight, after having been at school for the last 17 hours so my judgment might not be top notch :approve: )


I really think now that we must think of a massive string, so no actual piece of the string may move at c. All pieces *must* move at a speed below c. It is still true that we can not follow individual little sections of the string, but I think that for now we can imagine that we could, and then the statement is that no piece would move above or even at c. Then it's clear that at each point of the worldsheet there is a timelike tangent vector. Because (again, imagining for now that we could follow a small piece), there must be some frame in which this small piece is at rest.

Now the interesting thing is the end points. What I failed to fully appreciate before is that the endpoints are NOT physical pieces of the string. They are just the locations of the extremities of the string. If we would be considering actual real life strings, the end points would be the extremities of the last atoms in the string. So even though the end points move at c, there is no actual matter moving at c. What is really amazing of course is the fact that the endpoints must move at c, It is really a fascinating result. But, again, all the actual pieces of "stuff" making up the string are moving more slowly than c. This implies that the string cannot be in translation (the endpoints would move at c and the main body of the string would move more slowly, so the string would get longer and longer!). A possible motion would be for the string to be spinning (let's say around its midpoint). Then the endpoints can move at c while all the pieces move more slowly than c.

Do you see what I mean? Thus point of view makes the discussion of Zwiebach more natural because he compares the string to a point particle which is massive. And indeed, the body of the string always moves below c, like the point particle. The truly fascinating result is that the end points of the free string *must* move at c! I can follow the maths leading to this but it is a bit counterintuitive. I don't see any clear *physical* argument!


Regards

Pat
 
selfAdjoint said:
Are we agreed on that first paragraph and on the way its argument proceeds?

Yes. Of the two paragraphs you mention, the first is no problem for me, and the second one is the one for which I would appreciate any insight. Thank you for picking up this thread.
 
OK. My thinking is that the first two sentences of the second paragraph, about the radical nondecomposability of the string, should be treated as a side issue and not hold us up, since he says "as we shall make abundantly clear later on".

Then the contrapositive argument on the worldsheet (with an exception for the end points of the open string) just parallels that of the first paragraph, on the worldline of a particle. Do you have any particular objection to this argument? Do you think it is just hand-waving? If so why wasn't the particle argument also hand-waving?
 
selfAdjoint said:
OK. My thinking is that the first two sentences of the second paragraph, about the radical nondecomposability of the string, should be treated as a side issue and not hold us up, since he says "as we shall make abundantly clear later on".

Then the contrapositive argument on the worldsheet (with an exception for the end points of the open string) just parallels that of the first paragraph, on the worldline of a particle. Do you have any particular objection to this argument? Do you think it is just hand-waving? If so why wasn't the particle argument also hand-waving?

The obvious question is why an exception for the end points? What is the argument that says that we must make those points an exception? From the way I see it, this is the crux of the issue. (I already wrote in a previous post how I no wunderstand it, but I might be wrong).

Pat
 
Pat, I want to put off these general questions until we get resolution on whether Zwiebach's contrapositive argument about all possible Lorentz observers is both valid and strong enough to convince us.
 
  • #10
selfAdjoint said:
OK. My thinking is that the first two sentences of the second paragraph, about the radical nondecomposability of the string, should be treated as a side issue and not hold us up, since he says "as we shall make abundantly clear later on".

Agreed

selfAdjoint said:
Then the contrapositive argument on the worldsheet (with an exception for the end points of the open string) just parallels that of the first paragraph, on the worldline of a particle.

I'm not sure if I can agree with you on this. However, you do provide much food for thought.

We are trying to prove that "at each point on the worldsheet there is a timelike tangent vector". To assert the contrapositive he should have "Suppose there is a point on the worldsheet where there is no timelike tangent vector". I do not see an equivalent to this statement in his proof.

By analyzing the next few sentences in the manner you suggest, I see that we could break up his proof into three pieces like this:

Lemma 1: Among the points along a closed string, there is at least one point for which there is a timelike tangent vector to the worldsheet.

Lemma 2: Among the points along a piece of a closed string, there is at least one point for which there is a timelike tangent vector to the worldsheet.

Theorem: For each point along a closed string, there is a timelike tangent vector to the worldsheet. The statement of this last corollary is missing from the text, but should be placed just before the sentence which begins "Since the endpoints of the rest of the string ..."

Or so it seems to me. Is this the structure of the proof?
 
  • #11
nrqed said:
The obvious question is why an exception for the end points? What is the argument that says that we must make those points an exception? From the way I see it, this is the crux of the issue. (I already wrote in a previous post how I no wunderstand it, but I might be wrong).

You are right, this is the crux of the issue. selfAdjoint is generously applying himself to this problem and we should give him some leeway here. However, eventually we will have to revisit this question.

Here is where it stands for me.

1. I don't understand the proof. selfAdjoint is addessing this issue and I am pleased with the results so far.

2. I don't trust that the proof is correct. You have stated the reason why. We will tackle this issue once the first one is done. However, it may be that if I understood the proof, I would see why this was not an issue.

3. I don't believe the theorem. I wonder if the statement is not a consequence of first principles, but rather is itself a first principle. In other words, instead of a theorem with proof, it should be replaced with the words:

For the remainder of this book, we will assume that at each point on the worldsheet, there is a timelike tangent vector.

Again, if I understood, and trusted the proof, then my third concern would melt away.
 
  • #12
Is the reason you don't understand the proof the question of the endpoints? If that is so then let's discuss the endpoints. All the physics of the string is done with the worldsheet, which is treated as a two dimensional manifold, a curved surface. But in the case of the open string it's a manifold with boundary, because the world lines of the endpoints form edges of the worldsheet. Thus these worldlines are distinguished on the world sheet. While the timelike and spacelike vectors on the interior of the worldsheet have to be established, the edges are just there, independent of any coordinate system or anything. The geometry you establish on the worldsheet has exceptions for the edges, you have to do a little extra dido there; this isn't a shortcoming or a problem, it's just a geometrical fact, which the math is well able to deal with. In fact in Polchinski's book it's one of the first excercises.

I do suggest we pretend we are working with a closed string, so the endpoint issue doesn't come up, and see how the rest of the proof goes there.
 
Last edited:
  • #13
jimmysnyder said:
You are right, this is the crux of the issue. selfAdjoint is generously applying himself to this problem and we should give him some leeway here. However, eventually we will have to revisit this question.

Here is where it stands for me.

1. I don't understand the proof. selfAdjoint is addessing this issue and I am pleased with the results so far.

2. I don't trust that the proof is correct. You have stated the reason why. We will tackle this issue once the first one is done. However, it may be that if I understood the proof, I would see why this was not an issue.

3. I don't believe the theorem. I wonder if the statement is not a consequence of first principles, but rather is itself a first principle. In other words, instead of a theorem with proof, it should be replaced with the words:

For the remainder of this book, we will assume that at each point on the worldsheet, there is a timelike tangent vector.

Again, if I understood, and trusted the proof, then my third concern would melt away.


Hi Jimmy,

I don't know if you have read my post from yesterday night but I have adopted a point of view which makes, in my personal opinion, the presentation of Zwiebach completely satisfactory (to my taste, at least). SO I am quite happy with the situation, now. I'll paste part of that previous post I had below. It might be that it's not a satisfactory point of view for you in which case I sure would benefit from your criticisms. In any case, I appreciate your posts because it forced me to think about the whole issue and not to let myself set it aside as I did on my first reading. And I now feel I understand much better that aspect of string behavior.

Anyway, here's part of what I wrote yesterday:

nrqed said:
I really think now that we must think of a massive string, so no actual piece of the string may move at c. All pieces *must* move at a speed below c. It is still true that we can not follow individual little sections of the string, but I think that for now we can imagine that we could, and then the statement is that no piece would move above or even at c. Then it's clear that at each point of the worldsheet there is a timelike tangent vector. Because (again, imagining for now that we could follow a small piece), there must be some frame in which this small piece is at rest.

Now the interesting thing is the end points. What I failed to fully appreciate before is that the endpoints are NOT physical pieces of the string. They are just the locations of the extremities of the string. If we would be considering actual real life strings, the end points would be the extremities of the last atoms in the string. So even though the end points move at c, there is no actual matter moving at c. What is really amazing of course is the fact that the endpoints must move at c, It is really a fascinating result.


Pat
 
  • #14
selfAdjoint said:
Is the reason you don't understand the proof the question of the endpoints?

No, not at all. It is because of the question of the endpoints that I don't trust the proof. Here is the issue: The statement of the theorem doesn't mention endpoints and the proof itself doesn't mention endpoints. Why then doesn't the theorem apply to endpoints? But please, let us leave that question till later.

The reason I don't understand the proof is that I can't follow it. To my feeble lights, it seems to have missing steps. What I am looking for is for someone to either provide the missing steps, or perhaps to provide a completely different proof. For instance, is there a different proof in Polchinsky?

selfAdjoint said:
I do suggest we pretend we are working with a closed string, so the endpoint issue doesn't come up, and see how the rest of the proof goes there.

Yes, by all means.
 
  • #15
Great, so we pick up Zwiebach's argument in the third sentence of that second paragraph: (my comments are in red)

"For a closed string world-sheet, for example, consider first the possibility that that all along the string (all around the closed loop, that is) there is no timelike tanget vector to the world sheet. (Here he is assuming the contradiction of what he wants to prove, and his proof will be to show that contradictory assumption is false, or in physical terms "unphysical").

Then he just asserts the contradiction:

That means we could display all possible Lorentz observers at all points on the string and no observer could make any point of the string appear to be at rest. (Because if one observer saw one point at rest then that rest frame, be definition would have a timelike vector at that point)

And extends it:

A similar unphysical result would occur if any piece of the (closed) string failed to have timelike tangent vectors on the world-sheet. (This is the real contradiction, and the next sentence is the proof of it. A piece is a length of string from one interior point to another one.)

Since the endpoints of the rest of the string can not close up the string instantaneously, a piece of the string would have failed to move physically.

(Note that if a piece moves, time must pass, and that piece must have a timelike tangent somewhere along it. The only way to move without time passing is to have a null tangent vector, i,e, to move at the speed of light. But the interior of the string doesn't do that. Failing that, the only alternative is for the piece of the string to disappear, but without time passing (timelike tangent), that would have to happen instantaneously, and for points (the end points of the PIECE; interior points of the STRING) to move a finite distance (length of the piece) in no time is unphysical again. So the whole idea is unphysical, so the assumption is false, and there does exist a timelike tangent somewhere along the piece. Now go to many increasingly small pieces and you eventually get timelike tangents at a dense set of points on the string, and using continuity claim that every point on a closed string has one.)
 
Last edited:
  • #16
nrqed said:
Because (again, imagining for now that we could follow a small piece), there must be some frame in which this small piece is at rest.

Hi Pat,

I did read your post, and I had intended to respond to it, but just completely forgot to do so. I appreciate your input at least as much as you appreciate mine. I feel very strongly that if we all pull together, we can lick this thing.

Consider a string that is circular, not vibrating, and at rest wrt an inertial observer. The world sheet is a right cylinder. Quite obviously, there are timelike tangent vectors everywhere. Now 'paint' a point of the string as you suggested, and (momentarily suspending physical reality) follow the worldpath of the point. If the the string is stationary in the sense that the point is also at rest wrt to the observer, the worldpath is a straight line parallel to the axis of the cylinder. If the string is rotating in the sense that the point is moving in a circular path coincident with the string, then the world path is a spiral winding around the cylinder. Note that in either case, the world sheet is the same. In other words, the world path of the point has no effect on the shape of the worldsheet and therefore no effect on the question of whether there are timelike tangent vectors. This is true even if the string is rotating in such a way that our painted point is traveling at or even greater than c. The issue is the shape of the world sheet, not the path of any point. I expect the proof to rely on the geometry and perhaps the topology of the worldsheet. Indeed, I think there is some topology in Zwiebach's proof since he mentions not being able to patch up some gap.

All this is to say that I don't like to think of being able to follow any part of the string.

nrqed said:
If we would be considering actual real life strings, the end points would be the extremities of the last atoms in the string.

There is a very important difference between the endpoints of a string theory string, and the endpoints of a macroscopic string. If you cut off the endpoints of a macroscopic string, it still has endpoints, albeit different ones. But if you cut off the endpoints of a string theory string, it becomes a string with no endpoints. That is why I was so interested in selfAdjoint's suggestion that the endpoints are constituents of the string. You could actually cut them off and consider them as separate entities. Then the world would be made of strings and endpoints. Obviously, a statement like that must give us pause. Everything is supposed to be made of strings. I don't know how to resolve this issue. If a string has no endpoints, then it has nothing to attach it to branes. There is no point to apply Dirichlet or Neuman boundary conditions. Perhaps the answer is that you cannot cut off the endpoints. But then your objection comes to the fore. If the string is traveling in a straight line, and the endpoints are traveling at c and the interior points are traveling at less than c, then the string must get stretched in a bizarre way.

Too cloudy here to see the eclipsed moon. Second time in a row. Disappointment abounds.
 
  • #17
selfAdjoint, your last post doesn't display on my screen, can you repost please.
 
  • #18
I had my comments in red. They display on my sceen (IE), but here, I'll change them to italics.

----------------------------------------------------------------------
Great, so we pick up Zwiebach's argument in the third sentence of that second paragraph: (my comments are in italics)

"For a closed string world-sheet, for example, consider first the possibility that that all along the string (all around the closed loop, that is) there is no timelike tanget vector to the world sheet. (Here he is assuming the contradiction of what he wants to prove, and his proof will be to show that contradictory assumption is false, or in physical terms "unphysical").

Then he just asserts the contradiction:

That means we could display all possible Lorentz observers at all points on the string and no observer could make any point of the string appear to be at rest. (Because if one observer saw one point at rest then that rest frame, be definition would have a timelike vector at that point)

And extends it:

A similar unphysical result would occur if any piece of the (closed) string failed to have timelike tangent vectors on the world-sheet. (This is the real contradiction, and the next sentence is the proof of it. A piece is a length of string from one interior point to another one.)

Since the endpoints of the rest of the string can not close up the string instantaneously, a piece of the string would have failed to move physically.

(Note that if a piece moves, time must pass, and that piece must have a timelike tangent somewhere along it. The only way to move without time passing is to have a null tangent vector, i,e, to move at the speed of light. But the interior of the string doesn't do that. Failing that, the only alternative is for the piece of the string to disappear, but without time passing (timelike tangent), that would have to happen instantaneously, and for points (the end points of the PIECE; interior points of the STRING) to move a finite distance (length of the piece) in no time is unphysical again. So the whole idea is unphysical, so the assumption is false, and there does exist a timelike tangent somewhere along the piece. Now go to many increasingly small pieces and you eventually get timelike tangents at a dense set of points on the string, and using continuity claim that every point on a closed string has one.)

--------------------------------------------------------------------------------
 
  • #19
jimmysnyder said:
Hi Pat,

I did read your post, and I had intended to respond to it, but just completely forgot to do so. I appreciate your input at least as much as you appreciate mine. I feel very strongly that if we all pull together, we can lick this thing.

Consider a string that is circular, not vibrating, and at rest wrt an inertial observer. The world sheet is a right cylinder. Quite obviously, there are timelike tangent vectors everywhere. Now 'paint' a point of the string as you suggested, and (momentarily suspending physical reality) follow the worldpath of the point. If the the string is stationary in the sense that the point is also at rest wrt to the observer, the worldpath is a straight line parallel to the axis of the cylinder. If the string is rotating in the sense that the point is moving in a circular path coincident with the string, then the world path is a spiral winding around the cylinder. Note that in either case, the world sheet is the same. In other words, the world path of the point has no effect on the shape of the worldsheet and therefore no effect on the question of whether there are timelike tangent vectors. This is true even if the string is rotating in such a way that our painted point is traveling at or even greater than c. The issue is the shape of the world sheet, not the path of any point. I expect the proof to rely on the geometry and perhaps the topology of the worldsheet. Indeed, I think there is some topology in Zwiebach's proof since he mentions not being able to patch up some gap.


Hi Jimmy,

Thanks for your reply and very interesting comments. I agree with all that you are saying. Indeedd, I can't really follow any of the individual pieces of the string because there is no way to identify them, as you point out. And indeed, if a closed string is at rest completely or spinning around the center of its axis can't be distinguished.

But it's possible to define a velocity by using the method described by Zwiebach on page 109. I quote :

"consider a string at some fixed time and pick a point p on it. Draw the hyperplane orthogonal to the string at p. An infinitesimal instant later the string has moved, but it will still intersect the plane, this time at a point p'. The transverse velocity is what we get if we presume that the point p moved to p'. No string parameterization is needed to define this velocity"


Then my statement is that I think that the key point is that this velocity is taken to be smaller than c, for any point on the string. Given that, the rest of the discussion by Zwiebach on p. 98 makes sense.




There is a very important difference between the endpoints of a string theory string, and the endpoints of a macroscopic string. If you cut off the endpoints of a macroscopic string, it still has endpoints, albeit different ones. But if you cut off the endpoints of a string theory string, it becomes a string with no endpoints.That is why I was so interested in selfAdjoint's suggestion that the endpoints are constituents of the string. You could actually cut them off and consider them as separate entities. Then the world would be made of strings and endpoints. Obviously, a statement like that must give us pause. Everything is supposed to be made of strings. I don't know how to resolve this issue. If a string has no endpoints, then it has nothing to attach it to branes. There is no point to apply Dirichlet or Neuman boundary conditions. Perhaps the answer is that you cannot cut off the endpoints.

I have to say that I totally disagree with this. Of course I could be wrong, but I just can't make sense of it. The endpoints are just defined at the points where the string ends. Even if the string is a fundamental string, it does not change the meaning of what an endpoint is. If you cut an open string in two, you end up with two open strings having each two end points. If you "cut an endpoint" of an open string, you are cutting a small piece of the string and are creating two open strings (however short one may be compared to the other).

I really think that endpoints here are just the usual concepts of endpoints!

The subtle point of treating a fundamental string, as opposed to a real life macroscopic string, is the point you raised about not being able to follow individual pieces of the string in their motion. Then it becomes impossible to really say if they are moving above or below c, or at c. Then it makes the entire analogy with a point particle quite tricky.

My contention is that the equivalent of saying that the point particle moves below c is equivalent to saying thatnone of the transverse velocities at any point along the string (as defined above) moves above or even at c. Then the rest would follow. However, I agree that this is not the way Zwiebach presents things, so I don't know if I am correct. MAybe he wanted to discussed the presence of timelike tangent vectors before getting into the exact definition of transverse velocities and he therefore had to cheat a little bit.

But again, maybe I am totally wrong. To be honest then, if we don't impose the transverse velocities to be below c and since we can't follow any individual piece of the string, I would not see anyway to make any statement about timelike vs null vs spacelike tangent vectors! But given the result (which I trust is correct), then the only explanation thatmakes sense to me is the one I just presented.



But then your objection comes to the fore. If the string is traveling in a straight line, and the endpoints are traveling at c and the interior points are traveling at less than c, then the string must get stretched in a bizarre way.

Right. So if I am right, then the string *must* be spinning. That way it's always possible to have the endpoints moving at c while all the transverse velocities remaining below c. That's quite an intriguing conclusion! It seems to me that this should be mentioned somewhere, but I have never seen (or recall seeing) anywhere the mention that the classical string must be spinning!

Too cloudy here to see the eclipsed moon. Second time in a row. Disappointment abounds.

Too bad. It was quite clear here. Got quite reddish. It's easy to imagine how it must have provoked awe for ancient civilizations.


Pat
 
  • #20
selfAdjoint said:
Snip...

(Note that if a piece moves, time must pass, and that piece must have a timelike tangent somewhere along it. The only way to move without time passing is to have a null tangent vector, i,e, to move at the speed of light. But the interior of the string doesn't do that...


But that's the crux of the matter. How do we know that the interior of the string can't do that? That's the key assumption. And that was my starting point in a much earlier post in this thread.

But *even* if we accept this statement, it is still unclear what one means by "the interior can't move at the speed of light" since we can't follow an individual piece of the string. The only possible answer I came up with was to work in terms of transverse velocities, as defined on page 109. See my earlier post today for my discussion on this.

regards

Pat
 
  • #21
selfAdjoint said:
I had my comments in red. They display on my sceen (IE), but here, I'll change them to italics.

Hi selfAdjoint. When I was at home, I could not read your post because of the red. Now I am at work and I can read both the red text and the italics. This is no guarantee that I will be able to read the italics when I get home. No matter. I now realize that if wanted to read your post last night, all I needed to do was reply to it. Then it would be displayed with tags instead of rendering.

Zwiebach said:
For a closed string world-sheet, for example, consider first the possibility that that all along the string there is no timelike tangent vector to the world sheet.
selfAdjoint said:
Here he is assuming the contradiction of what he wants to prove.

No, not so. What he wants to prove is:
At each point on the worldsheet there is a timelike tangent vector.
And the contrapositive is:
There is a point on the worldsheet where there is no timelike tangent vector.

Zwiebach said:
A similar unphysical result would occur if any piece of the string failed to have timelike tangent vectors on the world-sheet.

This is still not the contrapositive.

selfAdjoint said:
The only way to move without time passing is to have a null tangent vector, i,e, to move at the speed of light. But the interior of the string doesn't do that.

I agree with Pat on this. You are assuming that which you are trying to prove.

Unfortunately, the rest of your paragraph is even less comprehensible to me than Zwiebach's. I take the blame for this myself. But at the same time I ask if you can find ways to simplify it. After all, I have agreed to put aside the issue of whether I think the proof is correct. I just want to understand what he is saying.
 
  • #22
selfAdjoint said:
you eventually get timelike tangents at a dense set of points on the string, and using continuity claim that every point on a closed string has one.

No, timelike vectors could converge to a null vector.

BUT!

Thanks to you selfAdjoint, and to you Pat, I think understand Zwiebach's proof now. I still fear that his proof may be incorrect because I don't know how to rule out the possibility that at some point on the world sheet there are only spacelike and null tangent vectors. I will post what I figured out when I get the time, tonight or tomorrow night. Meanwhile, I will give you the pieces and perhaps you can beat me to the punch.

From selfAdjoint - continuity, not of the timelike vectors, but of the spacelike ones.
From Pat - p can be associated with p'
From Professor Zwiebach - that word 'seems' in his proof.
From myself - My quasi-stationary circular string.
 
  • #23
jimmysnyder said:
No, not so. What he wants to prove is:
At each point on the worldsheet there is a timelike tangent vector.
And the contrapositive is:
There is a point on the worldsheet where there is no timelike tangent vector.

And it's exactly that contrapositive that he addressed first and that I discussed. "Assume there is a point". Then to get a better argument for the string circumstances he changed to "assume there is a segment which contains a point in its interior". That way he can't run into the endpoints of an open string. I agree that his development is a little loose here, but he is specifically trying to avoid the definition-theorem-proof kind of writing that puts students into a doze.
 
  • #24
Sorry guys, I still am too pressed for time to give the complete proof. What is more, I am suffering from a rather bad headache. However, the main thrust of his proof is that if there were a point on the worldsheet for which there were no timelike tangent vector, then two things:

1. The closed string would become an open string.

2. There would be an inertial frame from which this phenomonon could be seen.

The early part of the proof is about finding that inertial frame. The later part is about the changed condition of the string.
 
  • #25
Hi,

I'm sorry I haven't posted in such a long time. I fell ill and haven't been up to it till now. When I posted that I understood Professor Zwiebach's proof, I didn't have it in front of me. What I thought I saw was this:

I saw that if there were a point on the world sheet for which there were no timelike tangent vector and no null tangent vector, then there must be an interval of such points. I still feel that this is so. I came to realize it thanks to selfAdjoint's comment about the density of points with timelike tangent vectors. Such an interval would form a gap in the string, but how could we be sure that there would be any inertial observer capable of seeing it. I thought I saw the answer in the first part of the proof. I thought the author meant that on the string, near the endpoints of the gap, there were timelike tangent vectors, and therefore, a place for an inertial observer to stand and see the gap.

Perhaps there is a proof like that, but I am now convinced that this is not what the author meant.

Consider the following: What if there were timelike tangent vectors at every point on the worldsheet except for one. And suppose that at that point there were a null tangent vector. In that case, wouldn't the proof in the book break down?

Pat, you brought up a very good point about what the author says on page 109 and it gave me a good insight into what the author means when he says that a point 'seems' to be at rest. I will post on this issue later.
 
Back
Top