pob1212
- 21
- 0
Hi
I'm trying to determine the significance of a compact subset of a metric space in relation to calculus in general.
I know the definition: A subset \small K of a metric space \small X is said to be compact if every open cover of \small K contains a finite subcover.
But what is the importance of every open cover containing a finite subcover? For example suppose I have a subset \small E of a metrics space \small X, which is open relative to \small X. I assign to each p \in E a positive number r_{p} such that the conditions d(p,q) < r_{p}, q \in X imply q \in E. This is an open cover of \small E, which does not have a finite subcover which contains \small E, correct? If this is true, then I'm thinking this must be why no open set in \small X can be compact, because we can find an open cover with no finite subcover. (the one above)
Additionally, can't we obtain an open cover of this same \small E with a finite subcover if we simply pick neighborhoods of a finite set of points in \small E with radius large enough that \small E is contained in the union of these neighborhoods? Hence the importance of every, as noted before
If this is all true, then my point is I don't see the 'big picture' importance of these observations as they relate to the development of calculus? What are the implications?
Furthermore, I know things such as every sequence in a compact metric space \small X has a subsequence which converges to a point in \small X, and the theorems about all Cauchy sequences converging if in a compact metric space.
I'm struggling to tie things together...
As always, thanks
pob
I'm trying to determine the significance of a compact subset of a metric space in relation to calculus in general.
I know the definition: A subset \small K of a metric space \small X is said to be compact if every open cover of \small K contains a finite subcover.
But what is the importance of every open cover containing a finite subcover? For example suppose I have a subset \small E of a metrics space \small X, which is open relative to \small X. I assign to each p \in E a positive number r_{p} such that the conditions d(p,q) < r_{p}, q \in X imply q \in E. This is an open cover of \small E, which does not have a finite subcover which contains \small E, correct? If this is true, then I'm thinking this must be why no open set in \small X can be compact, because we can find an open cover with no finite subcover. (the one above)
Additionally, can't we obtain an open cover of this same \small E with a finite subcover if we simply pick neighborhoods of a finite set of points in \small E with radius large enough that \small E is contained in the union of these neighborhoods? Hence the importance of every, as noted before
If this is all true, then my point is I don't see the 'big picture' importance of these observations as they relate to the development of calculus? What are the implications?
Furthermore, I know things such as every sequence in a compact metric space \small X has a subsequence which converges to a point in \small X, and the theorems about all Cauchy sequences converging if in a compact metric space.
I'm struggling to tie things together...
As always, thanks
pob