What are the Different Formulations of Quantum Mechanics?

In summary, in classical mechanics you construct an action, then extremizing it gives the equations of motion. Alternatively, one can find a first order PDE for the action as a function of it's endpoints to obtain the Hamilton-Jacobi equation, and the Poisson bracket formulation is merely a means of changing variables in your PDE so as to ensure your new variables are still characteristics of the H-J PDE. All that makes sense to me.
  • #1
bolbteppa
309
41
In classical mechanics you construct an action (involving a Lagrangian in arbitrary generalized coordinates, a Hamiltonian in canonical coordinates [to make your EOM more "convenient & symmetric"]), then extremizing it gives the equations of motion. Alternatively one can find a first order PDE for the action as a function of it's endpoints to obtain the Hamilton-Jacobi equation, & the Poisson bracket formulation is merely a means of changing variables in your PDE so as to ensure your new variables are still characteristics of the H-J PDE (i.e. solutions of the EOM - see No. 37). All that makes sense to me, we're extremizing a functional to get the EOM or solving a PDE which implicitly assumes we've already got the solution (path of the particle) inside of the action that leads to the PDE. However in quantum mechanics, at least in the canonical quantization I think, you apparently just take the Hamiltonian (the Lagrangian in canonical coordinates) & mish-mash this with ideas from changing variables in the Hamilton-Jacobi equation representation of your problem so that you ensure the coordinates are characteristics of your Hamilton-Jacobi equation (i.e. the solutions of the EOM), then you put these ideas in some new space for some reason (Hilbert space) & have a theory of QM. Based on what I've written you are literally doing the exact same thing you do in classical mechanics in the beginning, you're sneaking in classical ideas & for some reason you make things into an algebra - I don't see why this is necessary, or why you can't do exactly what you do in classical mechanics? Furthermore I think my questions have some merit when you note that Schrodinger's original derivation involved an action functional using the Hamilton-Jacobi equation. Again we see Schrodinger doing a similar thing to the modern idea's, here he's mish-mashing the Hamilton-Jacobi equation with extremizing an action functional instead of just extremizing the original Lagrangian or Hamiltonian, analogous to modern QM mish-mashing the Hamiltonian with changes of variables in the H-J PDE (via Poisson brackets).

What's going on in this big Jigsaw? Why do we need to start mixing up all our pieces, why can't we just copy classical mechanics exactly - we are on some level anyway, as far as I can see... I can understand doing these things if they are just convenient tricks, the way you could say that invoking the H-J PDE is just a trick for dealing with Lagrangians & Hamiltonians, but I'm pretty sure the claim is that the process of quantization simply must be done, one step is just absolutely necessary, you simply cannot follow the classical ideas, even though from what I've said we basically are just doing the classical thing - in a roundabout way. It probably has something to do with complex numbers, at least partially, as mentioned in the note on page 276 here, but I have no idea as to how to see that & Schrodinger's original derivation didn't assume them so I'm confused about this, thanks!

To make my questions about quantization explicit if they aren't apparent from what I've written above:

a) Why does one need to make an algebra out of mixing the Hamiltonian with Poisson brackets?

(Where this question stresses the interpretation of Hamiltonian's as Lagrangian's just with different coordinates, & Poisson brackets as conditions on changing variables in the Hamilton-Jacobi equation, so that we make the relationship to CM explicit)

b) Why can't quantum mechanics just be modeled by extremizing a Lagrangian, or solving a H-J PDE?

(From my explanation above it seems quantization smuggles these ideas into it's formalism anyway, just mish-mashing them together in some vector space)

c) How do complex numbers relate to this process?

(Are they the reason quantum mechanics radically differs from classical mechanics. If so, how does this fall out of the procedure as inevitable?)

Apologies if these weren't clear from what I've written, but I feel what I've written is absolutely essential to my question, thank you.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Quantization basically means constructing a quantum theory corresponding to some theory that has your theory as it's classical limit.

In principle, there are no rules on how to do this. In practice however, several methods have emerged (like canonical quantization or path-integral quantization). There is no deep reason why these methods work. They are just heuristics. If they don't work, you just discard the theory and try to construct another one.

Unfortunately, nobody in the world knows how to find the right theory. You just have the guiding principle that your quantum theory must have the right classical limit (see correspondence principle). In the end, you always need to compare the predictions with experimental data.
 
  • #3
In other words there very well may be an answer to my question, which is a research question... ?
 
  • #4
I'm not sure what your question is exactly.

The most general answer to the question "What is quantization?" is given by the first line of my previous answer in my opinion. Quantization isn't a well-defined procedure that one can follow in order to get the correct theory. It's more like witchcraft. That doesn't mean that there are no well-defined procedures to quantize a theory. It's just not guaranteed that they yield quantum theories that describe physics correctly.

If your question is "Why can't we use the same methods in quantum theory that we use in classical mechanics?", then the answer is that classical mechanics and quantum mechanics are formulated within very different frameworks. Whereas classical systems are described by differential equations, quantum theories always involve Hilbert spaces and operators.

There is no reason to believe that there is a well-defined procedure to quantize a theory that automatically yields the correct predictions. That would mean that you can construct the general theory already, just from knowing it's behavior in a special case. It might be this way, but it's highly unlikely in my opinion.
 
  • #5
Quantum mechanics is fundamentally formulated as a Hamiltonian theory, and is defined via commutation relations and the Hilbert space.

There is a "Lagrangian" version which is not as fundamental, but is calculationally more powerful in many cases. This is Feynman's path integral. The "saddle point approximation" to the path integral recovers the classical "extremize the action" principle. Then deviations from classical mechanics can be thought of as corrections to the saddle point approximation. Because the Hamiltonian version is more fundamental, conditions on the Lagrangian must be satisfied if the Lagrangian is to correspond to a quantum theory - for relativistic quantum field theories, some conditions go by the name of the Osterwalder-Schrader axioms.

http://www.einstein-online.info/spotlights/path_integrals
 
  • #6
I'm really sorry guys, I've made my questions more explicit, adding them to the end of my OP.

rubi said:
If your question is "Why can't we use the same methods in quantum theory that we use in classical mechanics?", then the answer is that classical mechanics and quantum mechanics are formulated within very different frameworks. Whereas classical systems are described by differential equations, quantum theories always involve Hilbert spaces and operators.

Apologies for not being clearer before, my question is partially as to why one needs to invoke Hilbert spaces & operators? Are they a mathematical trick (the way H-J theory is a trick for working with Lagrangians & Hamiltonians)? Why do people claim this approach is absolutely essential & incontravertibly different from classical mechanics when Schrodinger's derivation was completely classical, albeit that the resulting eigenfunctions are complex (why that is I don't yet know).

rubi said:
There is no reason to believe that there is a well-defined procedure to quantize a theory that automatically yields the correct predictions. That would mean that you can construct the general theory already, just from knowing it's behavior in a special case. It might be this way, but it's highly unlikely in my opinion.

I think this is a nice aspect of my question. According to Schrodinger's original derivation of his equation, which is very much in the classical Lagrange-Hamilton-Poisson framework as is very very apparent from the derivation I've linked to above, one can see that you get the Schrodinger equation which yields correct predictions. As far as I can see quantization is some algebraic formalism that results in the same results you get from solving Schrodinger, & my question is merely about the necessity of this, about why people claim this approach is so radically different when one sees it springs naturally from classical mechanics when you consider Schrodinger's derivation I've linked to.

atyy said:
There is a "Lagrangian" version which is not as fundamental, but is calculationally more powerful in many cases. This is Feynman's path integral. The "saddle point approximation" to the path integral recovers the classical "extremize the action" principle. Then deviations from classical mechanics can be thought of as corrections to the saddle point approximation. Because the Hamiltonian version is more fundamental, conditions on the Lagrangian must be satisfied if the Lagrangian is to correspond to a quantum theory - for relativistic quantum field theories, some conditions go by the name of the Osterwalder-Schrader axioms.

http://www.einstein-online.info/spotlights/path_integrals

I don't know much about path integrals & what I do know shows that they involve complex numbers from the get-go. I wonder if you'd know whether one can naturally arrive at the path integral formulation starting from Schrodinger's derivation I've linked to above? I would be really happy if a textbook were to explicitly say that "yes, we involve complex numbers in our path integral because eigenfunctions of Schrodinger's equation show complex numbers to be necessary", as opposed to just postulating that it works or something. I'm not sure what one actually does, but I'd love to do it in a way that follows what I'm talking about in this thread if you know of anything :cool:
 
  • #7
bolbteppa said:
I don't know much about path integrals & what I do know shows that they involve complex numbers from the get-go. I wonder if you'd know whether one can naturally arrive at the path integral formulation starting from Schrodinger's derivation I've linked to above? I would be really happy if a textbook were to explicitly say that "yes, we involve complex numbers in our path integral because eigenfunctions of Schrodinger's equation show complex numbers to be necessary", as opposed to just postulating that it works or something. I'm not sure what one actually does, but I'd love to do it in a way that follows what I'm talking about in this thread if you know of anything :cool:

It's pretty standard to derive the path integral from Schroedinger's equation, try the first or second link below. The tricky thing is how to evaluate it - usually one goes to imaginary time, calculates the integral, then goes back to real time - and figuring out when this is legitimate from the point of view of Hailtonians and Hilbert spaces is part of the Osterwalder-Schrader axioms which are mentioned in the third link. It's best to regard the Hamiltonian version as fundamental, and the path integral as less fundamental tool, but a very powerful one.

http://arxiv.org/abs/quantph/0004090
http://www.blau.itp.unibe.ch/lecturesPI.pdf
http://www.einstein-online.info/spotlights/path_integrals
 
  • #8
Hmmmm.

I don't quite get your issue, but I SUSPECT is how do we form a quantum theory from a classical one.

That actually is a VERY VERY deep issue and to really get to grips with it you need to study the most mathematically developed version of QM we have:
https://www.amazon.com/dp/0387493859/?tag=pfamazon01-20

BEWARE. Such books are euphemistically said to be mathematically non trivial - translation - its bloody hard even for mathematics graduates like myself.

Also I would warm up with chapter 3 of Ballentine - QM - A Modern Development - which gives a similar sort of view but is much more accessible. Still if you are interested in this very deep issue Varadarajan is the book. Good luck - you will need it. Yea I have the book and one day may get around to a full study of it rather than a the cursory reading which is all I have so far done.

One thing I will mention is the need for complex numbers - its got to do with Wigners Theorem:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wigner's_theorem

Unless you go to complex vector spaces it doesn't hold. This means you can't necessary find unitary transformations for symmetries which is the real deep foundation of dynamics in QM. If you do symmetry transformations you want the transformation to leave orthogonal vectors orthogonal and superpositions to still be in superposition ie unitary - there is only one way to guarantee it - Wigners Theorem. But that is only one aspect of the deep study of this stuff - it aren't easy - not easy at all.

Added Later:
Based on what you said in your clarifying post Varadarajan is the book you want.

Also check out the following:
http://arxiv.org/pdf/quant-ph/0101012v4.pdf
http://arxiv.org/pdf/0911.0695v1.pdf

In modern times many people such as myself think of QM as the most reasonable generalized probability model that allows for entanglement. That however doesn't get to the issue of dynamics which seems to be your concern.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #9
bolbteppa said:
a) Why does one need to make an algebra out of mixing the Hamiltonian with Poisson brackets?

(Where this question stresses the interpretation of Hamiltonian's as Lagrangian's just with different coordinates, & Poisson brackets as conditions on changing variables in the Hamilton-Jacobi equation, so that we make the relationship to CM explicit)

(First of all: A Hamiltonian isn't just a Lagrangian with different coordinates. It's more than that.)
As I pointed out above, we want to construct the quantum theory in such a way that it might have the right classical limit. How can we do this? The most obvious way to see this is to compare the classical Hamilton's equations with the quantum Heisenberg equations of motion:

Hamiltons equations of motion in classical mechanics: ##\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} f(t) = \{f,H\}##
Heisenbergs equations of motion in quantum mechanics: ##\mathrm i\hbar\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} \hat f(t) = [\hat f,\hat H]##

Now if you want the expectation values of the quantum dynamics to approach the classical dynamics for sharply peaked states and ##\hbar\rightarrow 0##, you could postulate ##[\widehat A,\widehat B] = \mathrm i\hbar\widehat{\{A,B\}} + O(\hbar^2)##. Then the idea is:
[tex]\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} \left<\hat f(t)\right> = \frac{1}{\mathrm i\hbar}\left<[\hat f,\hat H]\right> = \left<\widehat{\{f,H\}}\right> + \frac{1}{\mathrm i\hbar}\left<O(\hbar^2)\right> \approx \{f,H\} + O(\hbar) \rightarrow \{f,H\}[/tex]
So we can at least hope to get some sort of correct classical limit by transforming the classical Poisson brackets into commutators of observables on the quantum side. For canonical conjugate variables, you even get the Heisenberg uncertainty principle.


b) Why can't quantum mechanics just be modeled by extremizing a Lagrangian, or solving a H-J PDE?

(From my explanation above it seems quantization smuggles these ideas into it's formalism anyway, just mish-mashing them together in some vector space)

Because quantum variables aren't real-valued functions. Instead, they are operators on some Hilbert space without any canonical ordering. You can say ##3 < 5##, but you can't say ##\frac{\partial}{\partial x} < \frac{\partial^2}{\partial x^2}## (this expression just doesn't make any sense). You can't "minimize" anything here.

c) How do complex numbers relate to this process?

(Are they the reason quantum mechanics radically differs from classical mechanics. If so, how does this fall out of the procedure as inevitable?)
Complex numbers aren't the reason why quantum mechanics is so drastically different. In fact, it might be possible to construct some reasonable quantum theories on Hilbert spaces over the real numbers. What makes QM so different from CM is the fact that it's formulated in an entirely different framework. States are (by definition) vectors in some Hilbert space, whereas in CM, they are just a list of real numbers and observables are self-adjoint operators (by definition), whereas in CM, they are just real-valued functions.
 
  • #10
bolbteppa said:
Apologies for not being clearer before, my question is partially as to why one needs to invoke Hilbert spaces & operators? Are they a mathematical trick (the way H-J theory is a trick for working with Lagrangians & Hamiltonians)? Why do people claim this approach is absolutely essential & incontravertibly different from classical mechanics when Schrodinger's derivation was completely classical, albeit that the resulting eigenfunctions are complex (why that is I don't yet know).
Hilbert spaces and operators are the way quantum theory is defined. If you don't have a Hilbert space, you are not doing quantum theory, but rather something else. Also nobody says that quantum theory is inevitable. It's just that our best theories are quantum theories, so at the moment, there is no reason to abandon it.

By the way: You don't derive Schrödingers equation. You can motivate it, but in the end, it's an axiom.

I think this is a nice aspect of my question. According to Schrodinger's original derivation of his equation, which is very much in the classical Lagrange-Hamilton-Poisson framework as is very very apparent from the derivation I've linked to above, one can see that you get the Schrodinger equation which yields correct predictions. As far as I can see quantization is some algebraic formalism that results in the same results you get from solving Schrodinger, & my question is merely about the necessity of this, about why people claim this approach is so radically different when one sees it springs naturally from classical mechanics when you consider Schrodinger's derivation I've linked to.

You can't derive quantum theories. What you actually do is to use as much physical input as you have available and then try to find a theory that is consistent with it. Schrödinger's derivation isn't water-proof either. It involves a large amount of heuristics.
 
  • #11
rubi said:
By the way: You don't derive Schrödingers equation. You can motivate it, but in the end, it's an axiom.

Sorry mate - you can derive it eg see Chapter 3 of Ballentine or for an even deeper look the book by Varadarajan.

Its physical basis is space-time symmetry invarience and is not an axiom per-se. Specifically it's Galilean symmetries that leads to Schrodinger's equation. In fact of course its wrong because Galilaen relativity is wrong - the correct symmetries are relativistic and leads to the relativistic equations such as the Dirac equation.

That's one reason why I always recommend Ballentine as the textbook to learn QM from - he does the treatment correctly.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #12
bhobba said:
Sorry mate - you can derive it eg see Chapter 3 of Ballentine or for an even deeper look the book by Varadarajan.

Its physical basis is space-time symmetry invarience and is not an axiom per-se. Specifically is Galilean symmetries that leads to Schrodinger's equation. In fact of course its wrong because Galilaen relativity is wrong - the correct symmetries are relativistic and leads to the relativistic equations such as the Dirac equation.

That why I always recommend Ballentine as the textbook to learn QM from - he does the treatment correctly.

Thanks
Bill
I know this. You can also view the unitary representation of time translations as the axiom if you want to. For strongly continuous representations, they are equivalent. You can also have quantum theories with neither Galilean nor Lorentz symmetry though and still have a Schrödinger equation. Just think about a spin in a magnetic field for example). The point is that you can either view the Schrödinger equation or the strongly continuous unitary representation of time translations (possibly embedded into some larger group of symmetries) as the axiom; it doesn't really matter.
 
  • #13
rubi said:
You can't derive quantum theories.

Hmmmm.

Yes and no.

Yes one requires postulated axioms that are motivated by observation etc etc, and even seat of the pants guesses. But from those you can derive it. Also most exposed to such axiomatic approaches recognize more fundamental approaches over others.

Of relevance to dynamics it has long been known from the work of Wigner and others its true basis is symmetries. While no one can prove it, because its not the type of thing that you can prove, I suggest anyone that has been exposed to the symmetry approach recognizes its more fundamental than simply postulating things like Schrodinger's equation. I could be wrong of course - there may be someone out there who doesn't see its elegance and power - but to be blunt - I think you would have to have a funny view of what physics is about in the sense of discovering fundamental principles if you don't see it.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #14
bhobba said:
Hmmmm.

Yes and no.

Yes one requires postulated axioms that are motivated by observation etc etc, and even seat of the pants guesses. But from those you can derive it. Also most exposed to such axiomatic approaches recognize more fundamental approaches over others.

Of relevance to dynamics it has long been known from the work of Wigner and others its true basis is symmetries. While no one can prove it, because its not the type of thing that you can prove, I suggest anyone that has been exposed to the symmetry approach recognizes its more fundamental than simply postulating things like Schrodinger's equation. I could be wrong of course - there may be someone out there who doesn't see its elegance and power - but to be blunt - I think you would have to have a funny view of what physics is about in the sense of discovering fundamental principles if you don't see it.

Thanks
Bill
What I mean by "you can't derive quantum theories" is that you can't derive the correct representation of the symmetries that corresponds to a classical system. Of course you need to represent the symmetries due to Wigner's theorem, but there are usually infinitely many inequivalent representations and there is no way to choose the right one without additional physical input and experimental testing.
 
  • #15
rubi said:
it doesn't really matter.

Really. You don't think symmetries is the more fundamental concept?

If you don't I can't prove you wrong - but I suspect most exposed to it would disagree - I certainly do.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #16
rubi said:
What I mean by "you can't derive quantum theories" is that you can't derive the correct representation of the symmetries that corresponds to a classical system. Of course you need to represent the symmetries due to Wigner's theorem, but there are usually infinitely many inequivalent representations and there is no way to choose the right one without additional physical input and experimental testing.

That goes right to the heart of what I think the original post was about - exactly how one derives a quantum from a classical system - you can't uniquely do it - but what's going on is very deep and to really get to the bottom of you need the more advanced approaches such as that found in Varadarajan's book.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #17
rubi said:
(First of all: A Hamiltonian isn't just a Lagrangian with different coordinates. It's more than that.)

If you take the calculus of variations as your starting point, then yes it is exactly just that, (refer to the Gelfand quote I linked to in my OP if you have an issue with this statement). If you take the theory of first order pde's as your starting point, then we can say something which ultimately leads us to the exact same statement (c.f. chapter 16 of the Chester book in the No. 37 link I linked to in my OP if interested). If you want to deny all this then that's fine, but it is a different conversation because Schrodinger assumed what I'm talking about in his original derivation of his equation & got the correct result, so this is something that can't be ignored in the context of my questions.
rubi said:
As I pointed out above, we want to construct the quantum theory in such a way that it might have the right classical limit. How can we do this? The most obvious way to see this is to compare the classical Hamilton's equations with the quantum Heisenberg equations of motion:

Hamiltons equations of motion in classical mechanics: ##\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} f(t) = \{f,H\}##
Heisenbergs equations of motion in quantum mechanics: ##\mathrm i\hbar\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} \hat f(t) = [\hat f,\hat H]##

Now if you want the expectation values of the quantum dynamics to approach the classical dynamics for sharply peaked states and ##\hbar\rightarrow 0##, you could postulate ##[\widehat A,\widehat B] = \mathrm i\hbar\widehat{\{A,B\}} + O(\hbar^2)##. Then the idea is:
[tex]\frac{\mathrm d}{\mathrm d t} \left<\hat f(t)\right> = \frac{1}{\mathrm i\hbar}\left<[\hat f,\hat H]\right> = \left<\widehat{\{f,H\}}\right> + \frac{1}{\mathrm i\hbar}\left<O(\hbar^2)\right> \approx \{f,H\} + O(\hbar) \rightarrow \{f,H\}[/tex]
So we can at least hope to get some sort of correct classical limit by transforming the classical Poisson brackets into commutators of observables on the quantum side. For canonical conjugate variables, you even get the Heisenberg uncertainty principle.

This is interesting, if you take Schrodinger's derivation as holding, & factor in the fact that solutions are complex-valued eigenfunctions, then yes I can see that to get some form of Poisson bracket formulation you'll have to slightly modify things by throwing in complex numbers, & the rest of what you've written makes vagues sense to my uneducated self. None of this requires Hilbert spaces or any assumptions deviating from classical mechanics, it just factors in the reality that we have complex-valued solutions & modifies things in light of this. Do you have any problem with that? I don't see anything crazy going on here, I don't see any departure from classical mechanics apart from a complex function solution...

rubi said:
Because quantum variables aren't real-valued functions. Instead, they are operators on some Hilbert space without any canonical ordering. You can say ##3 < 5##, but you can't say ##\frac{\partial}{\partial x} < \frac{\partial^2}{\partial x^2}## (this expression just doesn't make any sense). You can't "minimize" anything here.

I don't know much quantum mechanics, so this very well may be a good reason in terms of the formalism you know, however I'm just going off the basics, I'm not assuming any of that formalism I'm trying to find out about the motivation that leads to such formalism as being essential.

I'm not trying to be flippant or aggressive but fundamentally I just doubt that this could be the reason, mainly because you're just extremizing a functional defined on a space of functions. Furthermore, if you can't construct an action & a Lagrangian for a system then you can't even talk about a Hamiltonian for the system, just doesn't make sense if you know anything about the calculus of variations. This really is fundamental, & if I'm wrong about any of this then Schrodinger was also just as wrong as I am in his original derivation, he was never allowed to write a Hamilton-Jacobi equation for a particle in his derivation (remember this is completely derivable from an action in terms of a Lagrangian in turn expressed in terms of a Hamiltonian c.f. Landau Mechanics Section 43 & 47), yet he did & he got his Schrodinger equation which gave the correct result. I'm just trying to make sense of this, why people would ignore this & go on to all the formalism so hastily, especially when it seems to implicitly encode classical mechanics?

rubi said:
Complex numbers aren't the reason why quantum mechanics is so drastically different. In fact, it might be possible to construct some reasonable quantum theories on Hilbert spaces over the real numbers. What makes QM so different from CM is the fact that it's formulated in an entirely different framework. States are (by definition) vectors in some Hilbert space, whereas in CM, they are just a list of real numbers and observables are self-adjoint operators (by definition), whereas in CM, they are just real-valued functions.

If you read my OP carefully you'll see that I'm questioning this very process. I've spoken about how you're using classical ideas to construct this new space, & I'm asking why one needs to do this in the first place? Why does one ignore the fact that Schrodinger derived his equation using classical principles & instead chooses to mish-mash a bunch of classical ideas together in a vector space & simply assert you can't get it from classical principles, when Schrodinger went & got it from classical principles in his original derivation?

rubi said:
The point is that you can either view the Schrödinger equation ... as the axiom; it doesn't really matter.

One of my questions is about this statement - if you accept Schrodinger's equation as an axiom, & Schrodinger's equation is derivable from completely & utterly basic classical mechanics principles as in Schrodinger's original derivation, then are you not saying quantum mechanics derives from classical mechanics, albeit with eigenfunction solutions that are complex-valued?
 
  • #18
bhobba said:
Really. You don't think symmetries is the more fundamental concept?

If you don't I can't prove you wrong - but I suspect most exposed to it would disagree - I certainly do.

They are more fundamental (in case they are there), but that's not relevant here. In case you have two equivalent statements, you are free to choose which one is the axiom and which one is to be derived. I was just trying to say "you have to postulate something that is equivalent to Schrödinger's equation" in a simple way in order not to confuse the OP too much. I didn't want to reformulate his statement into something he possibly doesn't understand.

bhobba said:
That goes right to the heart of what I think the original post was about - exactly how one derives a quantum from a classical system - you can't uniquely do it - but what's going on is very deep and to really get to the bottom of you need the more advanced approaches such as that found in Varadarajan's book.

The problem is that in many cases, the number of possible candidate theories is so huge that advanced approaches don't help either and you can't help but wait for experimental data. I'm arguing that you can't derive the correct quantum theory from purely theoretical considerations.
 
  • #19
bolbteppa - rubi is giving you quite precise answers. I just want to add put a rough statement that may help you see that QM is really different, and as far as we know Hilbert spaces and commutation relations for operators are fundamental. The way to see that QM is really different from the Lagrangian or path integral point of view is that in classical mechanics we only take the extremal path, but in QM we sum over all paths, and those that are not extremal are very important in the sum. In QM, using only the extremal path in the path integral is a classical approximation, also called the "saddle point" approximation.

Again, the formulation with Hilbert spaces and commutation relations is fundamental. The path integral is not as fundamental, but is a very powerful tool.
 
Last edited:
  • #20
bhobba said:
One thing I will mention is the need for complex numbers - its got to do with Wigners Theorem:
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wigner's_theorem

Unless you go to complex vector spaces it doesn't hold. This means you can't necessary find unitary transformations for symmetries which is the real deep foundation of dynamics in QM. If you do symmetry transformations you want the transformation to leave orthogonal vectors orthogonal and superpositions to still be in superposition ie unitary - there is only one way to guarantee it - Wigners Theorem. But that is only one aspect of the deep study of this stuff - it aren't easy - not easy at all.

That may very well be true in the formalism you know, but if I try to stick to what I know & use Schrodinger's original derivation based on completely classical principles I then arrive at complex numbers naturally, & apparently from my last post we can see how one arrives at a modified Poisson bracket formulation involving complex numbers. Based on this I can happily see why one would end up with something like Wigner's theorem but to say that Wigner's theorem is the actual reason seems to me to implicitly assume a QM formalism which, to me, seems to implicitly encode classical mechanics in it's build up, which is circular to my eyes at present. Schrodinger's derivation based on classical mechanics seems pretty solid to me, & nobody has pointed out flaws or assumptions in it, why does one leave all this & start constructing hilbert spaces, postulating axioms & claiming CM derives from QM when apparently it's the other way around...?

bhobba said:
Added Later:
Based on what you said in your clarifying post Varadarajan is the book you want.

I can tell this book is crazy, & I unerstand enough of the absolute basics of the mathematics inside to tell it's far too advanced & far too left-field as regards my questions. Based on what you know of it though, do you think it addresses my concerns about Schrodinger's equation implicitly encoding classical mechanics since it was derived from CM, & naturally results in discrete energy levels & complex eigenfunctions? I mean based on this you can see why rubi's description of quantization looks natural (described in my last response to rubi), but it seems to me to fall out of completely classical principles.

bhobba said:

That's a nice article, & I'll definitely use it in the future, but at the moment I'm not willing to assume axioms for QM when it appears to derive naturally from classical mechanics according to Schrodinger's original derivation. I could accept axioms if they were axioms on a Hilbert space that was constructed as a mathematical trick for getting answers the same way the H-J equation is a trick for dealing with lagrangian's & hamiltonians, & I'd be happy using that safe in the knowledge that it's just math, but at the moment I'm not sure what those axioms would be formalizing, it appears to me that they are formalizing classical mechanics allowing for complex-valued solutions & nothing more... What are your thoughts on what I'm saying about it all deriving from classical mechanics?


bhobba said:
In modern times many people such as myself think of QM as the most reasonable generalized probability model that allows for entanglement. That however doesn't get to the issue of dynamics which seems to be your concern.

Thanks
Bill

I heard a great comment from a lecturer that QM is a c-star algebra representation of non-commutative probability or something, potentially what you are talking about :tongue:
 
  • #21
atyy said:
bolbteppa - rubi is giving you quite precise answers.

Please don't imply I'm ignoring him. I'm not at all, have I not addressed & counter-acted each of his/her statements with my concerns? I'm doing my best here, as I know you guys are, but be fair.

atyy said:
I just want to add put a rough statement that may help you see that QM is really different, and as far as we know Hilbert spaces and commutation relations for operators are fundamental.

Again my whole post is calling this statement into question. Re-read my OP, this is an aspect of question a) I've posted in my op, I'm asking why you can simply assert this to be the case in light of the fact that Schrodinger's equation is completely classical, & this is extremely important if people are willing to take Schrodinger's equation as an axiom because it then appears you're smuggling classical mechanics in as an axiom. I don't see how this can be wrong, I'm wondering what you guys think about this?

atyy said:
The way to see that QM is really different from the Lagrangian or path integral point of view is that in classical mechanics we only take the extremal path, but in QM we sum over all paths, and those that are not extremal are very important in the sum. In QM, using only the extremal path in the path integral is a classical approximation, also called the "saddle point" approximation.

The path integral approach seems to leave the realm of the calculus of variations, just because you can get answers using a different approach not involving ideas of the calculus of variations does not imply that the theory cannot also be studied using the calculus of variations. Again what makes my statements more than mere assertions is the fact that Schrodinger's original derivation assumed basic calculus of variations & got the fundamental equation. That is just too important to ignore.

atyy said:
Again, the formulation with Hilbert spaces and commutation relations is fundamental. The path integral is not as fundamental, but is a very powerful tool.

As to the first part of this statement I've addressed it above, for the second - the link you gave me said it was completely fundamental:

"The path integral is a formulation of quantum mechanics equivalent to the standard formulations, offering a new way of looking at the subject which is, arguably, more intuitive than the usual approaches."
http://arxiv.org/abs/quantph/0004090

and the path integral generalizes to quantum field theory, if anything is it not more fundamental? It seems to take the calculus of variations as it's starting point & go on from there, so for a theory derived from lagrangians & hamiltonians to be described by a formalism that takes these as it's starting point you may well be right about it not being as fundamental, I don't know but it's interesting.
 
  • #22
Schroedinger's "derivation" was not a derivation, as samalkhaiat already pointed out in the thread you linked to in your OP. In Schroedinger's equation, the wave function is a vector in a Hilbert space. Furthermore, Schroedinger did not know the Born rule at that time, which says that the square of the wave function is a probability.
 
  • #23
bolbteppa said:
If you take the calculus of variations as your starting point, then yes it is exactly just that, (refer to the Gelfand quote I linked to in my OP if you have an issue with this statement). If you take the theory of first order pde's as your starting point, then we can say something which ultimately leads us to the exact same statement (c.f. chapter 16 of the Chester book in the No. 37 link I linked to in my OP if interested). If you want to deny all this then that's fine, but it is a different conversation because Schrodinger assumed what I'm talking about in his original derivation of his equation & got the correct result, so this is something that can't be ignored in the context of my questions.
The Hamiltonian is defined to be ##H=pq-L##, so it is at best related to the Lagrangian, not the same as the Lagrangian.
Schrödinger definitely didn't derive his equation from just classical mechanics. He used additional axioms, given by physical input. There is definitely no way to derive Schrödinger's equation from just classical mechanics alone. Also, Schrödinger's equation has been generalized to much more abstract settings nowadays. It doesn't need to be a partial differential equation anymore. That's just the case if you are doing physics with a fixed number of particles.

This is interesting, if you take Schrodinger's derivation as holding, & factor in the fact that solutions are complex-valued eigenfunctions, then yes I can see that to get some form of Poisson bracket formulation you'll have to slightly modify things by throwing in complex numbers, & the rest of what you've written makes vagues sense to my uneducated self. None of this requires Hilbert spaces or any assumptions deviating from classical mechanics, it just factors in the reality that we have complex-valued solutions & modifies things in light of this. Do you have any problem with that? I don't see anything crazy going on here, I don't see any departure from classical mechanics apart from a complex function solution...
The departure from CM is that the variables with hats are operators and the ##\left<\ldots\right>## are inner products of vectors in a Hilbert space. Actually everything I wrote there is heavily based on the quantum formalism. The usage of complex numbers is actually the most irrelevant part of the calculation.

I don't know much quantum mechanics, so this very well may be a good reason in terms of the formalism you know, however I'm just going off the basics, I'm not assuming any of that formalism I'm trying to find out about the motivation that leads to such formalism as being essential.
The formalism is not essential. It's just the best thing we have at the moment. Maybe we will have something different in 50 years. (Who knows?) You just have to accept the axioms of quantum theory if you want to do quantum theory.

Furthermore, if you can't construct an action & a Lagrangian for a system then you can't even talk about a Hamiltonian for the system, just doesn't make sense if you know anything about the calculus of variations.
The Hamiltonian in quantum theory is completely unrelated to calculus of variations. We just use the same name for the quantum object and the classical object, because they both play the same roles in the corresponding theories: They are the generators of time-evolution. Apart from that, they are mathematically completely different objects.

This really is fundamental, & if I'm wrong about any of this then Schrodinger was also just as wrong as I am in his original derivation, he was never allowed to write a Hamilton-Jacobi equation for a particle in his derivation (remember this is completely derivable from an action in terms of a Lagrangian in turn expressed in terms of a Hamiltonian c.f. Landau Mechanics Section 43 & 47), yet he did & he got his Schrodinger equation which gave the correct result. I'm just trying to make sense of this, why people would ignore this & go on to all the formalism so hastily, especially when it seems to implicitly encode classical mechanics?
The best advice I can give you if you really want to understand quantum theory is: Forget about the historical "derivations" and learn it from modern books. You can read the historical stuff later. At the moment it will just confuse you.

If you read my OP carefully you'll see that I'm questioning this very process. I've spoken about how you're using classical ideas to construct this new space, & I'm asking why one needs to do this in the first place? Why does one ignore the fact that Schrodinger derived his equation using classical principles & instead chooses to mish-mash a bunch of classical ideas together in a vector space & simply assert you can't get it from classical principles, when Schrodinger went & got it from classical principles in his original derivation?
You can question it, but it doesn't help. It's just the way physics works. Schrödinger didn't derive anything. He just used lots of heuristics. I can't say this more clearly. It is impossible to derive the Schrödinger equation.

One of my questions is about this statement - if you accept Schrodinger's equation as an axiom, & Schrodinger's equation is derivable from completely & utterly basic classical mechanics principles as in Schrodinger's original derivation, then are you not saying quantum mechanics derives from classical mechanics, albeit with eigenfunction solutions that are complex-valued?
Schrödinger's equation is not derivable from classical mechanics. Every physicist working in quantum theory agrees with this. You can either postulate it directly or indirectly (using symmetry principles), but not derive it from classical mechanics. Please acknowledge this.
 
  • #24
atyy said:
Schroedinger's "derivation" was not a derivation, as samalkhaiat already pointed out in the thread you linked to in your OP. In Schroedinger's equation, the wave function is a vector in a Hilbert space. Furthermore, Schroedinger did not know the Born rule at that time, which says that the square of the wave function is a probability.

If you read Weinstock on page 262 he says "the reader familiar with quantum theory should soon recognize the identity of K with the well known (h/2pi)".

Then later he says:

In a more complete study of quantum mechanics than the present one the admissibility of complex eigenfunctions Ψ is generally shown to be necessary. If Ψ is complex, the quantity |Ψ|2 is employed as the position probability-density function inasmuch as Ψ2 is not restricted to real nonnegative values.

Apparently Schrodinger was able to do what I have posted using real-valued functions & have K as I have defined it, without i. If you're following what Weinstock is saying he shows how the hydrogen atom energy levels are explainable without complex numbers in it, i.e. he is able to derive a physical interpretation of the eigenvalues (discrete energy levels) of the Schrodinger equation that were in accord with experiment (see Section 11.3 Page 279 on). As far as I understand it it is in trying to find a physical interpretation of the eigenfunctions that one is forced into complex numbers, though apparently, according to the book, it can be shown to be necessary.

Finally if you read Weinstock you'll see Schrodinger implicitly assumes the normalization condition in an addendum to his paper, but that "it was, for some time after, uncertain what physical interpretation should be assigned to the corresponding eigenfunctions" & then goes on to discuss how later the square of the wave function was interpreted as a probability density function, but I mean the seeds of this were encoded in his original derivation as one can derive what he does in his original derivation by encoding the normalization as part of an isoperimetric problem.

To simply assert this derivation given in black & white in Weinstock's textbook is not a derivation is something else...

This was all more or less directed at samalkhaiat in my response in that thread where it was wasn't responded to, so again your implication I'm ignoring people is without merit.
 
  • #25
bolbteppa said:
If you read Weinstock on page 262 he says "the reader familiar with quantum theory should soon recognize the identity of K with the well known (h/2pi)".

Then later he says:
Apparently Schrodinger was able to do what I have posted using real-valued functions & have K as I have defined it, without i. If you're following what Weinstock is saying he shows how the hydrogen atom energy levels are explainable without complex numbers in it, i.e. he is able to derive a physical interpretation of the eigenvalues (discrete energy levels) of the Schrodinger equation that were in accord with experiment (see Section 11.3 Page 279 on). As far as I understand it it is in trying to find a physical interpretation of the eigenfunctions that one is forced into complex numbers, though apparently, according to the book, it can be shown to be necessary.

Finally if you read Weinstock you'll see Schrodinger implicitly assumes the normalization condition in an addendum to his paper, but that "it was, for some time after, uncertain what physical interpretation should be assigned to the corresponding eigenfunctions" & then goes on to discuss how later the square of the wave function was interpreted as a probability density function, but I mean the seeds of this were encoded in his original derivation as one can derive what he does in his original derivation by encoding the normalization as part of an isoperimetric problem.

To simply assert this derivation given in black & white in Weinstock's textbook is not a derivation is something else...

This was all more or less directed at samalkhaiat in my response in that thread where it was wasn't responded to, so again your implication I'm ignoring people is without merit.

I don't have access to Weinstock, but it seems that's the time-independent Schroedinger's equation. If that's the case, then basically it isn't the Schroedinger equation that I think most people in the discussions were referring to, which is the time-dependent Schroedinger equation.

Edit: I got a little view on Google books - is it eq 4 on p263 you are referring to as Schroedinger's equation? That's the time-independent equation.
 
Last edited:
  • #26
rubi said:
The Hamiltonian is defined to be ##H=pq-L##, so it is at best related to the Lagrangian, not the same as the Lagrangian.

Do you know what the Legendre transformation is? It's simply a change of variables to represent a function in terms of derivatives of that function. This is one way of arriving at the Hamiltonian, but there are others & Gelfand gives about three derivations of the Hamiltonian in there, one aimed at finding a more symmetric version of the equations of motion after a change of variables, nothing more (check the link I gave iin my OP), another using the legendre transformation & one or two more I think. In other words, in the calculus of variations they are equivalent in the sense one is just a re-parametrization of the other (assuming you can find an invertible change of variables from the Lagrangian to the Hamiltonian), where you can do it via Legendre transformations. There's a lot rolled up in there alright, the graph on page 3 here should make the use of, & geometric relationship to, the derivative look very intuitive.

rubi said:
Schrödinger definitely didn't derive his equation from just classical mechanics. He used additional axioms, given by physical input. There is definitely no way to derive Schrödinger's equation from just classical mechanics alone. Also, Schrödinger's equation has been generalized to much more abstract settings nowadays. It doesn't need to be a partial differential equation anymore. That's just the case if you are doing physics with a fixed number of particles.

I'm sorry but you must have missed the links I've given because I've posted Schrodinger's original derivation & I've explained in that thread, in my OP & subsequent posts how Schrodinger's derivation assumes nothing more than classical lagrangian & hamiltonian mechanics. Here it is again. You speak of additional axioms, but none are actually mentioned, are you sure you haven't accepted that on faith? Please read that derivation & re-evalute.

rubi said:
The departure from CM is that the variables with hats are operators and the ##\left<\ldots\right>## are inner products of vectors in a Hilbert space. Actually everything I wrote there is heavily based on the quantum formalism. The usage of complex numbers is actually the most irrelevant part of the calculation.

I read your Poisson bracket representation of Hamilton's equations as involving solutions of Schrodinger's equation where the function has a hat to express the fact it is in terms of complex numbers, & explicitly working out the poisson bracket results in extra terms thus the L.H.S. must be modified to get your Hamilton's equations back. It seems that complex numbers are literally the only new addition to your equations. This should only make sense if you really understand Schrodinger's derivation & understand that he assumes real values throughout, & naturally derives the necessity for complex-valued eigenfunction solutions as mentioned by Weinstock (it's mentioned in a note on page 276 as mentioned in the thread on Schrodinger's derivation). I don't see any other justification for quantization at present, in terms of Schrodinger's original derivation anyway (I'm happy to follow a textbook & do what they do, but in terms of understanding it I think Schrodinger's original derivation is just too important to ignore, I'm surprised nobody else thinks so!).

rubi said:
The formalism is not essential. It's just the best thing we have at the moment. Maybe we will have something different in 50 years. (Who knows?) You just have to accept the axioms of quantum theory if you want to do quantum theory.

Schrodinger didn't seem to need to, how does that not interest you?

rubi said:
The Hamiltonian in quantum theory is completely unrelated to calculus of variations. We just use the same name for the quantum object and the classical object, because they both play the same roles in the corresponding theories: They are the generators of time-evolution. Apart from that, they are mathematically completely different objects.

In modern QM you may well be right, however in Schrodinger's original derivation it is indeed the classical hamiltonian & the hamiltonian in his Schrodinger equation is indeed the clasical hamiltonian, so while modern theory may have nothing to do with the calculus of variations it seems the very origin of the modern theory did indeed.

rubi said:
The best advice I can give you if you really want to understand quantum theory is: Forget about the historical "derivations" and learn it from modern books. You can read the historical stuff later. At the moment it will just confuse you.

You're absolutely right, & I'm forced to do both, however for the purposes of this thread I hope we can ignore the modern theory as much as possible & just focus on how Schrodinger's derivation is flawed, or if it isn't why one must blindly accept axioms when apparently you can get it all from classical mechanics.

rubi said:
You can question it, but it doesn't help. It's just the way physics works. Schrödinger didn't derive anything. He just used lots of heuristics. I can't say this more clearly. It is impossible to derive the Schrödinger equation.

Again refer to Weinstock &/or my thread linked to above to see it in black & white, it's amazing, & if you can understand the mathematical tricks & whether they are generalizable let me know.

rubi said:
Schrödinger's equation is not derivable from classical mechanics. Every physicist working in quantum theory agrees with this. You can either postulate it directly or indirectly (using symmetry principles), but not derive it from classical mechanics. Please acknowledge this.

If you don't completely understand how the Hamilton-Jacobi equation implicitly assumes the existence of a Lagrangian & a Hamiltonian ala classical mechanics then you might be able to make this statement after reading Schrodinger's derivation. I don't see how you can do it if you do understand that & understand Schrodinger's derivation, I really don't. Think about it again after digesting what I've posted.
 
  • #27
bolbteppa said:
I can tell this book is crazy, & I unerstand enough of the absolute basics of the mathematics inside to tell it's far too advanced & far too left-field as regards my questions. Based on what you know of it though, do you think it addresses my concerns about Schrodinger's equation implicitly encoding classical mechanics since it was derived from CM,

Grin and hearty laugh.:rofl::rofl::rofl::rofl::rofl:

It's not crazy - just - mathematically non trivial - :rolleyes::rolleyes::rolleyes::rolleyes:.

It's spot on for the question you are looking at - exactly how QM is a generalization of the formalism of classical mechanics. It starts from our most mathematically sophisticated version of CM and works its way from there developing QM as a generalization and also providing the best approach we have to address the question how do we get a QM system from a classical one.

Of course Schrodinger's equation encodes CM. Although not usually presented this way - however Landau's classical book Mechanics does it - CM is basically the PLA and the Galilean Principle of Relativity - if you haven't seen this get Landau's book and give it a read - he even proves the existence of mass and that it must be positive.

Schrodinger's equation is basically the principles of QM and Galilean Relativity. You will find the approach in Ballentine and to an even greater extent in Varadarajan. If you don't want to go into the detail of that book (and I most definitely do NOT blame you) get Ballentine and study chapter 3.

QM, as presented in that book, is based on two axioms:

1. Observables are Hermitian operators over a complex vector space whose eigenvalues are the possible outcomes of observations.

2. Given an observable O there exists a positive operator of unit trace P such that the expected outcome of an observation is Tr(PO). P is by definition the state of the system.

The two axioms are not entirely unrelated in that, with the assumption the probability can not depend on the basis (called non-contextuality), 2 follows from 1 via Gleason's theorem - which is also used in Varadarajan - and one reason it's hard - Gleason's theorem is known as hard - Varadarajan is like that all the way through - as you probably know if you have looked at it.

Now what you find in Ballentine, is with the assumption of the principle of Galilean relativity you get Shrodenger's equation.

This is entirely analogous with CM because axiom 1 and 2 imply the PLA.

Basically the dynamics of CM and QM are due to the the classical POR - like so much of physics symmetry is the real rock bottom reason.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited:
  • #28
atyy said:
I don't have access to Weinstock, but it seems that's the time-independent Schroedinger's equation. If that's the case, then basically it isn't the Schroedinger equation that I think most people in the discussions were referring to, which is the time-dependent Schroedinger equation.

Edit: I got a little view on Google books - is it eq 4 on p263 you are referring to as Schroedinger's equation? That's the time-independent equation.

Oh my god... I think you've just destroyed my argument - it's time independent!

I'm going to have to think about this for a while now, well spotted!
 
  • #29
What a kick in the face, Schrodinger's original papers don't even mention the time-dependent equation. A nice discussion of all this is given http://www.mpipks-dresden.mpg.de/~rost/jmr-reprints/brro01.pdf. Seemed so nice for a moment :frown: Thanks for the help guys, will definitely use all your links throughout the year.
 
Last edited:
  • #30
bolbteppa said:
I heard a great comment from a lecturer that QM is a c-star algebra representation of non-commutative probability or something, potentially what you are talking about :tongue:

That's more related to Varadarajan - but not what I was getting at, which isn't really related to the highly mathematically sophisticated approach you find in that book. It most definitely is NOT bed time reading.

However Geometrical Quantisation it is the most powerful approach we have to answer the question how is QM related to CM
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Geometric_quantization
'In mathematical physics, geometric quantization is a mathematical approach to defining a quantum theory corresponding to a given classical theory. It attempts to carry out quantization, for which there is in general no exact recipe, in such a way that certain analogies between the classical theory and the quantum theory remain manifest. For example, the similarity between the Heisenberg equation in the Heisenberg picture of quantum mechanics and the Hamilton equation in classical physics should be built in.'

I am a bit surprised its even under discussion - I thought it was well known.

The issue of the relation of QM and CM is very deep and our most potent mathematical formalism's are required to fully flesh it out - and even then issues remain.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #31
bhobba said:
Sorry mate - you can derive it eg see Chapter 3 of Ballentine or for an even deeper look the book by Varadarajan.

Its physical basis is space-time symmetry invarience and is not an axiom per-se. Specifically it's Galilean symmetries that leads to Schrodinger's equation. In fact of course its wrong because Galilaen relativity is wrong - the correct symmetries are relativistic and leads to the relativistic equations such as the Dirac equation.

That's one reason why I always recommend Ballentine as the textbook to learn QM from - he does the treatment correctly.

Thanks
Bill

Unfortunately I don't have Ballentine or Varadarajan, so I thought I'd ask:

I'm guessing (maybe wrongly?) that what they derive is the single particle Schrodinger equation in coordinate space. But can they really derive the functional Schrodinger equation which must be satisfied by the states (discussed in Hatfield's book). Isn't this fundamental/axiomatic?
 
  • #32
sheaf said:
But can they really derive the functional Schrodinger equation which must be satisfied by the states (discussed in Hatfield's book). Isn't this fundamental/axiomatic?

Its derived for multi particle states. Whats fundamental and axiomatic depends on your choice of axioms. Ballentine derives it from the invarience of Born's rule under space-time rotations and translations which in implied by Galilean relativity. Most would consider that more fundamental than Schrodinger's equation because it is a general law of physics applicable to say EM as well - not just QM.

Specifically what he shows is the standard energy, momentum, and angular momentum operators must have the form of classical mechanics. In many cases of practical interest that's enough to quantize the system - its more general than the Poisson Bracket approach ala Dirac but not as powerful as the geometric approach - but that is mathematically quite advanced - still its the most powerful approach we have.

The standard cookbook methods in the usual undergrad texts like Griffiths skirt of over these issues. Applying Schrodinger's equation in many cases is not prescriptive. What these approaches attempt to do is rectify that - but unfortunately problems remain.

Thanks
Bill
 
  • #33
That paper http://www.mpipks-dresden.mpg.de/~rost/jmr-reprints/brro01.pdf above is quite frankly amazing, I wish I'd come across it before starting this thread. In it they begin with Schrodinger's original derivation of the TISE (albeit in more modern language, coincidentally in terms of the operators rubi said would prevent Schrodinger's derivation from holding true!), discuss Schrodinger's problems with the TDSE, go on to derive the TDSE from the TISE, discuss the importance of treating time as a classical quantity alien to quantum mechanics that arises in the TDSE as the result of a closed quantum system described by the TISE interacting with a classical external environment, speak about flaws in assuming time being an operator in QM, make a very interesting argument about the complex number in [itex]i\bar{h}\tfrac{\partial }{\partial t}[/itex] as arising only due to interactions with the external environment & not always being necessary (I think) & they also make an argument for the necessity of complex solutions in the TDSE as arising from interactions with the external classical system. I'd think this were a crank paper if it wasn't by a person in the Max-Planck-Institute...

In the paper they derive the TDSE by assuming the TISE holds for the system & the environment together. In other words, they derive the TDSE from the TISE equation which was derived from fully classical principles, the point I've been making throughout this thread. Apparently it is within that complicated derivation they give that one will find the true reason why we all need to assume axioms. It's too difficult for me right now, but if anybody found this thread interesting & is interested in finding an answer this is the place to find it. If it's interesting enough I'd love it if that person would dumb it down for me, if not I'll eventually get there (I hope) :tongue:

A less important point - they make a comment

In modern quantum mechanics textbooks little reference is made to Schrodinger's order of development or to his difficulties with the TDSE. Rather the TDSE is simply presented as the fundamental equation of wave mechanics from which the TISE (and hence a wavefunction with the exp(-iEt/(h/2pi)) factor) is derived as a special case for time-independent Hamiltonians. No mention is made of the fact that time is entering only from a classical interacting environment or that the TDSE does not correspond to energy conservation (the fundamental equation of wave mechanics violates the fundamental principle of physics)
Page 6

What do they mean by the fact that the fundamental equation of wave mechanics violates a fundamental principle of physics?

I think it relies on the fact time is involved in the equation (in the paper they stress the fact that time is a classical quantity whereas we're dealing with a quantum system) & it seems to me that they claim time only enters the TDSE by considering the TISE as fundamental & then imagining interaction of a closed system with a classical external environment as what changes in time represents:

the starting point is the TISE for a closed, energy conserving, quantum object comprised of two parts, called the system and the environment. In the limit that the environment can be treated classically, it provides a time variable with which to monitor the remaining quantum system whose development, as viewed from the environment, is governed by the TDSE for the system alone. This derivation shows explicitly that the origin of the classical time in [itex]H(t)[/itex] is due to coupling with the classical environment, and that the parametric derivative  [itex]\partial/\partial t[/itex] arises from the transition of environment variables from quantum to classical behaviour.
Page 2

Obviously time in a classical potential represents loss of conservation of energy, so I'm wondering how to make sense of all this here. In QM time in a potential allows "for transitions between one energy level & another" (Griffith QM P298), where the transition is caused by interactions with the external classical system as per the paper, yet I don't get what they mean by the TDSE violating fundamental principles, anybody have an idea?
 
  • #34
rubi said:
Schrödinger's equation is not derivable from classical mechanics. Every physicist working in quantum theory agrees with this. You can either postulate it directly or indirectly (using symmetry principles), but not derive it from classical mechanics. Please acknowledge this.

Of course it isn't - nor do I think it can ever be. Its just the physical principle that underlies CM is the same as in QM - the POR. But what the symmetries apply to is different - in CM its the PLA - in QM its the principles of QM (depending on what axioms you use). The PLA follows from those axioms so its hardly surprising there are analogies - but that's all there is. The Geometric approach to QM tries to pin down, as far as possible, exactly how QM and CM are related. A lot of progress seems to have been made, and I am surprised how far it has been taken, but there is zero doubt in my mind the program will always have issues. Still one never knows.

Just a personal comment. I have always been puzzled by Wigner famous paper:
http://www.dartmouth.edu/~matc/MathDrama/reading/Wigner.html

I now believe, along with Murray Gell-Mann, the reason for that is because each level is emergent from the level below it, so reproduces much of its formalism with a few twists.


QM and its relation to CM in an example of this. QFT and its relation to QM takes it further, and whatever theory lies below that (maybe string theory?) will as well.

Thanks
Bill
 
Last edited by a moderator:
  • #35
bhobba said:
Of course it isn't - nor do I think it can ever be. Its just the physical principle that underlies CM is the same as in QM - the POR.

Apparently that paper derives the TISE from the TDSE, in other words the TDSE is derived from an equation (the TISE) which itself was derived from classical mechanical principles. If this claim is incorrect it lies in the approximations in the derivation of the TISE, i.e. the derivation reaches a point at which classical mechanics simply disappears & becomes impossible to sustain. Up to this point, which I can't fathom in my persual of the derivation around page 12 of that article, I think I'm correct in saying that everything is completely classical & that hasn't been challenged by anybody yet.

Am I right in saying this? I think I am.

If it interests you enough to read that derivation please let me know where the point of no return lies & why it's unavoidable, maybe you'll see how it relates to what Varadarajan does.
 

Similar threads

  • Quantum Physics
Replies
6
Views
1K
Replies
62
Views
5K
  • Introductory Physics Homework Help
Replies
5
Views
255
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
951
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
8
Views
2K
Replies
44
Views
3K
Replies
3
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
22
Views
1K
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
1
Views
996
  • Quantum Physics
Replies
2
Views
1K
Back
Top