Gordon Watson said:
Bill, to cover ALL the specific experiments under discussion (W, X, Y, Z), I suggest it is better to state the general case:
All that remains now is to use Malus' Method to get P(B^+|Q,\,A^+) (or P(B^+|Q,\,A^-) according to the experimental conditions Q (be they W, X, Y or Z).
By Malus' Method I mean: Following Malus' example (ca 1808-1812, as I recall), we study the results of experiments and write equations to capture the underlying generalities.
Cheers, GW
harrylin said:
Likely this is indeed the main issue. For this is basically what QM did. And doing so does not provide a mechanism for how this may be possible.
Harald, thanks for your plain speaking: note that
what follows is to be understood as IMHO.
If you refer to the "Malus Method" as the main issue, keep in mind that its use is still limited (here) to
classical analysis with a focus on ontology (i.e., the nature of λ, the HVs; the nature of particle/device interactions -- δ
aλ, δ
bλ' -- from a classical point of view). In that way it differs from some "QM Methods". And in that way it DOES provide "a mechanism": for the method itself was prompted by the search for the "underlying" mechanics; and it would not be up for discussion if nothing of interest had been found: the interesting point in the OP being that of finding functions satisfying Bell's A and B.
In brief, the mechanics goes thus: The HV-carrying particles, their HVs pair-wise correlated by recognised mechanisms, separate and fly to Alice and Bob. Interaction with the respective devices leads to a local transformation of each HV, most clearly seen in W where photons (initially pair-wise linearly-polarised identically) are transformed into pairs with different linear-polarisations. (Representing a fact accepted early in the foundations of QM: a "measurement" perturbs the measured object.) ... ... ...
Since the classical analysis is straight-forward, and Einstein-local (but see below), I suggest you study it and then see how it applies to your interest in Herbert's Paradox and its mechanics.
If you ensure that every step in your classical analysis satisfies Einstein-locality, the accompanying part of the analysis MUST relate to determining the distribution of the Einstein-local outcomes. That brings in probability theory ("maths is the best logic") to derive the frequencies that will be found experimentally. And, classically, you need to clearly distinguish between causal independence and logical dependence.
harrylin said:
The purpose of such derivations as the one you are doing, should be to determine if the same is true for a similar law about the correlation between the detections of two light rays at far away places. Merely including experimental results does not do that. Malus law for the detected light intensity of a light ray going into one direction can be easily explained with cause and effect models, but this is not done by writing down Malus law.
Malus' famous Law is strictly limited to W. To move beyond that we move to Malus' Method: doing what we expect he would have done classically if he (like us) was confronted with data from multi-particle (Alice and Bob, EPRB-style experiments; GHSZ, GHZ, CRB, etc.) experiments. (NB: Malus' Law makes interesting reading in the QM context of particles being detected one-at-a-time; perhaps trickier than your comment suggests, in my view.)
harrylin said:
PS. Your "Note in passing" that "Einstein-locality [EL, per GW] is maintained through every step of the analysis", is the main point that is to be proved, as Bell claimed to have disproved it; it can't be a "note in passing".
My "note in passing" could equally have been "NB" or "friendly reminder to the diligent reader" -- it was (IMHO) incidental to the discussion in that EL is not the main point to be proved. Rather the main point , it seems to me, is to shoot-down the classical analysis if it fails to be totally faithful to EL.
For if EL is breached, anywhere in the classical analysis, then that analysis would be next to worthless.
So you should check to see how EL is dealt with (once and for all, at the start of the analysis), and then ensure that the remaining classical maths is focussed on determining the frequencies of the various outcomes that will be found experimentally: with no unintended disruption or fiddling-with EL; nor cheating.
As to what Bell proved, it is my opinion that he proved that EPR elements of physical reality are untenable. (A conclusion I support.) So, imho, it is possible to see EL maintained in Bell's work, and popular ideas about reality condemned.
Do you wonder then: Where does the classical analysis here depart from Bell's analysis?
You will see that nowhere here, classically, do we address a third device, at orientation
c, in the same context as discussing an experiment with Alice (device-orientation
a) and Bob (
b).
** That move by Bell, it seems to me, confirms his focus on EPR elements of reality. For, otherwise, he needs must recognise that a measurement locally perturbs the measured system ... and until that perturbation, EPR elements of reality (generally) do not exist (IMHO). Or, to put it another way: the move to
c follows from an acceptance of EPR's epr; though there may be other views of reality that also permit it ... remembering that Bell's theorem is
not a property of quantum theory (Peres 1995, 162), so it is not unreasonable to examine the extent to which it is NOT a property of classical theory.
PS: Discussion of this line would be best in a new thread, it seems to me. (The focus here should be on finding errors in the classical approach.)
** That is: The classical analysis ranges over (
a,
b), (
b,
c), (
a,
c); reflecting all possible real experiments, but no impossible ones. Also: The HVs are classically sourced from infinite sets so that (here, in this case)
no two pairs of particles are the same (P = 0).
With thanks again,
GW