It's just some people argue that it's almost MW's last problem and if it's derived,MW would be "over the other interpretations".vanhees71 said:For me there's no need to derive Born's rule, because it's simply a fundamental postulate of quantum theory.
It surely depends what the derivation is based on. For a long time I too believed that Born"s rule ought to be derivable from Schrödinger's equation. But whenever I studied promising articles, the proof contained an innocent looking assumption that was equivalent to Born's rule (if it wasn't just shrouded in mathematIcs). Now I'm convinced that it is an independent ingredient of QM and even more important than the wave function. (What's observable can always be expressed using operators.)Adrian Lee said:Many articles these years claim that they have derived it.
I don't consider MW an interpretation at all. It claims that Schrödinger's equation and continuous evolution is all there is to quantum theory. I can't believe that discrete events like the clicks of a Geiger counter are tricks played on us by our senses while the underlying reality evolves continuously. MWI glosses over the discrepancy with nothing but hand waving.Adrian Lee said:It's just some people argue that it's almost MW's last problem and if it's derived,MW would be "over the other interpretations".
I agree completely.vanhees71 said:I must admit that I never understood what MW is good for nor how it interprets quantum states.
Is there any non-minimal interpretation of QM for which you do understand what is it good for?vanhees71 said:I must admit that I never understood what MW is good for nor how it interprets quantum states.
Every observer with his or her own world. :-)Fra said:I agree completely.
Many interacting observers - yes, but many worlds? What is the explanatory value and how it helps us forward?
/Fredrik
Not own worldMathematicalPhysicist said:Every observer with his or her own world. :-)
The "one common world" is the one which needs proof of its existence, otherwise it's as always assumed that it exists.Fra said:Not own worldEvery observer with its own subjectively inferred imperfect expectation of the one common world.
Observer equivalence is the special case of observer democracy where all the observers evolved their views to be in tune as analogous to a Nash equilibrium. Once in tune, the views asymptotically exhibits the symmetries the traditional pardigm sees as timeless constraints.
/Fredrik
The only meaning I assign to the "one common world" is "what you get from all physical observers that are in causal contact with each other". Exactly what this is in detail - the microstructure of observers and their relations - is of course what the whole game of inference is about. It´s also necessarily moving target as I think the inference process itself helps to form and a self-organisation will take place. There will never be a complete answer, because the more complex and observer gets, it´s ability to encode more complex relations increase. The ambition is IMO just to understand the abductive inference mechanisms here.MathematicalPhysicist said:The "one common world" is the one which needs proof of its existence, otherwise it's as always assumed that it exists.
Its not much different from the continuous evolution of a discrete number of corona viruses from 0, to 1,2,3,4, to a huge number.WernerQH said:You mean there is continuous evolution from 5, 4, 3, ... down to 0 undecayed atoms? I think there is some actual granularity that theoreticians should not conceal just because differential equations are easier to work with.
It's strange for a mathematician to be lacking in a precise definition of the term "continuous". :-)A. Neumaier said:Its not much different from the continuous evolution of a discrete number of corona viruses from 0, to 1,2,3,4, to a huge number.
This is a physics forum, so I use the term consistent with physics usage. But I presume that the evolution of viruses is governed primarily by classical mechanics, which is continuous even in the mathematical sense.WernerQH said:It's strange for a mathematician to be lacking in a precise definition of the term "continuous". :-)
I think what's effectively continuous and what is not is observer-dependent. A binary state always has a discrete transition, but if can consider the probability for the transition of the same state by observing the context as well, it can be almost continous. But the latter description contains MORE information and thus requires a sufficiently complex observer.WernerQH said:You mean there is continuous evolution from 5, 4, 3, ... down to 0 undecayed atoms? I think there is some actual granularity that theoreticians should not conceal just because differential equations are easier to work with.
I think such infinite and uncountable amounts of information is likely a fiction that works well for describing atomic phenomena from the perspective of a dominant classical environment.vanhees71 said:In quantum theory the evolution of the state (statistical operator) is described by a partial differential equation and thus is continuous. So are the probabilities and related expectation values concerning discrete variables
Isn't that about the time evolution only? MWI says that the evolution of the state is given by the Schrödinger's equation, no collapse. It doesn't say that there are no other accpects of QM. At least that is how I always understood it.WernerQH said:Right. Schrödinger's equation by itself is not enough; we need the Born rule to obtain measurable quantities from the wave function. Accordingly it is not derivable from Schrödinger's equation. But it seems that MWI supporters disagree and prefer to think that Schrödinger's equation is all that quantum theory is about.
WernerQH said:What people have qualms about is how unitary evolution and "measurements" fit together. Schwinger's action principle that led to the closed time-path formalism allows direct calculation of observable quantities. It smoothly joins unitary evolution and "measurements" in one formalism.
The other aspects are the other universes, or branches thereof. The central puzzle is: How does the wave function relate to the real world that we perceive around us?martinbn said:Isn't that about the time evolution only? MWI says that the evolution of the state is given by the Schrödinger's equation, no collapse. It doesn't say that there are no other accpects of QM. At least that is how I always understood it.
WernerQH said:But it seems that MWI supporters disagree and prefer to think that Schrödinger's equation is all that quantum theory is about.
How does Schwinger's action principle lead to Born's rule?WernerQH said:What people have qualms about is how unitary evolution and "measurements" fit together. Schwinger's action principle that led to the closed time-path formalism allows direct calculation of observable quantities. It smoothly joins unitary evolution and the Born rule in one formalism.
It's the small subsystem seens as an "observer" that has no control, yes. This is my point as well! Yet it has to act without full control. How are its actions caused ? Totally random? By deterministic rules? If so, which ones? Can we get insighgs from pondering about this? (I think yes of course)vanhees71 said:To the contrary! If you have a small subsystem coupled to a macroscopic "environment", you don't have control
This is from the perspective of the dominany, classical observer - yes. This is statistical description from a different perspective, not a causation.vanhees71 said:i.e., we average over a lot of unknown degrees of freedom to effectively describe the "relevant observables" of the subsystem.
This extrapolation rules is something I think we can improve. A similar principle could be perhaps that "all agents" have actions causally chosen by a similar logic.vanhees71 said:Even in cosmology, all we can do is to observe local observables and then extrapolate to the "universe as a whole" assuming the cosmological principle, which is amazingly successful.
This direction of reasoning always seemed conceptually backwards to me. Set aside historical development, how can you start with an equation, and then ask what the dependent variable means? My take on this is to try to first understand in what way the state encodes the observers predictions of the future and how it's inferred. Then ask - what self evolution is implied, when you account for the dependence of some information. I think it's this depencence, that implies the evolution. This is why I interpret the "hamiltonian" as part of the initial information as well. Although it's not the way of standard formalism. In the standard formalism it's just put in there, or considered empirical requiring no explanation.WernerQH said:Right. Schrödinger's equation by itself is not enough; we need the Born rule to obtain measurable quantities from the wave function.
It doesn't. Born's rule is needed only when you think of the wave function as the linchpin of quantum theory, as an additional step (to obtain numbers that you can compare with experiment). But with a path integral over a complete time-path you can write down expressions for all measurable quantities directly. One obtains probabilities (rather than probability amplitudes) automatically. Born's rule is built-in, and there's no need to introduce "measurement" as a separate process that somehow disrupts unitary evolution. In my view QM/QFT is just a machinery for calculating correlation functions, and the closed time-path formalism doesn't need a derivation from a set of historical axioms. It works nicely.A. Neumaier said:How does Schwinger's action principle lead to Born's rule?
I'm sorry, but I can't see the advantage of the views you propose. (If I understand them at all.) No offence!Fra said:My take on this is to try to first understand in what way the state encodes the observers predictions of the future and how it's inferred.
No offence, my views are an extremal version of a sort of evolutionary information algorithmic qbism version. The supposed advantage I see, has todo with the quest of unification of forces. My view is that, if we disregard unification problems, and just wants to understand QM - as it is - then I am close to some minimalist statistical interpretation. Beacuse this interpretation makes perfect sense! but only as a limiting case of my general view. For the general case, modifcation of QM is required (this is my take on this).WernerQH said:I'm sorry, but I can't see the advantage of the views you propose. (If I understand them at all.) No offence!
This seems to me wishful thinking.WernerQH said:It doesn't. Born's rule is needed only when you think of the wave function as the linchpin of quantum theory, as an additional step (to obtain numbers that you can compare with experiment). But with a path integral over a complete time-path you can write down expressions for all measurable quantities directly. One obtains probabilities (rather than probability amplitudes) automatically. Born's rule is built-in, and there's no need to introduce "measurement" as a separate process that somehow disrupts unitary evolution. In my view QM/QFT is just a machinery for calculating correlation functions, and the closed time-path formalism doesn't need a derivation from a set of historical axioms. It works nicely.
There's more than one version of Schwinger's action principle. I had in mind the variant that he used in the paper in which he invented the closed time path formalism (J.Math.Phys. 2, 407):A. Neumaier said:For example, how does one obtain the probabilities that go into Bell experiments (i.e., the relation between the photon count statistics and the incident two_photon states) from the equations deduced from the Schwinger's action principle? Or those for a Stern-Gerlach experiment?
It has the Born rule sort of "built in", because probability amplitudes on the forward time branch are accompanied by their complex conjugates on the backward time branch.[...] a knowledge of the transformation function referring to a closed time path determines the expectation value of any desired physical quantity [...]
How in QFT do you get probabilities? I thought that the primary quantity that Feynman diagrams(for example) allow you to calculate is amplitudes.WernerQH said:It doesn't. Born's rule is needed only when you think of the wave function as the linchpin of quantum theory, as an additional step (to obtain numbers that you can compare with experiment). But with a path integral over a complete time-path you can write down expressions for all measurable quantities directly. One obtains probabilities (rather than probability amplitudes) automatically. Born's rule is built-in, and there's no need to introduce "measurement" as a separate process that somehow disrupts unitary evolution. In my view QM/QFT is just a machinery for calculating correlation functions, and the closed time-path formalism doesn't need a derivation from a set of historical axioms. It works nicely.
Of course it's easiest just to take the squared modulus of a scattering amplitude. Schwinger's closed time-path method is more complicated, because what it amounts to is computation of the product of the S-matrix with its time-reverse. For such cases where a single process is dominant it leads to the same result. But the closed time-path method also produces interference terms when more than one process is involved. It is especially useful for non-equilibrium systems.stevendaryl said:How in QFT do you get probabilities? I thought that the primary quantity that Feynman diagrams(for example) allow you to calculate is amplitudes.
WernerQH said:The probabilities that "go into Bell experiments" can of course be worked out using QED, as you surely are aware.
This only gives the recipes for calculating the probabilities, but not the statement that these are probabilities for detecting individual photons. Here Born's rule needs to be assumed. See, e.g., the discussion relating S-matrix entries to detection rates in Chapter 3 of Weinberg's QFT book, where he gives explicit details.WernerQH said:Of course it's easiest just to take the squared modulus of a scattering amplitude.
Of course Born's rule has to enter in one way or another. That's what I've been saying all along. Unitary evolution is not the whole story.A. Neumaier said:This only gives the recipes for calculating the probabilities, but not the statement that these are probabilities for detecting individual photons. Here Born's rule needs to be assumed.
WernerQH said:It doesn't. Born's rule is needed only when you think of the wave function as the linchpin of quantum theory, as an additional step (to obtain numbers that you can compare with experiment). But with a path integral over a complete time-path you can write down expressions for all measurable quantities directly. One obtains probabilities (rather than probability amplitudes) automatically. Born's rule is built-in,
You had claimed that Born's rule is built-in in his approach. I was just responding that Schwinger's approach does not eliminate the need for Born's rule (or something implying it) in addition to the formal mathematics. Thus it is not built-in but assumed in addition.WernerQH said:Of course Born's rule has to enter in one way or another. That's what I've been saying all along. Unitary evolution is not the whole story.
For me Schwinger's closed time-path "recipe" has more logical coherence than the usual prescription of (1) calculating the scattering amplitude (unitary dynamics), and then (2) taking the squared modulus (Born rule, "measurement"). You are not saying that Schwinger didn't know how to apply QED, are you?
That depends on what you accept as first principle(s). I'm inclined to accept the closed time-path formalism as "the" principle of quantum theory, and be happy about the marvelous agreement with experiments. Asking the question why that is so is like asking why the speed of light is the same in all reference frames.A. Neumaier said:The measurement problem - the quest to derive from first principles why the statistical expectations computed from measurement results (read from a large quantum system called detector) agree with the quantum expectations calculated from Schwinger's machinery (or its modern version given e.g., in the book by Calzetta and Hu) - remains unsolved.
The closed-time-path formulation (aka Schwinger-Keldysh formalism; when Keldysh was present, it has been better to call it only Keldysh formalism though) is just a method to calculate directly expectation values, taken with respect to a given statistical operator rather than transition amplitudes/S-matrix elements. The definition of expectation values in terms of the quantum-mechanical formalism, however, uses Born's rule to interpret the states, represented by statistical operators. So also with the closed-time-path action functional(s) you can't derive Born's rule but you use it to define the expectation values you calculate.WernerQH said:There's more than one version of Schwinger's action principle. I had in mind the variant that he used in the paper in which he invented the closed time path formalism (J.Math.Phys. 2, 407):
It has the Born rule sort of "built in", because probability amplitudes on the forward time branch are accompanied by their complex conjugates on the backward time branch.
The probabilities that "go into Bell experiments" can of course be worked out using QED, as you surely are aware. But perhaps you are viewing it from a wrong angle, if your focus is on how a photon wave function collapses to produce a definite measurement result.
Conincidently I ask this question as well, and I think a potential explanation is not unrelated to the probability question.WernerQH said:Asking the question why that is so is like asking why the speed of light is the same in all reference frames.
The CTP formalism does not say anything about measurement, it talks only about computing N-point functions. Why these N-point functions give expectation values of measurement results is not touched at all by this formalism.WernerQH said:That depends on what you accept as first principle(s). I'm inclined to accept the closed time-path formalism as "the" principle of quantum theory, and be happy about the marvelous agreement with experiments. Asking the question why that is so is like asking why the speed of light is the same in all reference frames.
What you see as a defect of the closed-time-path formalism I see as its biggest virtue. It avoids the discussion of "measurement" and its strange interplay with unitary evolution. It handles reversible (microscopic) and irreversible processes ("measurements", "detection events") on the same footing. One needs quantum theory to understand how the detectors in the Bell-type experiments work. I find it odd that you seek a secure foundation of a microscopic theory in a rigorous description of macroscopic devices. As John Bell has argued, there should be no place for the term "measurement" in the foundations of QM. It does sound silly to phrase the discussion of nuclear reactions in the interior of the sun (for example) in terms of "state preparation" and "measurement".A. Neumaier said:The CTP formalism does not say anything about measurement, it talks only about computing N-point functions. Why these N-point functions give expectation values of measurement results is not touched at all by this formalism.