Closures on Ordered Sets: Are the Endpoints Always Included?

  • Thread starter Thread starter radou
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Sets
radou
Homework Helper
Messages
3,148
Reaction score
8

Homework Statement



OK, this question may sound somewhat trivial, but I'd still like to check my answer. It's from Munkres.

Let X be an ordered set with the order topology. One needs to prove that Cl(<a, b>) is a subset of [a, b] and investigate the conditions necessary for equality.

The Attempt at a Solution



So, if x is any element in <a, b> it is obviously in [a, b], too. If it happens that either a or b (or both) are in Cl(<a, b>), they are in [a, b] too, so Cl(<a, b>) is a subset of [a, b].

Now, if x is any element of [a, b] different from a and b, obviously x is in <a, b>, too, which is a subset of Cl(<a, b>), and hence x is in Cl(<a, b>). Now, the interesting cases are a and b. Is a in Cl(<a, b>)? Well, if so, then every neighborhood of a intersects <a, b>. Let X be a finite ordered set. Is a is the least element of X, then every interval of the form [a, b> intersects <a, b>, and it's obviously the only type of neighborhood that contains a. But if a is not the least element of X, then <a1, a, a2> (where a1 < a and a2 is the first element such that a2 > a) is a neighborhood containing a which doesn't intersect <a, b>. So, a can't be in Cl(<a, b>) if X is finite, unless a is the least element of X. An analogous proof holds for b.

Now, if my reasoning above is correct, it's natural to ask the question: are a and/or b in Cl(<a, b>) if X is infinite? Clearly, motivated by the arguments above, one can reason that between every element which is the first one greater than a and a itself there should be another element, and so on, so we could chose an open neighborhood of a which intersects <a, b>. So X should be infinite. But does every infinite ordered set satisfy this condition?

I'm a bit confused on this one, thanks for any help.
 
Physics news on Phys.org
Oops, it just occurred to me that, if X has a smallest element a, {a} is a neighborhood of a which doesn't intersect <a, b> (since the smallest half-interval which contains a is {a}). So, actually, if X is finite, a and b can not belong to Cl(<a, b>). Still, my last question remains open.
 
The inclusion can be strict - consider the least uncountable well-ordered set.
 
Eynstone said:
The inclusion can be strict - consider the least uncountable well-ordered set.

Of course, if we consider N with the order topology, then every interval <a, b> contains at least one element. Clearly, if it contains one element, i.e. if it is of the form <n-1, n+1>, where n is a natural number greater than 2, then <n-2, n> and <n, n+2> are neighborhoods of n-2 and n+2 which contain n-1 and n+1, respectively, and don't intersect <n-1, n+1>. Hence, neither n-1 nor n+1 are contained in the clusure of <n-1, n+1>.

But still, the question about the other inclusion remains. Is there a general rule for an ordered set X so that [a, b] = Cl(<a, b>) for any a, b in X?
 
Here's an example where [a, b] is a subset of Cl(<a, b>): if <a, b> is a dense subset of X, then every open set in X intersects <a, b>. Hence, for every x in [a, b], and for any neighborhood Ux of x, Ux intersects <a, b>, so [a, b] is contained in Cl(<a, b>).
 
There are two things I don't understand about this problem. First, when finding the nth root of a number, there should in theory be n solutions. However, the formula produces n+1 roots. Here is how. The first root is simply ##\left(r\right)^{\left(\frac{1}{n}\right)}##. Then you multiply this first root by n additional expressions given by the formula, as you go through k=0,1,...n-1. So you end up with n+1 roots, which cannot be correct. Let me illustrate what I mean. For this...
Back
Top