kye said:
I read the lubus paper and understood it fully. Bottomline is. Docoherence is only interesting for Bohmian and Many Worlds. It is not important for Copenhagen because since collapse is not real in the objects. May as well just accept Collapse. Decoherence just makes it more complicated.
That really has me perplexed:
Measurement devices are classical
The fifth rule says that the measurement devices follow the rules of classical physics. This is another source of misunderstandings.
The Copenhagen school surely didn't want to say that quantum mechanics couldn't be applied to large systems. Indeed, many people from the Copenhagen school were key researchers who helped to show that quantum mechanics works for large systems including molecules, bubble chambers, solids, and anything else you can think of.
Instead, this rule was meant as a phenomenological rule. If you measure something, you may assume that the apparatus behaves as a classical object. So in particular, you may assume that these classical objects - especially your brain, but you don't have to go up to your brain - won't ever evolve into unnatural superpositions of macroscopically distinct states.
Is that true?
Is that a sign of a problem of the Copenhagen interpretation?
It is surely true. It's how the world works.
However, one may also say that this was a point in which the Copenhagen interpretation was incomplete. They didn't quite understand decoherence - or at least, Bohr who probably "morally" understood what was going on failed in his attempts to comprehensibly and quantitatively describe what he "knew".
However, once we understand decoherence, we should view it as an explicit proof of this fifth principle of the Copenhagen interpretation. Decoherence shows that the states of macroscopic (or otherwise classical-like) objects whose probabilities are well-defined are exactly those that we could identify with the "classical states" - they're eigenstates of the density matrix. The corresponding eigenvalues - diagonal entries of the density matrix in the right basis - are the predicted probabilities.
Because the calculus of decoherence wasn't fully developed in the 1920s, the Copenhagen school couldn't have exactly identified the point at which the classical logic becomes applicable for large enough objects. However, they were saying that there is such a boundary at which the quantum subtleties may be forgotten for certain purposes and they were damn right. There is such a (fuzzy) boundary and we may calculate it with the decoherence calculus today. The loss of the information about the relative phase of the probability amplitudes between several basis vectors is the only new "thing" that occurs near the boundary.
Again, this point was the only principle of the Copenhagen interpretation that was arguably "incomplete" but their proposition was definitely right! To make this point complete, one didn't have to add anything new to quantum mechanics or distort it in any way. One only needs to make the right calculation of the evolution of the density matrix in a complicated setup. In that way, one proves that they always treated the measuring devices in the right way even though they couldn't fully formulate a fully quantum proof why it was the right way.
End of quote
Decoherence is needed in Copenhagen to fix up the issue it had with dividing the world into classical and quantum.
Copenhagen was basically correct, and in the great scheme of things it was minor, but it was a problem, and it needed fixing.
IMHO modern interpretations like Decoherent Histories and my Ignorance Ensemble Interpretation that incorporate it from the outset are better. But that's just a matter of elegance and personal taste - its got nothing to do with its validity.
Thanks
Bill