How are moral assertions connected with the world of facts?

  • Thread starter Ivan Seeking
  • Start date
  • Tags
    Facts
In summary: I think the answer to this may be that it would be difficult to know what you were talking about if you had never experienced sadness. Sadness can be experienced in different ways, and might be a descriptor for a certain feeling, but it does not have a specific definition.
  • #1
Ivan Seeking
Staff Emeritus
Science Advisor
Gold Member
8,142
1,756
Unlike many ancient philosophical problems, this one has, paradoxically, been made both more urgent and less tractable by the gradual triumph of scientific rationality. Indeed, the prevailing modern attitude towards it is a sort of dogmatic despair: ‘you can‘t get an ought from an is, therefore morality must be outside the domain of reason‘. Having fallen for that non-sequitur, one has only two options: either to embrace unreason, or to try living without ever making a moral judgement. In either case, one becomes a menace to oneself and everyone else. [continued]
http://www.edge.org/q2002/q_deutsch.html
 
Physics news on Phys.org
  • #2
Did anyone ever actually demonstrate that one cannot get an ought from an is? Or did the phrase just sound good?
 
  • #3
>Unlike many ancient philosophical problems, this one has, paradoxically, been made both more urgent and less tractable by the gradual triumph of scientific rationality. Indeed, the prevailing modern attitude towards it is a sort of dogmatic despair: ‘you can‘t get an ought from an is, therefore morality must be outside the domain of reason‘. Having fallen for that non-sequitur, one has only two options: either to embrace unreason, or to try living without ever making a moral judgement. In either case, one becomes a menace to oneself and everyone else.

Morality has been made with the use of rationality and reason, how can it lie outside it? Morality has been under the guise of rational (& irrational) interpretation of actions. Morality does not exist on its own, we created it.

So there is no reason to say that rationality is to be abandoned because morality does not exist (ie. embrace unreason). But the idea of 'not making a moral judgement' does not mean that we are forced to embrace nihilism or anarchy.
 
Last edited:
  • #4
Canute said:
Did anyone ever actually demonstrate that one cannot get an ought from an is? Or did the phrase just sound good?

The phrase is a paraphrase of Hume's empiricist conclusions; you are free to read and refute him if you can.

Kant wrote his Critique of Pure Reason in part to refute Hume. Some think he succeeded, others not.

Hegel set out to refute Kant (not about ought and is). The subsequent history of Hegel's students and followers is, ummmm, lurid.

How would you get a morality out of empirical facts?
 
  • #5
selfAdjoint said:
How would you get a morality out of empirical facts?

I can't give an exact answer to you question, but I do think there are external indicators that can help establish "morals," depending on how we define morality. I've never been able to accept that doing harm to myself should be a moral issue. Even if it is, I don't see how it is a matter for public decisions, so it becomes irrelevant to most discussions of morality.

However, doing harm to others and the environment (i.e., what we all have to share) -- whether purposely, or from carelessness, or caused by selfish pursuits -- seems to me to be a good basis for morality.

If that is the standard for determining morality, then there is a lot of evidence to show that doing what benefits (or at least does no harm to) others and the environment helps to ensure our survival as a species. And of course, since survival is well accepted as biologically wired into us, there's the empirical basis for morality! :biggrin:

One of my favorite examples is how business management concepts changed as employers realized that treating employees like dirt hurt business. Unhappy employees work slower, uncreatively, and without commitment; they take more days off for sickness; they quit more; they steal and sabotage more. All of that costs the business both money and opportunities to make money. Figuring out and applying what helped employees thrive psychologically on the job benefitted everyone.

A couple of interesting things to me is that (still using the business example) some might say they are being selfish, and therefore immoral, by being good to their employees. But self interest is part of our make up too (from the survival imperative). So doing something for oneself per se can't be considered "selfish" (in the sense of not caring about others). Another interesting thing is that in that business, when managers attempt to apply beneficial management techniques selfishly (i.e., manipulatively, such as really only caring about making money), they seem to screw it up (that's been my experience anyway). In fact, all such "behaviorist" moralists seem to screw up, so it turns out sincerity seems to be required to moral.

Is sincerity more of a survival thing than we realize?
 
Last edited:
  • #6
There are facts which cannot be independently verified, but which are still facts. It is true that I can be sad, but how would you definitely know it? How would the term "sad" even make sense to you, other than with regards to behavior, if you had never been sad? How can you have any proof of the existence of feelings without relying on your own experiences?
 
  • #7
Les Sleeth said:
can't give an exact answer to you question, but I do think there are external indicators that can help establish "morals," depending on how we define morality. I've never been able to accept that doing harm to myself should be a moral issue. Even if it is, I don't see how it is a matter for public decisions, so it becomes irrelevant to most discussions of morality.

Your statement just about makes Hume's point, Les, since of course others describe suicide as a sin, and it's a felony in our legal system. Nobody has a system that works for everybody, and there are no universally accepted principles. Even the golden rule isn't considered valid everywhere.
 
  • #8
selfAdjoint said:
Your statement just about makes Hume's point, Les, since of course others describe suicide as a sin, and it's a felony in our legal system. Nobody has a system that works for everybody, and there are no universally accepted principles. Even the golden rule isn't considered valid everywhere.

Well, I thought we were trying to find an empirical basis for morality, not a consensual basis. :cool:
 
  • #9
How are moral assertions connected with the world of facts?

They are not, they are social / societal experiments accepted for time being.
 
  • #10
Building on my previous post, I would say that there are events that occur that have moral qualities ("goodness" and "badness"), and based on these value one can try to develop a system of action to minimize/maximize them. Of course, I can no further prove to you these moral qualities than I can demonstrate give you an equation that describes the smell of a flower.
 
  • #11
Microburst said:
They are not, they are social / societal experiments accepted for time being.

So you don't think I have a point that the idea "goodness" and "badness" have developed as part of the psychology of survival?

Look at the history of humankind as we shifted from hunter-gatherer nomadic life to community life. Why is stealing considered bad? It used to be good for a tribe to be strong enough to steal from Rome, but not for a tribe member to steal from another tribe member. The isolation a tribe felt from nonmembers people allowed them to believe they could escape negative consequences of stealing, and so it helped survival. But it was clear that if you couldn't trust fellow tribal members, then that hurt the functioning of the group and potentially threatened survival.

Over the centuries we've learned a lot about long term consequences, and also basic human psychological needs. W have learned, for example, (some of us anyway) that if a government is too oppressive it creates more problems than treating people fairly. In other words, we are learning that when people thrive psychologically, they are more likely to contribute to the general good, rather than damage it. As people gathered into larger and larger groups, the community aspect became more and more important, even between communities (e.g., where we used to believe in the "glory" of war, now it is the "evil" of war.)

If morality is ultimately determined by what helps us survive, then why are there still questions about it? Well, there are still lots of things we aren't sure if they help us survive or not. Should we put law breakers in prison, treat them like dogs, make them suffer, etc. Does that help us better survive? Or should we educate them, treat them humanely, etc. and see if that is better for survival (of the community). What about abortion? Save the baby, but what about the impact to society of having mothers either who can't or won't take care of the baby?

Even religious morals can be seen as trying to do what God wants in order to survive (go to heaven).

Now, I do think there is another avenue to the same thing. If morals is the "outward" behaviorist approach, then the "inner" approach is to be attentive to how things make one "feel." For me, it has turned out that kindness, love, compassion, honesty, understanding, being unselfish . . . all of it makes me happier than not being that way. I personally prefer to do what makes me feel good because it is easier than remembering a bunch of morals, and a lot more natural too. :smile:
 
  • #12
Les Sleeth said:
Now, I do think there is another avenue to the same thing. If morals is the "outward" behaviorist approach, then the "inner" approach is to be attentive to how things make one "feel." For me, it has turned out that kindness, love, compassion, honesty, understanding, being unselfish . . . all of it makes me happier than not being that way. I personally prefer to do what makes me feel good because it is easier than remembering a bunch of morals, and a lot more natural too. :smile:

I agree that while both those inner and outer behaviorist approach can be helpful...What happens when you feel better being mean, hateful, malevolent, dishonest, ignorant and selfish? ;)

Just as a little question/advice, what do you think of not 'relying' completely on how you feel and/or not 'relying' completely on "rational morals"? It doesn't mean that you should forget your feelings or just abandon rational thinking.
Basically, why not put thinking along with feeling and the senses in every decision whenever you can - according to the situation or the moment. Why not just forego universal or unchangeable principles and reactions. Adapt to the situation - if the situation changes around you, how come your actions do not?
 
Last edited:
  • #13
GeD said:
I agree that while both those inner and outer behaviorist approach can be helpful...What happens when you feel better being mean, hateful, malevolent, dishonest, ignorant and selfish? ;)

Just as a little question/advice, what do you think of not 'relying' completely on how you feel and/or not 'relying' completely on "rational morals"? It doesn't mean that you should forget your feelings or just abandon rational thinking.
Basically, why not put thinking along with feeling and the senses in every decision whenever you can - according to the situation or the moment. Why not just forego universal or unchangeable principles and reactions. Adapt to the situation - if the situation changes around you, how come your actions do not?

That sounds reasonable to me. I would say that the "feeling" side of it has taken me the major part of my life to recognize it to the degree I have. Conditioning can cloud sincere feeling and so, as you say, it might feel good to someone to harm another person.

The thing is, some things that feel good in the short term, do a number on one's psyche later and cumulatively. It might take a bit of living to discover what feels good from start to finish, and leaves one happier overall. In the meantime, I agree it is smart to study the situation or the moment and adapt.
 
  • #14
GeD said:
Just as a little question/advice, what do you think of not 'relying' completely on how you feel and/or not 'relying' completely on "rational morals"? It doesn't mean that you should forget your feelings or just abandon rational thinking.
Basically, why not put thinking along with feeling and the senses in every decision whenever you can - according to the situation or the moment. Why not just forego universal or unchangeable principles and reactions. Adapt to the situation - if the situation changes around you, how come your actions do not?

I think that your feelings are useful as a basis for knowledge, with respect to morals, because you learn of what pleasure and pain are. They do not directly tell you external facts, and even in the case of sensation, there are exceptions to correctness of the senses. However, based on knowledge of the existence of feelings, once can use reason to develop a system of ethics/morals.
 
  • #15
Pain in itself is bad. Pleasure in itself is good. This is unprovable, but I'm certain it's true.

The situation can get more complex when more than one person is involved... long term pain vs. short term... long term pleasure vs. short term... etc.

Would anyone challenge this assertion:
"A universe where all beings are happy, is better than a universe where all beings are miserable."
 
  • #16
Better than pleasure is health. Happy, ineffective morons are not as good people as unhappy, effective geniuses are.
 
  • #17
Dissident Dan said:
I think that your feelings are useful as a basis for knowledge, with respect to morals, because you learn of what pleasure and pain are. They do not directly tell you external facts, and even in the case of sensation, there are exceptions to correctness of the senses. However, based on knowledge of the existence of feelings, once can use reason to develop a system of ethics/morals.

The point is, not everyone feels the same phenomena, especially not in the same manner or intensity.

And of course, one can use reason to develop a system of ethics/morals based on the most common fit - we already have them. The problem is that ethical/moral phenomena do not exist. In relation to this, the definition of 'pain' as bad and 'pleasure' as good, is strictly something interpreted as good and bad in such a moral system. Unfortunately, it is only an interpretation, which even if useful, is neither universal nor free from subjective/relative grading.

It would better to simply adapt to the moment (or perhaps setting up a system that can be rapidly and easily changed to the situation), than to simply set up a rigid system of rules and values that is to be followed to the letter.
 
  • #18
It's not an interpretation. Pain and pleasure are moral phenomena. They have the qualities that they have regardless of how I would "interpret" them.
 
  • #19
Assuming that we don't need to prove the existence of moral phenomena, pain and pleasure are not moral phenomena - they're feelings that are a result of stimuli.

I agree with you that pain is pain, and pleasure is pleasure, but it does not tell us how strongly or weakly different people feel such pains and pleasures. There is simply no basis. Thus, if there were ever a moral system involving pain and pleasure, it would always be a relative grading system - a utilitarian faces this dilemma all the time (but instead with the levels of happiness). Your moral system does not become free of such effects simply because you choose to ignore it.
 
Last edited:
  • #20
GeD said:
I agree with you that pain is pain, and pleasure is pleasure, but it does not tell us how strongly or weakly different people feel such pains and pleasures. There is simply no basis.

Obviously, one cannot be completely sure of what others are feeling, but I wouldn't go so far as to say that there is no basis. As structurally and behaviorally similar creatures, we can often make rather accurate inferences.

Thus, if there were ever a moral system involving pain and pleasure, it would always be a relative grading system - a utilitarian faces this dilemma all the time (but instead with the levels of happiness). Your moral system does not become free of such effects simply because you choose to ignore it.

Who says that it has to?
 
  • #21
GeD said:
Assuming that we don't need to prove the existence of moral phenomena, pain and pleasure are not moral phenomena - they're feelings that are a result of stimuli.

I agree with you that pain is pain, and pleasure is pleasure, but it does not tell us how strongly or weakly different people feel such pains and pleasures. There is simply no basis. Thus, if there were ever a moral system involving pain and pleasure, it would always be a relative grading system - a utilitarian faces this dilemma all the time (but instead with the levels of happiness). Your moral system does not become free of such effects simply because you choose to ignore it.

The objections to utilitarianism (and hedonism) are matters of practicality... how to figure out when one is pain/pleasure... how to treat them... do we treat everyone the same etc... But the basic premise: the goodness of pleasure, and the badness of pain (in themselves). Can this be disputed?

Would you admit that with the existence of pain or pleasure or happiness or suffering, there would be no morality period? In the most fundamental way, pain and pleasure form the basis of morality.
 
  • #22
learningphysics said:
But the basic premise: the goodness of pleasure, and the badness of pain (in themselves). Can this be disputed?
The euphoria of the drug addict.

The "no pain, no gain" attitude of the excerciser.

And notice that long term drug addiction is very bad for you, while doctors say that vigorous excecise, id not overdone is beneficial.
 
Last edited:
  • #23
selfAdjoint said:
The euphoria of the drug addict.

The "no pain, no gain" attitude of the excerciser.

And notice that long term drug addiction is very bad for you, while doctors say that vigorous excecise, id not overdone is beneficial.
But in the end the drug addict gets less pleasure than if not doing drugs. And in the end the excerciser get more pleasure than if not doing the training.
 
  • #24
Aquamarine said:
But in the end the drug addict gets less pleasure than if not doing drugs. And in the end the excerciser get more pleasure than if not doing the training.

Exactly. The reason exerciser does the exercise is to increase long-term pleasure.
 
  • #25
This might seem a little simplistic, but I think that learningphysics' statement 'pain is bad, pleasure is good' can indeed be used to form the basis of a moral code. If pain is unpleasant, then to inflict it upon another is bad. Inflicting pain and inducing pleasure are real world events. If pleasure is good, then to induce it in another is good. You can pick holes in this with the good old 'one man's meat is another man's poison', but leaving such crudities aside, wouldn't this work quite well? It seems to me to form the basis of most moral positions that omit religion, and even of some religions. It also accommodates Kant rather nicely.
 
  • #26
But Kate, does it accommodate the definition "A sadist is someone who is nice to a masochist"?
 
  • #27
katelynndevere said:
This might seem a little simplistic, but I think that learningphysics' statement 'pain is bad, pleasure is good' can indeed be used to form the basis of a moral code.

Didn't Ayn Rand do exactly that?
 
  • #28
sid_galt said:
Didn't Ayn Rand do exactly that?

I thought it was: "Greed is good."
 
  • #29
Dissident Dan said:
I thought it was: "Greed is good."

This was a quote of hers I found
I am not primarily an advocate of capitalism,” she wrote in 1971, “but of egoism; and I am not primarily an advocate of egoism, but of reason. If one recognizes the supremacy of reason and applies it consistently, all the rest follows.

Based on this, I don't think her slogan was "Greed is good".

From what I know of her philosophy, it is something like this -
Man has two choices - to live or to die. If he chooses to live, then he must do everything to promote his life i.e. he must be rationally selfish. If he chooses to die, then morality does not apply to him as according to her morality is an act of gaining a value, not destroying it.

But then I am not a spokesman for her. What I said might be wrong so just take it with a grain of salt.
 
  • #30
selfAdjoint said:
But Kate, does it accommodate the definition "A sadist is someone who is nice to a masochist"?

Yes:

(1) Assuming your definition to be correct, the sadist inflicts pain in order to induce pleasure, making pleasure the overriding principle in the exchange, and thereby a 'good' action.

(2) As I understand it, a sadist is not someone who is nice to masochists, rather it is someone who derives pleasure from inflicting pain and or mental anguish in others. A true sadist is unlikely to derive a great deal of satisfaction from indulging the desires of a masochist. Under this definition, a sadistic action would be a 'bad' action.

Life might not be whole lot of fun for a sadist who respects the wishes of others, but there will always be deviants from any collective norm; this does not necessarily undermine the authority of the norm.
 
  • #31
Life might not be whole lot of fun for a sadist who respects the wishes of others, but there will always be deviants from any collective norm; this does not necessarily undermine the authority of the norm.


Of course. But some do not want to obey the "authority" of the collective norm.

Thus, the "deviants" will be punished - not because the collective norm is metaphysically "true" - but because the collective norm has more power than those "deviants" that oppose them.
 
Last edited:
  • #32
katelynndevere said:
Yes:

(1) Assuming your definition to be correct, the sadist inflicts pain in order to induce pleasure, making pleasure the overriding principle in the exchange, and thereby a 'good' action.

(2) As I understand it, a sadist is not someone who is nice to masochists, rather it is someone who derives pleasure from inflicting pain and or mental anguish in others. A true sadist is unlikely to derive a great deal of satisfaction from indulging the desires of a masochist. Under this definition, a sadistic action would be a 'bad' action.

I agree with the above.

A more interesting type of masochist (a fictional type, but more relevant to this topic) is one that derives 0 pleasure from painful acts, but still inflicts pain upon himself. He gets no satisfaction out of it. Let us also suppose that nobody benefits from his painful acts on himself. Also, let's assume that this masochist is not ignorant. He fully knows that he will derive 0 pleasure, and nobody benefits.

Can such a type of masochist exist? Is there any possible reason for such a person to exert pain on himself? What would such a reason be?
 
  • #33
GeD said:
Of course. But some do not want to obey the "authority" of the collective norm.

Thus, the "deviants" will be punished - not because the collective norm is metaphysically "true" - but because the collective norm has more power than those "deviants" that oppose them.

I'm not at all sure what you mean by 'metaphysically true'; could you explain, please?

Deviants are not necessarily punished. In fact, many forms of deviance are tolerated and accepted by, and eventually incorporated into the mainstream. We didn't execute punk-rockers for having green hair and safety pins through their noses, after all.

However, you're right about the power of the majority. Isn't all morality (where morality polarises 'good' and 'bad') determined by majority consensus? Could there be any other kind? Even rational anarchy presupposes a collective agreement about rationalism. In fact, it is possible to make a very good case for all of physical reality as we know it being the result of a consensus of opinion.

I think you may have misunderstood what I mean by authority; I'm not talking about jack-booted troopers enforcing comformity and punishing deviants. I'm only referring to the legitimacy of the concept of 'right' agreed upon by members of a group. If nine out of ten people in a club agree on a particular mode of behaviour, that becomes the norm for the group, even if one out of ten dissents. The dissension or deviance of the one does not diminish the legitimacy of the norm. That is not to say that the one must necessarily be wrong, just because they are different.

A moral assertion however, does allow for the statement that the deviant is 'wrong'. Morals are like 'norms-plus', in that they are required or strongly preferred norms. They are usually the product of group consensus, to the extent that they tend to be rejected or changed when sufficient members of a group reject them: that's why women now have the vote, and overt segregation is a thing of the past in the USA. There is nothing inherently sinister about the consensual, collective nature of morals, or the concept of deviance from a collective norm. It is because more people agree than disagree, that murder and rape are considered 'bad' and subject to harsh punishments. This is a collective norm which has become 'required' to the point where deviance is punishable, and rightly so.
 
  • #34
katelynndevere said:
I'm not at all sure what you mean by 'metaphysically true'; could you explain, please?
That means that the collective norm is not actually "right", it's just that they have the power to enforce their beliefs.


However, you're right about the power of the majority. Isn't all morality (where morality polarises 'good' and 'bad') determined by majority consensus? Could there be any other kind? Even rational anarchy presupposes a collective agreement about rationalism. In fact, it is possible to make a very good case for all of physical reality as we know it being the result of a consensus of opinion.
Yes, morality is for the greater number. And thus, morality supports the weak - it must level everyone's power, or the stronger will take over. The wrong in morality are thus the deviants - whoever is stronger or different from the standard of the majority.

It is because more people agree than disagree, that murder and rape are considered 'bad' and subject to harsh punishments. This is a collective norm which has become 'required' to the point where deviance is punishable, and rightly so.
Yet this authority to punish does not actually exist - it does not tell us that they are "correct" (metaphysically true). It is only a sign that the enforcers of the morality have greater power. Morality is that consolidated belief structure of the overall group, that focuses the peoples' combined strength into enforcing those beliefs. The degree of truth a morality promises is just dependent on the group's beliefs, not any "actual truth" - I think we agree with that one.
 
Last edited:

What is the relationship between moral assertions and facts?

The relationship between moral assertions and facts is complex and often debated. Some argue that moral assertions are based on objective facts, while others believe that they are subjective and based on personal beliefs and values. Ultimately, the connection between moral assertions and facts depends on one's philosophical perspective.

Can moral assertions be proven with facts?

It is difficult to prove moral assertions with facts because moral values and beliefs are often subjective and cannot be objectively measured or proven. However, some argue that certain moral assertions can be supported by empirical evidence or logical reasoning.

Do moral assertions have any basis in reality?

This is a highly debated question. Some argue that moral assertions are based on objective facts and therefore have a basis in reality. Others believe that moral assertions are purely subjective and do not correspond to any objective reality. Ultimately, the answer to this question depends on one's philosophical perspective.

How do moral assertions impact our understanding of the world?

Moral assertions can play a significant role in shaping our understanding of the world. They can influence our beliefs, values, and actions, and can also impact how we perceive and interpret facts. Additionally, moral assertions can contribute to the development of societal norms and values.

Is there a universal connection between moral assertions and facts?

This is a highly debated question and there is no clear consensus. Some argue that there is a universal connection between moral assertions and facts, while others believe that this connection is subjective and varies depending on cultural and societal beliefs. Ultimately, the answer to this question may depend on one's philosophical perspective.

Similar threads

  • General Discussion
2
Replies
50
Views
8K
  • General Discussion
Replies
2
Views
5K
  • General Discussion
Replies
9
Views
3K
Back
Top