Proof of Identity Theorem: Understanding G is Non-Empty

  • Thread starter Thread starter disregardthat
  • Start date Start date
  • Tags Tags
    Identity Theorem
disregardthat
Science Advisor
Messages
1,864
Reaction score
34
I'm slightly confused at the proof of this theorem, hopefully someone can help.

Identity theorem: Suppose X and Y are Riemann surfaces, and f_1,f_2:X \to Y are holomorphic mappings which coincide on a set A \subseteq X having a limit point a \in X. Then f_1 and f_2 are identically equal.

The proof starts out with: Let G be the set of all points x \in X having an open neighbourhood W such that f_1|_W = f_2|_W.

Now, it seems like they assume without argument that G is non-empty. Why is G non-empty?

Also, maybe I'm just confused about this, what does it mean that A has a limit point a in X? As I understand it, a is simply a point which cannot be separated from A by two open sets. Couldn't it be the case that A is a one-point set, doesn't every set have a limit point? In that case I don't see how G could be non-empty.

EDIT: Ok, upon some thought I think I recall that a limit point a \in X of A is a point which cannot be separated from A / \{a\}. Is this right? In that case A must be infinite. Still, this doesn't resolve the question of the existence of such a W as described above.
 
Last edited:
Physics news on Phys.org
disregardthat said:
I'm slightly confused at the proof of this theorem, hopefully someone can help.

Identity theorem: Suppose X and Y are Riemann surfaces, and f_1,f_2:X \to Y are holomorphic mappings which coincide on a set A \subseteq X having a limit point a \in X. Then f_1 and f_2 are identically equal.

The proof starts out with: Let G be the set of all points x \in X having an open neighbourhood W such that f_1|_W = f_2|_W.

Now, it seems like they assume without argument that G is non-empty. Why is G non-empty?

So far I don't see them assuming that ##G## is non-empty. Can you give the entire proof here (or at least the next few steps) so that I can check.

Also, maybe I'm just confused about this, what does it mean that A has a limit point a in X? As I understand it, a is simply a point which cannot be separated from A by two open sets. Couldn't it be the case that A is a one-point set, doesn't every set have a limit point? In that case I don't see how G could be non-empty.

EDIT: Ok, upon some thought I think I recall that a limit point a \in X of A is a point which cannot be separated from A / \{a\}. Is this right? In that case A must be infinite. Still, this doesn't resolve the question of the existence of such a W as described above.

A limit point of ##A## is a point ##a## such that for each neighborhood ##V## of ##a## holds that ##V\cap (A\setminus\{a\})## is nonempty. So ##A## can't be a one-point set in particular. Since your space is ##T_1## (all singletons are closed), you can indeed deduce that ##A## is infinite.
 
Continuation of proof:

By definition G is open. We claim that G is also closed. For, suppose b is a boundary point of G. Then f_1(b)=f_2(b) since f_1 and f_2 are continuous. Choose charts \phi : U \to V and \psi : U' \to V' on Y with b \in U and f_i(U) \subseteq U'. We may also assume that U is connected. The mappings

g_i = \psi \circ f_i \circ \phi^{-1} : V \to V' \subseteq \mathbb{C}

are holomorphic. Since U \cap G \not = \emptyset, the Identity theorem for holomorphic functions on domains in \mathbb{C} implies that g_1 and g_2 are identically equal. Thus f_1|_U = f_2|_U. Hence b \in G and thus G is closed. Now since X is connected either G = \emptyset or G = X. But the first case is excluded since a \in G (using the identity theorem in the plane again). Hence f_1 and f_2 coincide on all of X.
 
So basically,
why is U \cap G \not = \emptyset, and why is a \in G by using the identity theorem in the plane?

U \cap G \not = \emptyset is actually fine since we have already assumed b \in G. But I don't see why such a b must exist. It does exist if G is non-empty.

So it boils down that the fact that a \in G.

EDIT: Just a note: b \in G is wrong at this stage of the argument, but b being a boundary point of G implies that U \cap G \not = \emptyset anyway.
 
Last edited:
In ##C##, you could apply the following argument:
Let ##f## be zero on a set ##A## with a limit point ##a##.Then there is a sequence ##a_n\rightarrow a## such that ##a_n\in A##. By continuity, we have ##0=f(a_n)\rightarrow f(a)##. Thus ##a\in A##.
Thus (in a neighborhood of ##a##):

f(x) = \sum_{n=1}^{+\infty}\alpha_n (x-a)^n = (x-a) g(x)

where ##g## is a holomorphic function. Clearly, ##g(a_n) = 0##. Thus by the same argument, ##g(a) = 0##. By induction we can show that ##\alpha_n = 0## for each ##\alpha_n##.

In a standard way, you can lift this result to the Riemann surface to prove that if ##f## and ##g## coincide on a set ##A## with limit point ##a##, then ##f## and ##g## coincide on a neighborhood of ##a##.
 
Thanks, this does resolve the issue. (I don't think that it follows that a \in A by the way, but it doesn't affect your argument)
 
disregardthat said:
So basically,
why is U \cap G \not = \emptyset, and why is a \in G by using the identity theorem in the plane?

U \cap G \not = \emptyset is actually fine since we have already assumed b \in G. But I don't see why such a b must exist. It does exist if G is non-empty.

So it boils down that the fact that a \in G.

Yeah, so consider the maps ##g_1## and ##g_2##. Since ##\varphi## are homeomorphisms, we have that ##\varphi(a)## is a limit point of ##\varphi(A)##. Furthermore, it is easy to check that ##g_1## and ##g_2## coincide on ##\varphi(A)##. Thus by the identity theorem in the plane (or the proof I gave in my last post), we can deduce that there is a neighborhood ##W## of ##\varphi(a)## such that ##g_1\vert_W = g_2\vert_W##. Then you can easily check that ##f_1 = f_2## on ##\varphi^{-1}(W)## and that ##a\in \varphi^{-1}(W)##. Thus ##a\in G##.
 
disregardthat said:
(I don't think that it follows that a \in A by the way, but it doesn't affect your argument)

Oh right. I was mentally taking ##A## to be the set of all points where ##f_1## and ##f_2## coincide. But that wasn't given. Sorry.
 
  • Like
Likes 1 person
a key point, not given in the statement, is the connectivity of X. Other than that, the proof of non emptiness of G rests on the principle of "isolated zeroes" for non trivial holomorphic functions. I.e. a non trivial powers series, looks like z^k.g(z) where g(0) ≠ 0. Hence there is an isolated zero at z=0. By taking local coordinates near a limit point a, and subtracting f1 from f2, one sees that f1 = f2 on a nbhd of a. This is why the set G is non empty. They presumably took it for granted that this fact from one vbl complex analysis was known.
 
  • #10
That's right, a riemann surface is defined in my book to be connected.
 
Back
Top